Constructive Empiricism Without the Epistemic Community

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Constructive Empiricism Without the Epistemic Community Online ISSN 2424-6158. PROBLEMOS 2017 91 DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.15388/Problemos.2017.91.10498 Constructive EMPIRICISM WITHOUT THE EPISTEMIC COMMUNITY Justas Bujokas Vilnius University Department of Logic and History of Philosophy Universiteto str. 3, LT-01513 Vilnius, Lithuania E-mail: [email protected] Abstract. Constructive empiricism (CE), a widely debated anti-realist philosophy of science by Bas van Fraassen, offers a philosophical interpretation of scientific practice. The agent of the scientific practice, according to CE, is what Bas van Fraassen himself calls the “epistemic community”. However, William Seager argued that by appealing to the epistemic community constructive empiricists warrant scientists’ belief in unobservables. Moreover, Simone Bahrenberg et al. maintained that if what is observable is defined in terms of whom a particular epistemic community consists of, then observability cannot be an objective property, while CE needs observability to be objective. In this paper, based on four thought experiments, I consider a special hypothetical case of the epis- temic community consisting of only one person and notice that in this hypothetical case the objections by Seager and Bahrenberg et al. dissolve: Seager’s requirement to treat the reports of other members of epistemic community as an evidence for the epistemic belief collapses; and, contra Bahrenberg et al., ob- servability for a single person is unproblematically objective in CE. Based on this observation I argue that constructive empiricists would be better off reformulating their main thesis in terms of a single cognitive agent (person, scientist), because (i) this would not only allow CE to render all the objections appealing to the concept of epistemic community ineffectual once and for all, but also (ii) using the proposed mo- dification constructive empiricists could straightforwardly account for some cases of possible scientific practice, for which their original thesis cannot account in an obvious manner. The above change in the policy of CE (iii) would still allow to retain the key features of the empiricist position—the observable/ unobservable distinction, the distinction between acceptance and belief, the principles of epistemic mo- desty and the principle of scientific rationality—at least on an equal footing to the original thesis by van Fraassen. Keywords: constructive empiricism, epistemic community, observability, objectivity Constructive empiricism (CE) is probably agent of the scientific practice is: according one of the most debated antirealist concep- to CE, looking at our science, it is obviously tions of science. The main idea of CE, as our “epistemic community” or just us as a expressed by Bas van Fraassen in his semi- group of scientists. One of the many issues nal work Scientific Image (1980a), is that surrounding CE, as an influential empiricist science seeks not true but rather empirically alternative to the realist approach to science, adequate theories. is the question whether CE correctly bases Van Fraassen is straightforward in an- its philosophy on the concept of epistemic swering the question of who or what the community. 17 Besides the general puzzlement about temic belief seems unavailing. Also, contra how we can ascribe the epistemic belief Bahrenberg et al., in the case of a single to a society of scientists without getting person the observability (for that person) into sociological debates (Rosen 1994, van is unproblematically objective in CE, be- Fraassen 1994, Mizrahi 2014), and despite cause what a single person observes is just van Fraassen’s effort to define the epis- a function of how she as a sort of measuring temic community, to describe its change, apparatus interacts with the outside world, and to draw its boundaries (van Fraassen and not a function of the problematic moral 1980a, 2006), there are at least two direct and ideological criteria. arguments against the attempt to treat the Based on the above I, furthermore, sug- “epistemic community” as a basis for the gest that constructive empiricists would be CE view on science. better off reformulating their main thesis in William Seager (1988) argued that by terms of a single cognitive agent (person, appealing to the epistemic community CE scientist, or anyone capable of acting and warrants scientists’ belief in unobservables, creating what we would consider to be the because if the epistemic community is re- features of science as an epistemic activity) ally “epistemic”, ideally every member of instead of the whole epistemic community. it should believe what every other member First of all, this would allow CE to rebuke believes, even though in principle the per- all the objections appealing to the concept ceptual capabilities of different members of epistemic community, because if CE of the same epistemic community can be interpreted the essentially epistemic nature different to the extreme. of the endeavour of knowing the observ- Bahrenberg et al. (2006) maintained able phenomena without the concept of that if what is observable is defined in epistemic community (the community be- terms of whom particular epistemic com- ing epistemically contingent or pragmatic munity consists of, which in turn depends feature of science), there just would be noth- on non-scientific criteria like moral choice, ing to attack. Secondly, using the proposed ideology, etc., then observability cannot modification CE can straightforwardly ac- be an objective property, while CE claims count for some cases of possible scientific observability to be objective. practice (for example, for those described In this paper using four thought experi- in this paper), for which its original thesis ments I consider a special hypothetical case cannot account in an obvious manner. of the epistemic community consisting of Third, I will argue that the proposed only one person (human or non-human). change in the policy of CE still allows One can immediately notice that in this constructive empiricists to retain the key hypothetical case the objections raised by features of their philosophy and to hold CE Seager and Bahrenberg et al. simply do not ground in other well known CE debates, work. If we agree that a single person can at least as well as using the original CE conduct epistemically full-fledged scientific thesis. Here I take the most salient features activity, Seager’s requirement to treat the of the CE philosophy to be the observable/ reports of other members of the epistemic unobservable distinction, the distinction community as an evidence for the epis- between the pragmatic acceptance and the 18 epistemic belief, the principle of epistemic sidering the life of Jane Doe for a while they (or “ontological”) modesty and the commit- describe what Jane Doe is doing, or rather ment to make sense of science as a practical what the purpose of Jane Doe’s activity is, rational activity. in the usual manner as per famous thesis (let’s call it OCE - the original CE) by Bas A Lonely Scientist van Fraassen: Thought Experiment Science aims to give us theories which are Imagine a post-apocalyptic world in which empirically adequate; and acceptance of a all human-beings had been wiped out from theory involves as a belief only that it is em- the face of Earth with the exception of a pirically adequate. (van Fraassen 1980a: 12) single person, Jane Doe, a capable yet evil Note that, if constructive empiricists nuclear physicist, who happened to know are able to interpret science in terms of about the upcoming global disaster (not that the above thesis in the case of scientific she had anything to do with it) but failed to community which consists of millions of inform about it her beloved ones1 (not that people, they should be able to do so in she had many), let alone anyone else in the the case of single Jane Doe as well. After doomed world. all, Jane’s science is not so much differ- There is not much to do in an empty ent from the science as we know it. The planet, so Jane Doe continues doing what former is just slower and less diverse, but she likes and knows best, namely, science. constructive empiricists would be reluctant As World Wide Web is still working, she has to admit that their thesis is about financial access to all the automated experimental fa- and human resources in science rather than cilities, including the Large Hadron Collider an interpretation of the most salient (if not (LHE), gravitational-waves observatories, essential) features of the epistemic activ- neutrino detectors, plethora of space and ity they happen to admire so much (van ground telescopes, etc. Also, she possesses Fraassen 1994: 191). superior mathematical skills to construct Moreover, when describing Jane Doe’s new theories and to test them using the activity, constructive empiricists have aforementioned scientific instrumentation. no business in trying to define epistemic Jane Doe’s scientific activity might last not community and draw its boundaries as van for too long, as the scientific infrastructure Fraassen himself had taken pains to on at is subject to wear and tear. This, however, least a couple of occasions (van Fraassen need not to be of big concern for the phi- 1980a: 18; 2006: 128-130). After all, in losophers of science who might decide to this case the epistemic community is just describe (or to interpret) Jane Doe’s scien- the lucky Jane Doe. Unsurprisingly, some tific practice at that particular period in the critical arguments against CE, appealing to human history. the concept of epistemic community, just Now suppose typical constructive em- dissolve in the case of Jane Doe, because piricists decide to do just that and after con- in this case an epistemic community or a 1 Some say she was the little sister of Mary, the set of scientists is just equivalent to a single color scientist (see Jackson 1982).
Recommended publications
  • In Defence of Constructive Empiricism: Metaphysics Versus Science
    To appear in Journal for General Philosophy of Science (2004) In Defence of Constructive Empiricism: Metaphysics versus Science F.A. Muller Institute for the History and Philosophy of Science and Mathematics Utrecht University, P.O. Box 80.000 3508 TA Utrecht, The Netherlands E-mail: [email protected] August 2003 Summary Over the past years, in books and journals (this journal included), N. Maxwell launched a ferocious attack on B.C. van Fraassen's view of science called Con- structive Empiricism (CE). This attack has been totally ignored. Must we con- clude from this silence that no defence is possible against the attack and that a fortiori Maxwell has buried CE once and for all, or is the attack too obviously flawed as not to merit exposure? We believe that neither is the case and hope that a careful dissection of Maxwell's reasoning will make this clear. This dis- section includes an analysis of Maxwell's `aberrance-argument' (omnipresent in his many writings) for the contentious claim that science implicitly and per- manently accepts a substantial, metaphysical thesis about the universe. This claim generally has been ignored too, for more than a quarter of a century. Our con- clusions will be that, first, Maxwell's attacks on CE can be beaten off; secondly, his `aberrance-arguments' do not establish what Maxwell believes they estab- lish; but, thirdly, we can draw a number of valuable lessons from these attacks about the nature of science and of the libertarian nature of CE. Table of Contents on other side −! Contents 1 Exordium: What is Maxwell's Argument? 1 2 Does Science Implicitly Accept Metaphysics? 3 2.1 Aberrant Theories .
    [Show full text]
  • Curriculum Vitae
    BAS C. VAN FRAASSEN Curriculum Vitae Last updated 3/6/2019 I. Personal and Academic History .................................................................................................................... 1 List of Degrees Earned ........................................................................................................................................................ 1 Title of Ph.D. Thesis ........................................................................................................................................................... 1 Positions held ..................................................................................................................................................................... 1 Invited lectures and lecture series ........................................................................................................................................ 1 List of Honors, Prizes ......................................................................................................................................................... 4 Research Grants .................................................................................................................................................................. 4 Non-Academic Publications ................................................................................................................................................ 5 II. Professional Activities .................................................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophical Analysis on the Nature and Forms of Information—From the Perspective of Marxist Philosophy †
    Proceedings Philosophical Analysis on the Nature and Forms of Information—From the Perspective of Marxist Philosophy † Mingfang Feng 1 and Liang Feng 2,* 1 School of Economics & Law, Shaanxi University of Technology, No.1, First Eastern Ring Road, Hanzhong 723001, China; [email protected] 2 School of Marxism Studies, Xi’an Jiaotong University, No.28 Xianning West Road, Xi’an 710049, China * Correspondence: [email protected] † Presented at the IS4SI 2017 Summit DIGITALISATION FOR A SUSTAINABLE SOCIETY, Gothenburg, Sweden, 12–16 June 2017. Published: 8 June 2017 Abstract: The aim of this research essay attempt to reveal the nature of information form the perspective of Marxist Philosophy. The nature of Information is the first question that philosophy of information science and technology research must be answered, thus the problem is still debated. According to Marxist dialectical materialism method to the essence of information has made the analysis and argumentation, points out the essence of information between what is and its internal contact things, and this contact information is presented. Due to the connection between the protean and endless things, thus produce the endless, full of beautiful things in eyes, each are not identical information. To grasp the nature of information, must pay attention to and the specific form of information and information processing, the reorganization, transmission, storage, use and so on. Keywords: information; nature; connection; philosophy of information 1. Introduction The development of information science and technology has spar ked the nature of information exploration after World War II. The question that ‘What is the nature of information?’ is always unable to avoid in information science and philosophical technology research.
    [Show full text]
  • The Tyranny of Method: a Pragmatic Defense of Philosophical Pluralism
    THE TYRANNY OF METHOD: A PRAGMATIC DEFENSE OF PHILOSOPHICAL PLURALISM Vincent M. Colapietro Abstract: The history of philosophy is in no small measure a series of attempts to institute a fail-safe method. In response to what they take to be the scandal of disagreement (disagreement itself being judged as scandalous), a number of historically influential philosophers (e.g., Descartes, Peirce, Husserl, and Carnap) have time and again tried to craft a method for guaranteeing agreement. In light of the failure of these attempts, this tendency might be seen as remotely analogous to what is called in psychoanalytic parlance a “repetition compulsion.” In any event, historical reflections on this repeated tendency promise to be illuminating. But there is a polemical purpose animating these historical reflections. The author tries, in light of these reflections, to render plausible the suggestion that this tendency amounts to a tyranny of method and, in turn, such tyranny results in an inevitable impoverishment of philosophical thought. THE TOPIC of my essay is best brought into focus by recalling a central figure in the history of Western philosophy. 1 This recollection is, however, far from methodologically innocent. My deliberate turn toward a pivotal moment in our intellectual history – in brief, my turn toward history – will provide the basis for my critique of what I am disposed to identify as the tyranny of method. This tyranny is not so much exercised by any particular method as by the repeated impulse to institute a philosophical method of allegedly revolutionary significance. Most often, this impulse is bound up with the hope that philosophy can transform itself into a science (an unquestionable form of certain knowledge) either by adopting the method of science itself (e.g., the efforts of C.
    [Show full text]
  • Plato's Symposium: the Ethics of Desire
    Plato’s Symposium: The Ethics of Desire FRISBEE C. C. SHEFFIELD 1 Contents Introduction 1 1. Ero¯s and the Good Life 8 2. Socrates’ Speech: The Nature of Ero¯s 40 3. Socrates’ Speech: The Aim of Ero¯s 75 4. Socrates’ Speech: The Activity of Ero¯s 112 5. Socrates’ Speech: Concern for Others? 154 6. ‘Nothing to do with Human AVairs?’: Alcibiades’ Response to Socrates 183 7. Shadow Lovers: The Symposiasts and Socrates 207 Conclusion 225 Appendix : Socratic Psychology or Tripartition in the Symposium? 227 References 240 Index 249 Introduction In the Symposium Plato invites us to imagine the following scene: A pair of lovers are locked in an embrace and Hephaestus stands over them with his mending tools asking: ‘What is it that you human beings really want from each other?’ The lovers are puzzled, and he asks them again: ‘Is this your heart’s desire, for the two of you to become parts of the same whole, and never to separate, day or night? If that is your desire, I’d like to weld you together and join you into something whole, so that the two of you are made into one. Look at your love and see if this is what you desire: wouldn’t this be all that you want?’ No one, apparently, would think that mere sex is the reason each lover takes such deep joy in being with the other. The soul of each lover apparently longs for something else, but cannot say what it is. The beloved holds out the promise of something beyond itself, but that something lovers are unable to name.1 Hephaestus’ question is a pressing one.
    [Show full text]
  • What Is a Philosophical Analysis?
    JEFFREY C. KING WHAT IS A PHILOSOPHICAL ANALYSIS? (Received 24 January 1996) It is common for philosophers to offer philosophical accounts or analyses, as they are sometimes called, of knowledge, autonomy, representation, (moral) goodness, reference, and even modesty.1 These philosophical analyses raise deep questions. What is it that is being analyzed (i.e. what sorts of things are the objects of analysis)? What sort of thing is the analysis itself (a proposition? sentence?)? Under what conditions is an analysis correct? How can a correct analysis be informative? How, if at all, does the production of philo- sophical analyses differ from what scientists do? The purpose of the present paper is to provide answers to these questions. The traditional answers to the ®rst and last of these questions are that concepts are the objects of philosophical analysis and that philo- sophical analyses differ from the results of scienti®c investigation in being conceptual analyses. Like many philosophers I am suspicious of the notions of concept and conceptual analysis as traditionally understood. Though the critique of these notions is beyond the scope of the present work, the answers I shall give to the questions raised above shall not invoke concepts (understood as things distinct from properties).2 I count it as a virtue of my account that it is able to provide answers to the questions raised above without an appeal to concepts. And to the extent that it has been felt that concepts are needed to answer these questions, the present account weakens the case for positing concepts. Before addressing these questions, however, we shall make the simplifying assumption that analyses are given in a ªcanonical formº.
    [Show full text]
  • The Theory of Descriptions 1. Bertrand Russell (1872-1970): Mathematician, Logician, and Philosopher
    Louis deRosset { Spring 2019 Russell: The Theory of Descriptions 1. Bertrand Russell (1872-1970): mathematician, logician, and philosopher. He's one of the founders of analytic philosophy. \On Denoting" is a founding document of analytic philosophy. It is a paradigm of philosophical analysis. An analysis of a concept/phenomenon c: a recipe for eliminating c-vocabulary from our theories which still captures all of the facts the c-vocabulary targets. FOR EXAMPLE: \The Name View Analysis of Identity." 2. Russell's target: Denoting Phrases By a \denoting phrase" I mean a phrase such as any one of the following: a man, some man, any man, every man, all men, the present King of England, the present King of France, the centre of mass of the Solar System at the first instant of the twentieth century, the revolution of the earth round the sun, the revolution of the sun round the earth. (479) Includes: • universals: \all F 's" (\each"/\every") • existentials: \some F " (\at least one") • indefinite descriptions: \an F " • definite descriptions: \the F " Later additions: • negative existentials: \no F 's" (480) • Genitives: \my F " (\your"/\their"/\Joe's"/etc.) (484) • Empty Proper Names: \Apollo", \Hamlet", etc. (491) Russell proposes to analyze denoting phrases. 3. Why Analyze Denoting Phrases? Russell's Project: The distinction between acquaintance and knowledge about is the distinction between the things we have presentation of, and the things we only reach by means of denoting phrases. [. ] In perception we have acquaintance with the objects of perception, and in thought we have acquaintance with objects of a more abstract logical character; but we do not necessarily have acquaintance with the objects denoted by phrases composed of words with whose meanings we are ac- quainted.
    [Show full text]
  • Politics and Philosophy in the Left Vienna Circle
    Intersubjective Accountability: Politics and Philosophy in the Left Vienna Circle Thomas Uebel The University of Manchester In different places Rudolf Carnap and Otto Neurath affirmed “a noteworthy agreement” and an “inner link” between their philosophy of science and political movements agitating for radical socio-economic change. Given the normative abstinence of Vienna Circle philosophy, indeed the metaethical com- mitments of its verificationism, this claim presents a major interpretive chal- lenge that is only heightened when Neurath’s engagement for the socialization of national economies is taken into account. It is argued here that Carnap’s and Neurath’s positions are saved from inconsistency once some careful distinc- tions are understood and it is recognized that they, together with the other members of the Circle, adhered to an epistemic norm here called “intersubjective accountability.” 1. Introduction The question of the political potential possessed by the philosophies of the Vienna Circle is complex for more than one reason. It is so partly due to the politically heterogeneous membership of the Circle, partly due to the dif- ficult if not extreme political circumstances under which they had to operate, and partly due to the variable meanings of the parameter “political,” some of which are and some of which are not compatible with, in turn, variable ver- sions of the doctrine of the value-neutrality of science. For instance, philos- ophies of science may steadfastly be standing guard against pseudo-scientific nonsense being paraded as worthy of credence in public discourse, this con- cern for intellectual hygene becoming “political” depending on who spouts An earlier version of this paper was presented at the workshop “Positivismus als gesellschaftliches und politsches Projekt” convened by Eric Hilgendorf at the University of Münster in January 2017 and I thank the participants for discussions.
    [Show full text]
  • Moritz Schlick and Bas Van Fraassen: Two Different Perspectives on Causality and Quantum Mechanics Richard Dawid1
    Moritz Schlick and Bas van Fraassen: Two Different Perspectives on Causality and Quantum Mechanics Richard Dawid1 Moritz Schlick’s interpretation of the causality principle is based on Schlick’s understanding of quantum mechanics and on his conviction that quantum mechanics strongly supports an empiricist reading of causation in his sense. The present paper compares the empiricist position held by Schlick with Bas van Fraassen’s more recent conception of constructive empiricism. It is pointed out that the development from Schlick’s understanding of logical empiricism to constructive empiricism reflects a difference between the understanding of quantum mechanics endorsed by Schlick and the understanding that had been established at the time of van Fraassen’s writing. 1: Introduction Moritz Schlick’s ideas about causality and quantum mechanics dealt with a topic that was at the forefront of research in physics and philosophy of science at the time. In the present article, I want to discuss the plausibility of Schlick’s ideas within the scientific context of the time and compare it with a view based on a modern understanding of quantum mechanics. Schlick had already written about his understanding of causation in [Schlick 1920] before he set out to develop a new account of causation in “Die Kausalität in der gegenwärtigen Physik” [Schlick 1931]. The very substantial differences between the concepts of causality developed in the two papers are due to important philosophical as well as physical developments. Philosophically, [Schlick 1931] accounts for Schlick’s shift from his earlier position of critical realism towards his endorsement of core tenets of logical empiricism.
    [Show full text]
  • Analyticity George Bealer 1
    Analyticity George Bealer 1. In Critique of Pure Reason Kant introduced the term ‘analytic’ for judgments whose truth is guaranteed by a certain relation of ‘containment’ between the constituent concepts, and ‘synthetic’ for judgments which are not like this. Closely related terms were found in earlier writings of Locke, Hume and Leibniz. In Kant’s definition, an analytic judgment is one in which ‘the predicate B belongs to the subject A, as something which is (covertly) contained in this concept A’ ([1781/1787] 1965: 48). Kant called such judgments ‘explicative’, contrasting them with synthetic judgments which are ‘ampliative’. A paradigmatic analyticity would be: bachelors are unmarried. Kant assumed that knowledge of analytic necessities has a uniquely transparent sort of explanation. In the succeeding two centuries the terms ‘analytic’ and ‘synthetic’ have been used in a variety of closely related but not strictly equivalent ways. In the early 1950s Morton White (1950) and W.V. Quine (1951) argued that the terms were fundamentally unclear and should be eschewed. Although a number of prominent philosophers have rejected their arguments, there prevails a scepticism about ‘analytic’ and the idea that there is an associated category of necessary truths having privileged epistemic status. 1 The attack on ‘analytic’ 2 Extending the attack to ‘necessary’ and ‘a priori’ 3 Defending ‘analytic’ against Quine 4 More damaging problems with ‘analytic’ 5 Epistemological problems with ‘analytic’ 6 Whither ‘analytic’? 1 The attack on ‘analytic’ 1. ‘Analytic’ has been used in a wide variety of ways: truth by conceptual containment and truth whose denial is contradictory (Kant 1781/1787); logical truth (Bolzano 1837; Feigl 1949); truth by definition and logical derivation (Frege 1884; Pap 1958); truth in virtue of form (Schlick 1930–1); truth by definition and logical truth (Carnap 1937, 1947); truth by definition (Ayer 1936); truth based on meaning (Ayer 1936; C.I.
    [Show full text]
  • Reductionism in Education R.T
    Reductionism in Education R.T. Alien, Loughborough Leicestershire, England 1. Reductionism as a Metaphysical Issue In an earlier article, I demonstrated the necessary ingredients of metaphysics in education1• I propose now to show how Reductionism, some­ times called 'Reductivism', is a metaphysical issue, has serious consequences for human life, and can gravely affect educational practice and theory.2 Firstly, we need to distinguish Reductionism from the reduction of one set of laws to another within the same science, whereby the former set are shown to be special cases of the latter. Such reductions are legitimate simplifications. Reductionism, in contrast, is to be understood as the claim that one whole set of things is or can be wholly explained in terms of another set. It is, therefore, a reduction in the number of types of entity or the regions of the world. In particular, Reductionism today operates with a stratified conception of the universe--for example, mind, life, matter or energy--and claims to be able to eliminate the higher levels or to explain them completely in terms of the lower. Familiar examples are the claims that mind is observable behaviour and that people's beliefs and attitudes can be entirely explained in terms of their upbring­ ing or social class. Reductionism, therefore, is to be understood as the claim that a given set of things are either illusory or epiphenomenal: they have either no reality or no independent power. Three types of Reductionism have been distinguished3: a. Methodological--breaking down presently unintelligible wholes into their component parts, which can be managed, fmding their structures and func­ tions, and working thence back to an understanding of the whole.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Constructive Empiricism: Normative Or Descriptive?
    Constructive Empiricism: Normative or Descriptive? Moti Mizrahi Forthcoming in International Journal of Philosophical Studies Abstract: In this paper, I argue that Constructive Empiricism (CE) is ambiguous between two interpretations: CE as a normative epistemology of science and CE as a descriptive philosophy of science. When they present CE, constructive empiricists write as if CE is supposed to be more than a normative epistemology of science and that it is meant to be responsible to actual scientific practices. However, when they respond to objections, constructive empiricists fall back on a strictly normative interpretation of CE. This ambiguity seems to make CE immune to objections in a rather ad hoc fashion. Keywords: Bas van Fraassen; constructive empiricism; inference to the best explanation; observable; scientific realism; voluntarist epistemology 1. Introduction Roughly speaking, constructive Empiricism (CE) is the view that scientific theories “save the phenomena.” More precisely, as far as theories are concerned, constructive empiricists recommend suspending belief with respect to the existence of unobservable entities, events, or processes. As van Fraassen (1980, p. 12) puts it, CE is the view that “Science aims to give us theories that are empirically adequate; and acceptance of a theory involves as belief only that it is empirically adequate.” For van Fraassen (1980, p. 18), “to accept a theory is (for us) to believe 1 that it is empirically adequate—that what the theory says about what is observable (by us) is true.” CE is supposed to be an alternative to scientific realism. Usually, scientific realism is taken to include one or more of the following theses (Psillos 2006, p.
    [Show full text]