Julie E. Cooper Democracy and Theocracy in Jewish Political Thought: from Baruch Spinoza to Michael Walzer [DO NOT Cite Or Circulate!!]

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Julie E. Cooper Democracy and Theocracy in Jewish Political Thought: from Baruch Spinoza to Michael Walzer [DO NOT Cite Or Circulate!!] Julie E. Cooper Democracy and Theocracy in Jewish Political Thought: From Baruch Spinoza to Michael Walzer [DO NOT cite or circulate!!] In recent years, theocracy has come to the fore as a live question for political and theoretical debate. To their surprise and, in most cases, chagrin, contemporary democratic theorists are now confronted with professed theocrats, to whose arguments for divine jurisdiction they must respond. In most critical conversations, democracy and theocracy are considered mutually exclusive. Debates about the prospects for Islamic democracy pit critics who dismiss Islam as inherently theocratic against defenders who argue that Islamic thought contains resources for indigenous forms of democracy. Scholars who alert readers to the persistent challenge of political theology often take their bearings from Carl Schmitt, whose insistence on absolutes is cast as a theocratic rejoinder to liberal democracy. At a moment when scholars are increasingly determined to refashion secularism – to accommodate a broader spectrum of religious practice and commitment – theocracy remains beyond the pale of scholarly consideration, dismissed as a grave threat to democracy. The relationship of theocracy to democracy is also a central preoccupation of an emerging scholarly field – the study of Jewish political thought. The publication, in 2000, of the first installment of The Jewish Political Tradition (a projected four volume anthology) arguably marks the debut of Jewish political thought as an academic field.1 1 Other major works in the field include the Hebraic Political Studies journal (2005- 2009); Novak 2000, 2005; and Biale, 1986. Although his work has been overshadowed 2 Edited by Michael Walzer and colleagues from the Shalom Hartman Institute in Jerusalem, these volumes pair primary texts (from the Bible, midrash, rabbinics, medieval philosophy, and modern political theory) with contemporary commentary. In their selection of primary texts, the editors reconstruct “the political arguments that have gone on for more than three millennia” of Jewish history, and in their inclusion of critical commentary, they invite contemporary readers “to join the arguments that have characterized the tradition and to carry them forward” (Walzer 2000, xiv, xxiv). Documenting a continuous and contentious tradition of Jewish political argument, these volumes seek to establish the canon for a new scholarly field. As set by Walzer and his colleagues, the field’s research agenda includes the demonstration that theocracy does not exhaust Jewish political discourse. With their selections from rabbinic texts, the editors seek to rebut charges that “the Jewish religion and the existence” of a democratic state “are antithetical to each other by their very essence” (Weiler 1988, xiii). On the editors’ interpretation, the Jewish political tradition is not inherently theocratic. Indeed, the editors uncover sources to support the contention that a state can be authentically Jewish, even if it is not ruled by Jewish law (halachah).2 Showcasing Jewish thinkers who embrace “the secularization of politics, affirming human, as opposed to divine, political agency,” the field’s architects provide ammunition by the volumes that Walzer has edited, Daniel Elazar was the first contemporary scholar to introduce the concept of a Jewish political tradition. See Elazar, 1997. 2 Israeli law incorporates elements from halachah, granting the state rabbinate jurisdiction over matters of personal status (marriage, divorce, burial, conversion) for the state’s Jewish citizens. 3 against those who would expand halachah’s jurisdiction in the state of Israel (Lorberbaum 2000, 2; see also 14, 151, 156). That theocracy is an undemocratic regime – a regime best combatted with alternative Jewish sources, which are fortunately copious – is an animating conviction of the project that Walzer and his colleagues have undertaken. Yet Walzer and his colleagues do not only task scholars of Jewish political thought with rebutting claims that Judaism is inherently theocratic and, consequently, inimical to democracy. As critics of theocracy, Walzer and his colleagues must also discredit the argument – counter-intuitive for most contemporary readers – that theocracy is a radically democratic, egalitarian regime. The campaign against theocracy takes a distinctive form for scholars of Jewish political thought. In addition to defending democracy against clerical rule, they must resist what Walzer identifies as a characteristically Jewish temptation: the temptation to embrace theocracy as an antidote to all forms of hierarchy and coercion. For participants in The Jewish Political Tradition project, exposing the “anarchist” tendencies of theocracy’s democratic defenders is as urgent as disarming democracy’s theocratic critics (see Walzer 2000, 128-132). The controversy surrounding theocracy has long taken this form in traditions of modern Jewish thought. As we will see, Baruch Spinoza is the first Jewish thinker to argue that theocracy is both a Jewish political signature and a democratic regime.3 3 In the twentieth century, the equation of democracy and theocracy is most closely associated with Martin Buber, who credits the ancient Israelites with “the rejection of political forms of rulership which impair a person’s immediate relation to God” (Buber 1990, 25). Buber is an express target of Walzer, Lorberbaum, and their colleagues in The Jewish Political Tradition and related works. An engagement with Buber’s admiring 4 Spinoza is also the first modern political theorist to endorse democracy, whose integrity he defends against the incursions of clerical rule. Spinoza’s Theologico-Political Treatise is a canonical source for the worry that independent clerical authority subverts democracy, as well as for the hope that establishing a direct political relationship with God exempts one from hierarchy and subordination. Using a narrative about Jewish political history to articulate a theory of state sovereignty, Spinoza vacillates between appreciation for the Hebrews’ idiosyncratic political achievements and dismay at their legacy for modern Jewish politics. In this essay, I return to Spinoza’s Theologico-Political Treatise in an effort to understand why the critique of theocracy takes this distinctive form in Jewish traditions, and what is at stake in making theocracy’s repudiation a central tenet of the study of Jewish political thought. I return to Spinoza because he establishes the conceptual framework that Walzer and his colleagues inhabit, a framework in which state sovereignty provides the default configuration for political community. Writing as a proponent of absolute sovereignty at the moment of the state’s ascendance, Spinoza understood that the nation-state system would require radical transformations in the Jews’ political posture, and that Jewish political claims would challenge norms of state sovereignty. In a framework that makes sovereignty the defining horizon of the political, rabbinic Judaism’s bonds of obligation do not register as political. To join the ranks of portrait of the biblical theocracy as a voluntary community, free from hierarchy and coercion, is beyond the scope of this essay. Here, I do the ground clearing work necessary to establish Buber’s thought as a alternative trajectory for the study of Jewish political thought. 5 the political, Jews must either embrace the nation-state system – through individual citizenship in democratic republics or the establishment of a Jewish state – or they must resist norms of state sovereignty. In the story that Spinoza tells about Jewish political history, relaxing the strictures of unified sovereignty is precisely what theocracy allows. When Spinoza makes theocracy the vehicle for this relaxation, he traces Jewish ambivalence regarding sovereignty to foundational theological convictions. Even before the destruction of the second temple, in 70 C.E., consigned the Jews to statelessness and dispersion, Spinoza argues, they exhibited idiosyncratic attitudes toward political institutions that Spinoza hopes to make standard. As Spinoza reveals, sovereignty’s status as the defining horizon of the political is what is really at stake in Jewish debates about theocracy. In the framework that Spinoza establishes, the critique of theocracy serves not only to keep ambitious clerics in place, but also to counter Jewish resistance to norms of state sovereignty. Against interpretations that reduce Spinoza’s motives for relating Hebrew political history to Erastian convictions, I contend that, with the introduction of theocracy as a distinctive regime type, Spinoza exposes the tension between Jewish political aspirations and norms of absolute sovereignty. To account for Hebraic political success, in biblical times, Spinoza must concede that theocratic communities can persist in the absence of an absolute sovereign. Indeed, Spinoza expresses qualified admiration for a regime (theocracy) in which theological delusions support an imperfect sovereign. Yet Spinoza ultimately recoils from the flexible attitude toward sovereignty required to account for Hebraic political success, because this attitude also accounts for what Spinoza considers rabbinic Judaism’s abject political failure (specifically, its insistence 6 that legal obligation outlasts and transcends state borders). As Spinoza stages the Jews’ encounter with the state, in the Theologico-Political Treatise, the confrontation ends with the induction of the Jews into the state system, rather
Recommended publications
  • Theocracy in Nigeria: the Religious Gamble and National Cohesion
    Ibrahim Musa Ahmadu BETH 10: 1998 69 The Search for Theocracy in Nigeria: The Religious Gamble and National Cohesion By Ibrahim Musa Ahmadu Preamble Religion has been an important force for facilitating radical political and social change, providing' the motivation, ideology and justification for rebellion or revolt against established governments. Religiously inspired revolutionary movements have occurred throughout history in a bid to founding theocratic states in which Godor some conceived deity would direct the affairs of the society through human agents. Often led by a messianic figure, many of such revolutionary movements have produced significant political and social innovations that have been beneficial or detrimental to the well being of the society it was out to improve. The phenomenon of religio-political insurgence often began as a dream of re-enacting a past or creating a future "Golden Age" that would usher in an era of justice and bliss on earth. Undergirding such millenarian expectation was a general dissatisfaction with the existing political order believed to have been brought about as a result of human deviation from divine mandate. Embued with the conviction that the contemporary travail which had reduced human dignity and value was after all redeemable through some divine intervention, an ideological spirit of heroism would be infused on believers that could sustain their struggle against the forces of evil and decay that have engulfed the society. In the attempt to bring the anticipated new order in line with the mover's conception of justice, a necessary myth that would instil fear and hatred for the old system must be put in place to provide legitimacy for intervention.
    [Show full text]
  • Freedom Or Theocracy?: Constitutionalism in Afghanistan and Iraq Hannibal Travis
    Northwestern Journal of International Human Rights Volume 3 | Issue 1 Article 4 Spring 2005 Freedom or Theocracy?: Constitutionalism in Afghanistan and Iraq Hannibal Travis Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarlycommons.law.northwestern.edu/njihr Recommended Citation Hannibal Travis, Freedom or Theocracy?: Constitutionalism in Afghanistan and Iraq, 3 Nw. J. Int'l Hum. Rts. 1 (2005). http://scholarlycommons.law.northwestern.edu/njihr/vol3/iss1/4 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by Northwestern University School of Law Scholarly Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Northwestern Journal of International Human Rights by an authorized administrator of Northwestern University School of Law Scholarly Commons. Copyright 2005 Northwestern University School of Law Volume 3 (Spring 2005) Northwestern University Journal of International Human Rights FREEDOM OR THEOCRACY?: CONSTITUTIONALISM IN AFGHANISTAN AND IRAQ By Hannibal Travis* “Afghans are victims of the games superpowers once played: their war was once our war, and collectively we bear responsibility.”1 “In the approved version of the [Afghan] constitution, Article 3 was amended to read, ‘In Afghanistan, no law can be contrary to the beliefs and provisions of the sacred religion of Islam.’ … This very significant clause basically gives the official and nonofficial religious leaders in Afghanistan sway over every action that they might deem contrary to their beliefs, which by extension and within the Afghan cultural context, could be regarded as
    [Show full text]
  • Religion–State Relations
    Religion–State Relations International IDEA Constitution-Building Primer 8 Religion–State Relations International IDEA Constitution-Building Primer 8 Dawood Ahmed © 2017 International Institute for Democracy and Electoral Assistance (International IDEA) Second edition First published in 2014 by International IDEA International IDEA publications are independent of specific national or political interests. Views expressed in this publication do not necessarily represent the views of International IDEA, its Board or its Council members. The electronic version of this publication is available under a Creative Commons Attribute-NonCommercial- ShareAlike 3.0 (CC BY-NC-SA 3.0) licence. You are free to copy, distribute and transmit the publication as well as to remix and adapt it, provided it is only for non-commercial purposes, that you appropriately attribute the publication, and that you distribute it under an identical licence. For more information on this licence visit the Creative Commons website: <http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-sa/3.0/> International IDEA Strömsborg SE–103 34 Stockholm Sweden Telephone: +46 8 698 37 00 Email: [email protected] Website: <http://www.idea.int> Cover design: International IDEA Cover illustration: © 123RF, <http://www.123rf.com> Produced using Booktype: <https://booktype.pro> ISBN: 978-91-7671-113-2 Contents 1. Introduction ............................................................................................................. 3 Advantages and risks ...............................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • The Communitarian Critique of Liberalism Author(S): Michael Walzer Reviewed Work(S): Source: Political Theory, Vol
    The Communitarian Critique of Liberalism Author(s): Michael Walzer Reviewed work(s): Source: Political Theory, Vol. 18, No. 1 (Feb., 1990), pp. 6-23 Published by: Sage Publications, Inc. Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/191477 . Accessed: 24/08/2012 12:14 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Sage Publications, Inc. is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Political Theory. http://www.jstor.org THE COMMUNITARIAN CRITIQUE OF LIBERALISM MICHAEL WALZER Institutefor A dvanced Study 1. Intellectualfashions are notoriously short-lived, very much like fashions in popularmusic, art, or dress.But thereare certainfashions that seem regularlyto reappear. Like pleated trousers or short skirts, they are inconstant featuresof a largerand more steadily prevailing phenomenon - in this case, a certainway of dressing. They have brief but recurrent lives; we knowtheir transienceand excepttheir return. Needless to say,there is no afterlifein whichtrousers will be permanentlypleated or skirtsforever short. Recur- renceis all. Althoughit operatesat a muchhigher level (an infinitelyhigher level?) of culturalsignificance, the communitarian critique of liberalismis likethe pleatingof trousers:transient but certainto return.It is a consistently intermittentfeature of liberalpolitics and social organization.No liberal successwill make it permanently unattractive.
    [Show full text]
  • In the Individualism/Communitarianism Debate: in Defense of Personism1 Nancy O. Myles
    Myles, N. O./ Legon Journal of the Humanities 29.2 (2018) DOI: https://dx.doi.org/10.4314/ljh.v29i2.9 ‘The individual’ in the individualism/communitarianism debate: In defense of personism1 Nancy O. Myles Assistant Lecturer Department of Philosophy and Classics University of Ghana, Legon, Ghana PhD Candidate, University of Utrecht, The Netherlands Email: [email protected]; [email protected] Submitted: April 16, 2018 / Accepted: October 20, 2018 / Published: December 3, 2018 Abstract Conceptually obfuscating the construct ‘the individual’ with the individuality of persons is the main underlying presupposition that generates the communitarianism/individualism debate and nourishes its tensions. Adopting chiefly an analytic approach, this paper brings some clarity to the substance of the debate focusing on Western ‘communitarian’ thought. It advocates making ‘the person’ the focus as ‘personism’ necessarily encompasses individuality and communality. Dispelling many quandaries of the debate, it is hoped, exposes to a greater degree, what should be one main, if not the main, concern of socio- political theory and practice. Keywords: ‘the individual’, individuality, community, communality, personism 1 The author wishes to acknowledge that substantive portions of this article appear in some form in her PhD dissertation. Legon Journal of the Humanities 29.2 (2018) Page | 241 Myles, N. O./ ‘The individual’ in the individualism/communitarianism debate Introduction The disagreement in the communitarianism/individualism debate: A recap A bone of contention between individualist and communitarian thought, regardless of the particular differentiation per author, is the idea of ‘the individual’. The question or concern that engaged the neo-Kantianism of Rawls’ A theory of justice (1971) as well as other individualist thinkers such as Robert Nozick, David Gauthier, Ronald Dworkin, and to some extent Kymlicka is ‘the individual’.
    [Show full text]
  • COURSE OUTLINE PHI/POL-220 Philosophy of Politics Course
    COURSE OUTLINE PHI/POL-220 Philosophy of Politics Course Number: PHI 220 or POL 220 Course Title: Philosophy of Politics / Modern Political Theory Required Materials: Text: Classics of Modern Political Theory, ed. by Steven M. Cahn (NY: Oxford University Press, 1997) Catalog Description: An introduction to modern political theory starting with Machiavelli and concluding with Mill. Highlights include readings from Hobbes, Spinoza, Locke, Rousseau, Kant, The Federalist Papers, Burke, Bentham, Hegel, and Marx and Engels. Critical analysis and selected issues in modern political theory are stressed. Students may opt to take this course either as a political science or philosophy elective. See course description number under each area. Course Coordinator: Saul Goldwasser I. THE ORGANIZATION OF THE COURSE (ORIGINAL READINGS) (Weekly Class Schedule by Topic) INTRODUCTION - Lecture on Modern Political Theory: Criteria for Evaluation and Application to Modern Issues 1. Machiavelli 2. Thomas Hobbes 3. Baruch Spinoza 4. John Locke 5. Montesquieu 6. Jean-Jacques Rousseau 7. David Hume 5-8 Page Joint Researched Position Paper Due 8. Adam Smith 9. Immanuel Kant 10. The Declaration of Independence The Constitution of the US the Federalist Papers 11. Edmund Burke and Alexis De Tocqueville 12. Georg Wilheim Friedrich Hegel 13. Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels 14. Jeremy Bentham and John Stuart Mill II. GENERAL OBJECTIVES A. Defining Political Theory (aka Political Philosophy and Political Thought) 1. History 2. Significance - The Proper Purposes of Government B. Introduce Criteria for Evaluation of Political Theories - Analysis and Assessment 1. Desirable Political Arrangements Involving Analysis of Moral Values 2. Possible Political Social Contractual Arrangements 3.
    [Show full text]
  • Is Theopolitics an Antipolitics? 65 Stipulate That the Purpose of Politics Is to Maintain the State, It Refusestoallow Politics Its Autonomous Existence
    Samuel HayimBrody Is TheopoliticsanAntipolitics? Martin Buber,Anarchism, and the Ideaofthe Political We havecome to recognize that the political is the total, and as aresult we know that any decision about whether something is unpolitical is always a political decision... – Carl Schmitt, “Preface to the Second Edition” of Political Theology (1934) Hereisthe serpent in the fullness of its power! – Martin Buber, “Letter to Gandhi” (1939) Introduction:The Shape of the Theopolitical Problem “Antipolitics,” writes Michael Walzer, “is akind of politics.”¹ Thispuzzling state- ment occurs in Walzer’srecent discussion of the Bible, which he calls “apolitical book,” but one that has “no political theory” in it; its writers are “engaged with politics” but are “not very interested in politics,” although he admits that “writ- ers who are uninterested in politics nonetheless have alot to saythat is politi- callyinteresting.” Walzerhas always been aclear writer,and if this series of statements seems convoluted, this maybedue to the subject matter itself. Close examination of the relationship of religion and politics has away of calling into question our very understanding of the natureofboth “religion” and “pol- itics” as distinct and separate spheres that can each be described according to its own special set of characteristics. This, of course, is an inconvenient state of af- fairs for university departments like PoliticalScience and Religion, which would like to assume thatthe objects of their studydoinfact exist. This essayexcavates and explicates the potential contribution of Martin Buber to the contemporary resurgence of interest in the borders between religion and politics, through an examination of the category “theopolitics” in Buber’s mature work, particularly Königtum Gottes (1932), as well as his later biblical writings.² Interest in Buber,both during and after his lifetime, has centered on Michael Walzer, In God’sShadow:Politics in the HebrewBible (New Haven: Yale University Press, 2012), xiii.
    [Show full text]
  • Editors' Interview with Michael Walzer
    [50] JOURNAL OF POLITICAL THOUGHT INTERVIEW [with Michael Walzer] Michael Walzer is a prominent American political theorist and public intel- lectual. A professor emeritus at the Institute for Advanced Study in Princ- eton, New Jersey, he is co-editor of Dissent, an intellectual magazine that he has been affiliated with since his years as an undergraduate at Brandeis University. He has written about a wide variety of topics in political theory and moral philosophy, including political obligation, just and unjust war, nationalism and ethnicity, economic justice, and the welfare state. He has played a critical role in the revival of a practical, issue-focused ethics and in the development of a pluralist approach to political and moral life. Wal- zer’s books include Just and Unjust Wars (1977), On Toleration (1997), and Spheres of Justice (1983). We sat down with him in May for a wide- ranging conversation on the interplay between personal identity and po- litical thought, the state of political theory today, and the overlapping chal- lenges posed by religion and ethnicity for the contemporary nation-state. I. Identity and the Political interested in left-issue politics. Theory License My teachers at Brandeis told me I should apply to graduate school JPT: What first drew you to the in political science, because it field of political theory? wasn’t really a field and you could do whatever you wanted. Whereas MW: When I was a history major in history you would be commit- at Brandeis, I was first interested ted to archival research, in politi- in studying the history of ideas.
    [Show full text]
  • Islam and the Challenge of Democratic Commitment
    Fordham International Law Journal Volume 27, Issue 1 2003 Article 2 Islam and the Challenge of Democratic Commitment Dr. Khaled Abou El-Fadl∗ ∗ Copyright c 2003 by the authors. Fordham International Law Journal is produced by The Berke- ley Electronic Press (bepress). http://ir.lawnet.fordham.edu/ilj Islam and the Challenge of Democratic Commitment Dr. Khaled Abou El-Fadl Abstract The author questions whether concurrent and simultaneous moral and normative commit- ments to Islam and to a democratic form of government are reconcilable or mutually exclusive. The author will argue in this Article that it is indeed possible to reconcile Islam with a commitment in favor of democracy. The author will then present a systematic exploration of Islamic theology and law as it relates to a democratic system of government, and in this context, address the various elements within Islamic belief and practice that promote, challenge, or hinder the emergence of an ideological commitment in favor of democracy. In many ways, the basic and fundamental ob- jective of this Article is to investigate whether the Islamic faith is consistent or reconcilable with a democratic faith. As addressed below, both Islam and democracy represent a set of comprehensive and normative moral commitments and beliefs about, among other things, the worth and entitle- ments of human beings. The challenging issue is to understand the ways in which the Islamic and democratic systems of convictions and moral commitments could undermine, negate, or validate and support each other. ISLAM AND THE CHALLENGE OF DEMOCRATIC COMMITMENT Dr. Khaled Abou El Fadl* The question I deal with here is whether concurrent and simultaneous moral and normative commitments to Islam and to a democratic form of government are reconcilable or mutually exclusive.
    [Show full text]
  • Separation of Church and State: a Theologically Liberal, Anti-Catholic, and American Principle Philip Hamburger
    University of Chicago Law School Chicago Unbound Occasional Papers Law School Publications 2002 Separation of Church and State: A Theologically Liberal, Anti-Catholic, and American Principle Philip Hamburger Follow this and additional works at: http://chicagounbound.uchicago.edu/occasional_papers Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Philip Hamburger, "Separation of Church and State: A Theologically Liberal, Anti-Catholic, and American Principle," University of Chicago Law Occasional Paper, No. 43 (2002). This Working Paper is brought to you for free and open access by the Law School Publications at Chicago Unbound. It has been accepted for inclusion in Occasional Papers by an authorized administrator of Chicago Unbound. For more information, please contact [email protected]. OCCASIONAL PAPERS FROM THE LAW SCHOOL THE UNIVERSITY OF CHICAGO NUMBER 43 2002 Occasional Papers from The University of Chicago Law School Number 43 November 2002 Separation of Church and State A Theologically Liberal, Anti-Catholic, and American Principle By Philip Hamburger John P. Wilson Professor of Law 'A Theologically Liberal, Anti-Catholic, andAmerican Principle"isan excerptfrom Separation of Church and State by Philip Hamburger,Harvard University Press, 2002. @ 2002 INTRODUCTION This Occasional Paper reproduces a chapter from Professor Philip Hamburger's new book, Separation of Church and State, published in the summer of 2002 by Harvard University Press. The book argues that during the past two centuries the adoption of the idea of separa- tion between church and state has transformed American conceptions of the religious liberty guaranteed by the First Amendment. Many Americans take the idea of separation between church and state for granted.
    [Show full text]
  • Islam and Democracy: Is Modernization a Barrier? John O
    Religion Compass 1/1 (2007): 170±178, 10.1111/j. 1749-8171.2006.00017.x Islam and Democracy: Is Modernization a Barrier? John O. Voll Georgetown University Abstract The relationship between Islam and democracy is a hotly debated topic. Usually the disagreements are expressed in a standard form. In this form, the debaters' definitions of ªIslamº and ªdemocracyº determine the conclusions arrived at. It is possible, depending upon the definitions used, to ªproveº both positions: Islam and democracy are compatible and that they are not. To escape from the predefined conclusions, it is necessary to recognize that ªIslamº and ªdemocracyº are concepts with many definitions. In the twenty-first century, important interpretations of Islam open the way for political visions in which Islam and democracy are mutually supportive. Does religion represent an obstacle to modernization and democratization? Does religion pose a threat to democracy if a democratically elected govern- ment becomes a ªtheocracyº? Does the majority rule of democracy threaten the liberty and freedom of other members of a society? If the majority imposes its will upon minorities, is that a departure from democracy in general or form of ªliberalº democracy? Does modernization strengthen or inhibit democratization and individual liberty? These broad questions are being debated in many different contexts around the world. They provide a framework for looking at the experience of Muslim societies and the relationships between Islam and democracy. Tensions between democracy and liberty
    [Show full text]
  • Redalyc.Myths and Realities on Islam and Democracy in the Middle East
    Estudios Políticos ISSN: 0121-5167 [email protected] Instituto de Estudios Políticos Colombia Cevik, Salim Myths and Realities on Islam and Democracy in the Middle East Estudios Políticos, núm. 38, enero-junio, 2011, pp. 121-144 Instituto de Estudios Políticos Medellín, Colombia Available in: http://www.redalyc.org/articulo.oa?id=16429066007 How to cite Complete issue Scientific Information System More information about this article Network of Scientific Journals from Latin America, the Caribbean, Spain and Portugal Journal's homepage in redalyc.org Non-profit academic project, developed under the open access initiative Myths and Realities on Islam and Democracy in the Middle East* Salim Cevik** Abstract There is a strong body of literature that claims that Islam and democracy are essentially incompatible. However, Islam like all other religions is multivocal and it has strong theorethical elements that can also work for a basis of a democratic polity. Throughout the Muslim world there are certain countries that achieved a considerable level of democratization. It is only the Arab world, not the Muslim world, that so far represents a complete failure in terms of democratic transition. The failure of Arab world should be attributed to more political reasons, such as oil economy and the rentier state model than to Islam. Lack of international support for pro-democracy movements in the region, under the fear that they might move towards an Islamist political system is also an important factor in the democratic failures in the region. However, democratic record of Turkey’s pro-Islamic Justice and Development Party challenges these fears. With the international attention it attracts, particularly from the Arab world, Turkish experience provides a strong case for the compatibility of [ 121 ] democracy and Islam.
    [Show full text]