A First Order Semantic Approach to Adjectival Inference

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

A First Order Semantic Approach to Adjectival Inference A first order semantic approach to adjectival inference Marilisa Amoia Claire gardent INRIA/Universite´ de Nancy 1 & CNRS/Loria University of the Saarland Campus Scientifique BP 239 Saarbrucken,¨ Germany 54506 Vandoeuvre-les-Nancy, France [email protected] [email protected] Abstract der automated reasoners that could be put to use to reason about the meaning of higher-order formulae. As shown in the formal semantics litera- In this paper, we present a semantics for adjec- ture, adjectives can display very different tives that adopts an ontologically promiscuous ap- inferential patterns depending on whether proach and thereby supports first order inference for they are intersective, privative, subsective all types of adjectives including extensional ones. or plain non subsective. Moreover, many Indeed, traditional semantic classifications of ad- of these classes are often described using jectives such as (?; ?; ?) subdivide adjectives second order constructs. In this paper, we into two classes namely extensional vs. intensional adopt Hobbs’s ontologically promiscuous adjectives, the latter grouping together adjectives approach and present a first order treatment which intuitively denote functions from properties of adjective semantics which opens the way to properties i.e., second order objects. for a sophisticated treatment of adjectival We present a compositional semantics for ad- inference. The approach was implemented jectives which both (i) defines a first order repre- and tested using first order automated rea- sentation and (ii) integrates interactions with other soners. sources of linguistic information such as lexical se- mantics and morpho-derivational relations. We then 1 Introduction show that the proposed semantics correctly predicts As has often been observed, not all of natural lan- the inferential patterns observed to hold of the var- guage meaning can be represented by first order ious adjective subclasses identified in the literature logic. There are expressions such as, most, former, (?; ?; ?; ?). I didn’t whose meaning intuitively involve higher- This paper is structured as follows. We start by order constructs. presenting a classification of adjectives which is mo- Nevertheless, as (?) and others have argued, se- tivated by the different inferential patterns observed. mantic representations for natural language need not We then propose a compositional semantics for each be higher-order in that ontological promiscuity can class and show that it correctly predicts their inferen- solve the problem. That is, by reifying all objects tial behaviour. We conclude with a brief discussion that can be predicated of, it is possible to retain a of related work and pointers for further research. semantic representation scheme for NL that is first- 2 Inferential patterns and adjective classes order. This observation is crucial for computational ap- In the literature (?; ?; ?; ?), adjectives are usually plications for two reasons. First, logics that goes be- divided into four main classes namely, intersective, yond first order are highly undecidable. Second and subsective, privative and plain non subsective de- more importantly, there is no off the shelf higher or- pending on whether or not the [Adj N]AP phrase en- tails the properties expressed by the noun and/or the by very) and most of them can only be used attribu- adjective. More specifically, each of the four classes tively (He is a former president but not The presi- is characterised as follows. dent is former). Semantically, they are usually taken to denote second order properties i.e., functions of Intersective adjectives. This class includes com- the type hhe,ti, he,tii. mon categorical (e.g., red, rectangular, French) and Intensional adjectives include denominal (or rela- tautological (e.g., real, present) adjectives. It is char- tional) adjectives (e.g polar bear, atomic scientist), acterised by the inferential patterns: manner (or adverbial) adjectives (e.g. a poor liar, a fast car), emotive (e.g. a poor man) and modals, i.e. [A N] |= N all adjectives which are related to adverbs, quanti- [A N] |= A fiers or determiners (e.g. a feeble excuse, the specific For instance, saying that there is a red table im- reason, a fake nose, etc.). plies both that there is something red and that there is a table. 3 Assigning FOL Representation to Intensional adjectives Subsective adjectives form an ontologically het- erogeneous class including for instance denominal We now show how adjectives can be assigned an ap- (e.g., gastronomical) and measure (e.g. big) adjec- propriate first order logic representation which ap- tives. They are characterised by the fact that the [Adj propriately reflects their inferential behaviour. N]AP phrase does not entail the Adj property: Following Hobbs, we adopt a promiscuous ontol- ogy and assume that for every predication that can [A N] |= N be made in natural language, there corresponds an [A N] 6|= A “eventuality”. As Hobbs has argued, this allows for higher order predications to remain first order in that a big mouse For instance, is a mouse but is not they become predications over (first order) eventual- big. Instead it is “big for a mouse”. In other words, ities. ’bigness’ cannot be directly inferred as e.g., a big Thus, in the domain there are entities which are mouse and a big elephant are big in very different either eventualities or individuals and relations be- ways. tween individuals. Moreover like Hobbs, we assume Privative adjectives denote adjectives such that a model to describe a platonic universe containing the [Adj N]AP phrase entails the negation of the N everything that can be spoken about whether or not property: these things exist in the real world. To express exis- [A N] |= ¬N tence in the real world, a special predicate (Exists) is introduced. For instance, the former king is not the king and a We use the following notation: fake weapon is not a weapon. • ei, for eventuality variables, Plain non subsective adjectives are adjectives which preclude any inference wrt to the N property: • xi, for individuals, [A N] |= (N ∨ ¬N) • Pi, for properties of individuals. [A N] 6|= A And the following types: Thus, if Peter is an alleged murderer, it is impos- sible to know whether or not he is a murderer. • e will denote the type of individuals, Now, the class of intensional adjectives groups to- gether adjectives with a syntactic and semantic id- • ev the type of eventualities and iosyncratic behaviour. Syntactically, intensional ad- jectives are not gradable (e.g., cannot be modified • t a truth value. 3.1 The intuition As we shall shortly see, the additional lambda variable e is imposed by the treatment of adjective As shown in section ??, the semantics of [Adj N]AP semantics we propose and more specifically by the phrases has very different inferential properties de- necessity to sometimes distinguish between the indi- pending on the type of the adjective Adj. The differ- vidual described by the noun and the individual de- ences stem from three main points. scribed by the adjective. The variable P ol accounts The number of individuals introduced by the for the polarity of the noun, e.i. whether it occurs [Adj N]AP phrase. Thus, the red table evokes a with the negation or not. single individual x which is both red and a table We give here also the semantics assigned to the whilst the gastronomical book refers to a book x pronouns someone/something which will be used in which is about the gastronomy concept y. More gen- the derivations throughout this paper: erally, the variables predicated of by the noun and by the adjective can refer either to the same or to two (2) a. someone/something: λP ∃x.P (x) distinct individual(s). 3.3 The semantics of the copula The properties licensed by the adjective and the Following the proposal of Mantague, we assign a noun to contribute to the meaning of the [Adj unique representation for both the uses of the cop- N]AP phrase. Depending on the adjective type, ula in identity statements (e.g. John is Mary → the properties denoted by Adj and N will contribute john=mary) and in predicative assertions (e.g. John either directly or indirectly to the meaning of the is a man → man(john)): [Adj N]AP phrase. Thus in an intersective [Adj N]AP phrase, the meaning contributed by Adj and (3) a. be: λKλx.K(λy(x = y)) N are simply the properties they denote. By con- trast, the privative fake forces the negation of the N In the case of predicative assertions in which the property to be part of the Adj N meaning whilst the predicate is an adjective (e.g. John is brave), we subsective gastronomical induces a relation to the adjust the type of the argument of the copula in the morphoderivationally related noun concept (about following way: gastronomy) to be included in the the Adj N mean- ing. More generally, the properties that compose the (4) a. be Adj: be(Adj(λP olλeλx.true)) meaning of the Adj N phrase can be the denotation of Adj and/or N, the negation of N, its denotation in 3.4 The semantics of adjectives the past or some property derived from it. Given such a representation for nouns, we represent adjectives using the schema given in Figure ??. The existence in the real world of the entity de- Briefly, schema ?? captures the observations noted by the NP. In all cases the Adj N Phrase de- made in section (??) as follows. First it intro- notes a set of individuals but whilst in most cases the duces an existential quantification (in the platonic Adj N phrases is neutral with respect to the existence universe) over not one but two variables (ea and en) in the real world of these individuals, plain non sub- – depending on how the formula is instantiated (and sective (e.g., alleged murderer) explicitly questions in particular on the value of R1 and R2) these two it (an alleged murderer may or not exist in the real variables may or not denote the same object.
Recommended publications
  • Facing the Facts of Fake: a Distributional Semantics and Corpus Annotation Approach Bert Cappelle, Pascal Denis, Mikaela Keller
    Facing the facts of fake: a distributional semantics and corpus annotation approach Bert Cappelle, Pascal Denis, Mikaela Keller To cite this version: Bert Cappelle, Pascal Denis, Mikaela Keller. Facing the facts of fake: a distributional semantics and corpus annotation approach. Yearbook of the German Cognitive Linguistics Association, De Gruyter, 2018, 6 (9-42). hal-01959609 HAL Id: hal-01959609 https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-01959609 Submitted on 18 Dec 2018 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. Facing the facts of fake: a distributional semantics and corpus annotation approach Bert Cappelle, Pascal Denis and Mikaela Keller Université de Lille, Inria Lille Nord Europe Fake is often considered the textbook example of a so-called ‘privative’ adjective, one which, in other words, allows the proposition that ‘(a) fake x is not (an) x’. This study tests the hypothesis that the contexts of an adjective-noun combination are more different from the contexts of the noun when the adjective is such a ‘privative’ one than when it is an ordinary (subsective) one. We here use ‘embeddings’, that is, dense vector representations based on word co-occurrences in a large corpus, which in our study is the entire English Wikipedia as it was in 2013.
    [Show full text]
  • Person Features: Deriving the Inventory of Persons
    Chapter 2 Person Features: Deriving the Inventory of Persons 1. Introduction One long-standing aim of research into person has been to achieve a deeper understanding of the inventory of personal pronouns by decomposing them into a limited set of person features. The main aim of this chapter is to make a contribution to this enterprise. We will argue that a set of two privative person features is sufficient to derive the full inventory of attested pronouns and their interpretations, without generating non-attested pronouns. In chapter 1 we showed that the cross-linguistic inventory of attested persons is a small subset of the set of theoretically possible persons. The theoretically possible persons are those that can be formed by freely combining the speaker (for which we use the symbol i), associates of the speaker (ai), the addressee (u), associates of the addressee (au), and others (o). The generalizations that distinguish between the attested and non-attested persons are the following (repeated from (9) in chapter 1): (1) a. There is no person that contains associates of a participant but not the participant itself. b. There is no person that consists of others and only speaker(s) or of others and only addressee(s). c. No person system distinguishes pluralities containing a participant but not its associates from pluralities containing that participant as well as its associates. d. First and second person plural pronouns show an ‘associative effect’: any element contained in them other than i or u must be ai or au and cannot be o. 31 This leaves us with three persons with a singular interpretation and four persons with a plural interpretation.
    [Show full text]
  • So-Called Non-Subsective Adjectives
    So-Called Non-Subsective Adjectives Ellie Pavlick Chris Callison-Burch University of Pennsylvania University of Pennsylvania [email protected] [email protected] Abstract Privative Non-Subsective (AN N= ) anti- artificial counterfeit\ deputy; The interpretation of adjective-noun pairs erstwhile ex- fabricated fake false fictional fictitious former plays a crucial role in tasks such as rec- hypothetical imaginary mock mythical ognizing textual entailment. Formal se- onetime past phony pseudo- mantics often places adjectives into a simulated spurious virtual would-be Plain Non-Subsective (AN N and AN N = ) taxonomy which should dictate adjec- alleged apparent arguable6⇢ assumed\ 6 ; tives’ entailment behavior when placed in believed debatable disputed doubtful dubious erroneous expected faulty adjective-noun compounds. However, we future historic impossible improbable show experimentally that the behavior of likely mistaken ostensible plausible subsective adjectives (e.g. red) versus possible potential predicted presumed probable proposed putative questionable non-subsective adjectives (e.g. fake) is not seeming so-called supposed suspicious as cut and dry as often assumed. For ex- theoretical uncertain unlikely unsuccessful ample, inferences are not always symmet- ric: while ID is generally considered to be Table 1: 60 non-subsective adjectives from Nayak mutually exclusive with fake ID, fake ID is et al. (2014). Noun phrases involving non- considered to entail ID. We discuss the im- subsective adjectives are assumed not to entail the head noun. E.g. would-be hijacker hijacker. plications of these findings for automated 6) natural language understanding. (See Section 2 for definition of privative vs. plain). 1 Introduction Most adjectives are subsective, meaning that an in- In this example, recognizing that 1(a) does not en- stance of an adjective-noun phrase is an instance tail 1(b) hinges on understanding that a would-be of the noun: a red car is a car and a successful hijacker is not a hijacker.
    [Show full text]
  • Journal of South Asian Linguistics
    Volume 6 December 2013 Journal of South Asian Linguistics Contents 1 Copy theory in wh-in-situlanguages:SluicinginHindi-Urdu 3 Emily Manetta 2 The Priniciple A Problem 25 Pritty Patel-Grosz 3 Reviewof Ibero-Asian Creoles: Comparative Perspectives 51 Adam Roth Singerman 1 2 / Journal of South Asian Linguistics Editorial Statement We are very happy to present to you the sixth volume of the Journal of South Asian Linguistics. It comes to you several months later than the date it bears; we hope the excellence of the papers that make up this volume will make up in a small way for this delay. The volume consists of two papers and a book review. The first paper is by Emily Manetta and it investigates sluicing in Hindi-Urdu. Sluicing has been a topic of much interest for the syntax-semantics interface at least since the publication of a seminal paper by Chung, Ladusaw, and McCloskey in 1995. A commonly assumed treatment of sluicing analyzes it as clausal ellipsis that leaves out the wh-phrase. Given this assumption, the very existence of sluicing in wh-in-situ languages becomes surprising. This is where Manettas paper comes in. It argues that even though Hindi-Urdu is in general descriptively wh-in-situ, in sluicing contexts a higher copy of the wh-phrase is pronounced. The notion of ‘wh-in-situ’ is not a primitive property of the syntax of Hindi-Urdu; instead it is contextually determined. The second paper is by Pritty Patel-Grosz and it provides a solution for a very curious puzzle concerning the binding of anaphors in English, Greek, and Kutchi Gujarati.
    [Show full text]
  • From Montague Semantics to MTT-Semantics: a Meaningful Comparison
    From Montague Semantics to MTT-Semantics: A Meaningful Comparison Stergios Chatzikyriakidis and Zhaohui Luo (ESSLLI 2019: Lecture 1.1 by ZL) Type-Theoretical Semantics ❖ Montague Semantics ❖ R. Montague (1930–1971) ❖ Dominating in linguistic semantics since 1970s ❖ Set-theoretic with Church’s simple type theory as intermediate lang ❖ MTT-semantics: formal semantics in modern type theories ❖ Examples of MTTs: ❖ Predicative: MLTT (Martin-Löf 73,84); MLTTh (h-logic in HoTT) ❖ Impredicative: pCIC (Coq) and UTT (Luo 1994) ❖ Ranta (1994): formal semantics in Martin-Löf’s type theory ❖ Recent development on MTT-semantics ➔ full-scale alternative to Montague semantics ESSLLI 2019 2 ❖ Recent development on rich typing in NL semantics ❖ Asher, Bekki, Cooper, Grudzińska, Retoré, … ❖ S. Chatzikyriakidis and Z. Luo (eds.) Modern Perspectives in Type Theoretical Sem. Springer, 2017. (Collection on rich typing & …) ❖ MTT-semantics is one of these developments. ❖ Z. Luo. Formal Semantics in Modern Type Theories with Coercive Subtyping. Linguistics and Philosophy, 35(6). 2012. ❖ S. Chatzikyriakidis and Z. Luo. Formal Semantics in Modern Type Theories. Wiley/ISTE. (Monograph on MTT-semantics, to appear) ESSLLI 2019 3 Simple Type Theory v.s. Modern Type Theories ❖ Compare them from two aspects ❖ Type structure ❖ Logic ❖ Type structures ❖ Church’s simple type theory (in Montague’s semantics) ❖ Base types: e, t (plus s …) ❖ Function types: → (e.g., e→e→t) ❖ Modern type theories (next page: example type constructor) ❖ Dependent types (-types, -types, …) ❖ Inductive types (Nat, Fin(n), …) ❖ Universes – types of types (logical, linguistic, …) Note: MTTs are defined by proof-theoretic rules. ESSLLI 2019 4 x:A.B(x) – Example ❖ x:Human.Child(x) ❖ Type of functions mapping h to Child(h), type of h’s children.
    [Show full text]
  • Inference and Grammar: Intersectivity, Subsectivity, and Phases1
    INFERENCE AND GRAMMAR: INTERSECTIVITY, SUBSECTIVITY, AND PHASES1 Ulrich Reichard In the semantic tradition, the difference between intersective, subsective and non-subsective adjectives has often been taken to be a lexical phenomenon. The difference between them can be encoded in „meaning postulates‟ which are part of the lexical entry of the adjective (Kamp and Partee 1995). Alternatively, intersective and non-intersective adjectives may be treated as two different lexical categories (Siegel 1976). After a short exposition of the semantic perspective in section 1, I argue against this „lexicalist‟ treatment of adjectives by showing that, for most adjectives, both intersective and non-intersective readings are systematically available. This suggests that the phenomenon is grammatical rather than lexical (section 2). In section 4, I argue that the difference between intersective and subsective occurrences of adjectives follows from interface-conditions, given we assume a phasal architecture of grammar (Chomsky 2001) and adopt the recent thesis that intersective modifiers are clausal whereas non-intersective modifiers are not (Alexiadou, et al. 2007; Cinque 2010). Some of the independent grammatical evidence for this thesis is shortly summarized in section 3. To make a long story short: my overall proposal is that, due to the asymmetric structure of grammar, it is expected that modifiers are interpreted relative to their hosts. Subsectivity is thus the „normal case‟. However, if the modifier is clausal, it is also a phase. Phases are taken to be units of semantic interpretation. The interpretation of the modifier is thus already fixed at the time of modification and the modifier can therefore not be relativized to its modifee.
    [Show full text]
  • MODIFICATION? 9 Not Elsewhere
    DRAFT Modification Marcin Morzycki Michigan State University June 12, 2013 Latest revision: June 2014 This is a draft of a book in preparation for the Cambridge University Press series Key Topics in Semantics and Pragmatics. It’s something between a textbook for people with a basic background in semantics and an introduc- tory survey of work on the semantics of adjectives, adverbs, and degrees. For a fuller explanation, see section 1.2. Comments would be extremely helpful, so please don’t hesitate to contact me if you have any, even very minor ones. DRAFT Contents Acknowledgments vii 1 Preliminaries 1 1.1 Two problems .............................. 1 1.2 What this book is and isn’t ..................... 2 1.3 Background assumptions ...................... 3 1.3.1 Glossing logical notation ................. 3 1.3.2 Theoretical framework ................... 4 1.3.3 Notational and typographical conventions ....... 7 1.4 What, if anything, is modification? ................ 8 1.5 Roadmap ................................ 12 2 The Lexical Semantics of Adjectives: More Than Just Scales 13 2.1 Introduction .............................. 13 2.2 How adjectives and nouns combine: a typology . 14 2.2.1 Intersective interpretations . 14 2.2.2 Subsective interpretations . 16 2.2.3 Apparently subsective intersective interpretations . 20 2.2.4 Ordinary non-subsective adjectives . 22 2.2.5 Privative adjectives, which may not exist . 24 2.3 The type of adjectives and the nature of subsectivity . 26 2.3.1 How powerful are adjectives? . 26 2.3.2 Siegel: The Doublet Theory . 30 2.3.3 Larson: events inside the nominal extended projection 34 2.3.4 The implicit argument approach .
    [Show full text]
  • Adjectives: a Uniform Semantic Approach
    Adjectives: A Uniform Semantic Approach Nabil Abdullah and Richard A. Frost† School of Computer Science, University of Windsor, Windsor, Ontario N9B 3P4, Canada [email protected], [email protected] Abstract. Despite their simple syntactic form, adjective-noun combinations seem to have no straightforward semantic method that parallels the simplicity of the syntax. This has led to the conventional belief that adjectives belong to a (semantically motivated) hierarchy. This has the consequence that a uniform treatment of adjectives is unattainable—without resorting to notions such as possible worlds, which are difficult to map into competent computer programs. Moreover, because of their seemingly “undisciplined” semantic behaviour, adjective-noun combinations have been used by some authors (e.g. [5]) to further the argument of non-compositionality of natural-language expressions. Contrary to such views, we believe that adjectives are more systematic in their behaviour than originally thought. In support of this claim and based on typed sets, we propose a uniform approach to the semantics of adjective-noun combinations. It hypothesizes that adjective-noun combinations can semantically be thought of as a set intersection involving the adjective(s) and the head noun of the compound. 1 Adjective Hierarchy: The Conventional View It is a commonly-accepted view that adjectives have different underlying semantic rules (see [1,3,4,6,7,8,9,13,14,16,17]). This has led to the belief that adjectives assume a semantically-motivated hierarchy1 . This hierarchy is listed below: • Intersective e.g. ‘red’. • Subsective: o Pure, e.g. ‘accomplished’. o Double, e.g. ‘beautiful’. • Non-subsective: o Non-privative or non-committal, e.g.
    [Show full text]
  • Lecture 9. Issues in the Semantics of Adjectives 1. the Puzzle of Privative Adjectives
    Formal Semantics and Lexical Semantics, Lecture 9 Barbara H. Partee, MGU, May 10, 2013 Lecture 9. Issues in the Semantics of Adjectives 1. The puzzle of privative adjectives. ................................................................................................................... 1 1.1. Early formal semantics treatments of adjectives ........................................................................................... 1 1.2. Adjective classification ................................................................................................................................ 2 1.3. Are privative adjectives really privative? ..................................................................................................... 2 1.3.1. Modal and privative adjectives and NP-splits ................................................................................... 2 1.3.2. Principles of interpretation and the “no privative adjectives” hypothesis .................................... 5 2. Adjectives vs. Nouns: Sassoon's hypothesis. ...................................................................................................... 7 2.1. The RS Hypothesis ........................................................................................................................................ 7 2.2. Linguistic evidence. ................................................................................................................................... 10 References .............................................................................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Unimorph Schema)
    The Composition and Use of the Universal Morphological Feature Schema (UniMorph Schema) John Sylak-Glassman Center for Language and Speech Processing Johns Hopkins University [email protected] June 2, 2016 c John Sylak-Glassman ** Working Draft, v. 2 ** Contents 1 Introduction 3 2 Overview 4 3 Construction Methodology 5 3.1 Guiding Principles . .5 3.2 Constructing the Schema . .6 4 Annotation Formatting Guidelines 7 5 Dimensions of Meaning and Features 8 5.1 Aktionsart . .8 5.2 Animacy . 10 5.3 Argument Marking . 12 5.4 Aspect . 13 5.5 Case . 15 5.5.1 Core Case . 15 5.5.2 Non-Core, Non-Local Case . 16 5.5.3 Local Case . 18 5.6 Comparison . 20 5.7 Definiteness . 21 5.8 Deixis . 22 5.8.1 Distance . 22 5.8.2 Reference Point . 22 5.8.3 Visibility . 23 5.8.4 Verticality . 23 5.8.5 Summary . 24 1 5.9 Evidentiality . 24 5.10 Finiteness . 26 5.11 Gender and Noun Class . 27 5.12 Information Structure . 28 5.13 Interrogativity . 29 5.14 Language-Specific Features . 29 5.15Mood ............................................ 30 5.16 Number . 34 5.17 Part of Speech . 36 5.18 Person . 40 5.19 Polarity . 42 5.20 Politeness . 42 5.20.1 Speaker-Referent Axis . 43 5.20.2 Speaker-Addressee Axis . 44 5.20.3 Speaker-Bystander Axis . 44 5.20.4 Speaker-Setting Axis . 45 5.20.5 Politeness Features . 45 5.21 Possession . 46 5.22 Switch-Reference . 49 5.23 Tense . 53 5.24 Valency . 55 5.25 Voice .
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Introduction
    Numerals and the theory of number1 Abstract. I argue for an account of the semantics and of the number marking of nouns in the numeral+noun construction in Turkish, Western Armenian and English that combines insights from Scontras’ (2014) approach to the same data with Martí’s (2017, 2019) treatment of grammatical number, based on Harbour (2014). Fundamental to my approach are two of Harbour’s number features, [±atomic] and [±minimal], their compositional semantics, and a syntax where these features take the phrase that contains the numeral, which I call NumeralP, as their sister, following Scontras. The number marking we find on noun phrases with numerals across languages is thus viewed as a result of the principled interplay of the spell out of number features, their place, and that of numerals, in the syntactic structure of noun phrases, and their semantic import. Numerals are provided with a uniform semantics, no matter the language, and the semantics assumed for Turkish and Western Armenian noun phrases is empirically justified. I compare my proposal to Scontras (2014) and to Bale, Gagnon and Khanjian (2011a), highlighting in particular the empirical and theoretical shortcomings of the latter. The account uncovers a new domain where the effects of [±minimal] can be detected (cf. Harbour 2011, 2016), and demonstrates that an inclusive-only approach to plurality is not necessary in the account of the data, this time contra Scontras (2014). 1 Introduction This paper is concerned with the morphology and compositional semantics of the numeral2+noun construction in plural-marking languages. At least three types of languages must be recogniZed, depending on the number marking that appears on the noun accompanying the numeral.
    [Show full text]
  • Case and Number Suppletion in Pronouns
    Nat Lang Linguist Theory (2019) 37:1029–1101 https://doi.org/10.1007/s11049-018-9425-0 Case and number suppletion in pronouns Peter W. Smith1, · Beata Moskal1 · Ting Xu2 · Jungmin Kang3 · Jonathan David Bobaljik4 Received: 22 August 2016 / Accepted: 15 June 2018 / Published online: 27 September 2018 © Springer Nature B.V. 2018 Abstract Suppletion for case and number in pronominal paradigms shows robust patterns across a large, cross-linguistic survey. These patterns are largely, but not en- tirely, parallel to patterns described in Bobaljik (2012) for suppletion for adjectival degree. Like adjectival degree suppletion along the dimension positive < compar- ative < superlative, if some element undergoes suppletion for a category X, that element will also undergo suppletion for any category more marked than X on in- dependently established markedness hierarchies for case and number. We argue that the structural account of adjectival suppletive patterns in Bobaljik (2012) extends to pronominal suppletion, on the assumption that case (Caha 2009) and number (Har- bour 2011) hierarchies are structurally encoded. In the course of the investigation, we provide evidence against the common view that suppletion obeys a condition Electronic supplementary material The online version of this article (https://doi.org/10.1007/s11049-018-9425-0) contains supplementary material, which is available to authorized users. B P.W. Smith [email protected] B. Moskal [email protected] T. Xu [email protected] J. Kang [email protected] J.D. Bobaljik [email protected] 1 Goethe-Universität, Frankfurt, Germany 2 The Chinese University of Hong Kong, Hong Kong, China 3 Queens College, City University of New York, New York, USA 4 Harvard University, Cambridge, USA 1030 P.W.
    [Show full text]