Kant's Argument for the Apperception Principle

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Kant's Argument for the Apperception Principle EJOP 364 Dispatch: 6.5.09 Journal: EJOP CE: Latha Journal Name Manuscript No. B Author Received: No. of pages: 26 PE: Bindu KV/Bhuvi DOI: 10.1111/j.1468-0378.2009.00364.x 1 2 3 Kant’s Argument for the Apperception 4 Principle 5 6 Melissa McBay Merritt 7 8 9 Abstract: My aim is to reconstruct Kant’s argument for the principle 10 of the synthetic unity of apperception. I reconstruct Kant’s 11 argument in stages, first showing why thinking should be 12 conceived as an activity of synthesis (as opposed to attention), 13 and then showing why the unity or coherence of a subject’s 14 representations should depend upon an a priori synthesis. The 15 guiding thread of my account is Kant’s conception of enlight- 16 enment: as I suggest, the philosophy of mind advanced in the 17 Deduction belongs to an enlightenment epistemology. Kant’s 18 conception of enlightenment turns on the requirement that a 19 subject be able to recognize herself as the source of her cognitions. 20 The argument for the apperception principle is reconstructed under 21 the guidance of this conception of the ideal of enlightenment. 22 23 24 25 If by the word ‘understanding’ is meant the faculty of cognition by 26 means of rules [. .] then these rules are not to be understood as those 27 according to which nature guides the human being in his conduct, as 28 occurs with animals which are driven by natural instinct, but only those 29 that he himself makes. (Kant, Anth §42 (7:197)) 30 31 32 33 1. Introduction 34 35 The fundamental principle of Kant’s epistemology is called the ‘principle of the 36 original synthetic unity of apperception’ (§17, B137). I shall simply refer to it as the 37 ‘apperception principle’.1 Kant maintains that it is the ‘highest’ and ‘first 38 principle’ of human cognition (§16, B135; §17, B139). Although Kant does not 39 offer a concise statement of this principle, let me begin with what I take to be an 40 to be an uncontroversial report of its content: the apperception principle says that 41 a cognitive subject’s representations belong to it in virtue of an a priori synthesis.2 42 What is crucial here, as some commentators have noted, is that the 43 apperception principle makes a claim about ‘a priori synthesis’. One reason 44 why this is puzzling is that we generally speak of propositions or modes of 45 knowledge as being a priori—independent of experience—so it is unclear what it European Journal of Philosophy ]]]:]] ISSN 0966-8373 pp. 1–26 r 2009 Blackwell Publishing Ltd., 9600 Garsington Road, Oxford OX4 2DQ, UK and 350 Main Street, Malden, MA 02148, USA. EJOP(BWUK EJOP 364.PDF 06-May-09 21:19 188139 Bytes 26 PAGES n operator=gs.ravishnkar) 364 2 Melissa McBay Merritt 1 could mean for synthesis to be a priori. At the end of the paper I will address 2 Kant’s claims about a priori synthesis in particular. The bulk of the paper, 3 however, will be devoted to considering the significance of Kant’s appeal to 4 synthesis as such—an issue that is not often directly addressed by commentators, 5 and which we need to come to terms with before considering the significance of 6 calling the synthesis in question ‘a priori’. One of the major moves Kant makes in 7 the Transcendental Deduction is to suggest that thinking must be conceived as an 8 activity of synthesis—a point which is encapsulated in the apperception principle. 9 As I will argue, this conception of the activity of thinking is advanced in 10 opposition to a conception of thinking as attention. The attention model of 11 thinking, I will suggest, is rejected on the grounds that it is not compatible with 12 the enlightenment aspirations of a properly ‘critical’ philosophy. Much of what I 13 shall say about Kant’s apperception principle will stem from this point. 14 Let me say outright that I do not find an explicitly delineated argument for the 15 apperception principle in the pages of the Critique—though my aim here is to 16 reconstruct one from materials that Kant provides.3 Commentaries often present 17 the apperception principle as an unargued, or self-evident, presupposition of 18 Kant’s Transcendental Deduction.4 We should be wary of this suggestion: it 19 should hardly be appropriate for Kant to present the fundamental principle of his 20 epistemology (and, by extension, theoretical metaphysics) as an unargued 21 presupposition—the principle simply does too much work in Kant’s system to be 22 granted such easy passage. That being said, it is the case that the Deduction kicks 23 off with a putatively self-evident claim about self-consciousness; and since Kant 24 takes apperception to be a mode of self-consciousness, it is true that the argument 25 of the Deduction proceeds from a claim about apperception.5 Yet that initial claim 26 is not identical with the apperception principle, as we shall see: the starting point 27 of the Deduction contains no claim about a priori synthesis. Taking the 28 apperception principle to be an unargued presupposition confuses claims that 29 Kant keeps distinct. Part of what I shall be doing in this paper is to pry apart and 30 explore the argumentative distance between that starting point and the 31 apperception principle itself. 32 My reconstruction of Kant’s argument for the apperception principle rests on 33 two related presuppositions about the ‘critical philosophy’ to which it belongs. 34 First, the Critique of Pure Reason is billed as human reason’s assessment of its own 35 cognitive capacity. The genitive construction in the title (Kritik der reinen Vernunft) 36 is ambiguous, suggesting that reason may be both the subject and object of the 37 inquiry. This point will inform my interpretation of Kant’s use of the first-person 38 in the argument for the apperception principle.6 The second point can also be 39 drawn out of the title, now focusing on the term ‘critique’: at issue is Kant’s 40 conception of a properly critical philosophy. By a critical philosophy in this 41 generic sense, I mean a philosophical project that properly acknowledges the 42 demands of enlightenment. For Kant, as for many others, the motto of 43 enlightenment is to ‘think for oneself’—and not accept claims passively on the 44 basis of external authority. This ideal is invoked in various ways throughout the 45 Critique: in its initial portrayal of the scientist as a judge putting nature to the r 2009 Blackwell Publishing Ltd. EJOP(BWUK EJOP 364.PDF 06-May-09 21:19 188139 Bytes 26 PAGES n operator=gs.ravishnkar) 364 Kant’s Argument for the Apperception Principle 3 1 question, rather than as a pupil passively registering information from without 2 (Bxiii); in its suggestion that an individual cannot be said to possess rules or 3 principles for knowledge unless she is able to recognize, independently, their 4 applicability in various contexts (A134/B172-5); and in its spoof of the student of 5 dogmatic metaphysics, who is able to make sanctioned moves within a given 6 system but is dumbstruck should someone ‘dispute a definition with him’ 7 (A836/B864). Yet the ideal of enlightenment is writ most large in Kant’s 8 conception of critical philosophy as an exercise of corrective self-knowledge—an 9 exercise carried out under the motto that only human reason can adjudicate the 10 claims of human reason (A752/B780; A849/B877; P 4:263). Now, if Kant takes the 11 apperception principle to be the fundamental principle of human knowledge, 12 then presumably the account of our cognitive capacity that arises from this 13 principle should be appropriate to the enlightenment ideal. In other words: the 14 apperception principle belongs to an enlightenment epistemology. 15 As I will suggest, Kant’s conception of enlightenment provides the general 16 framework within which he argues for a particular view of the nature of 17 thinking—the view, indeed, that is expressed in the apperception principle. I begin 18 by sketching that framework, focusing on a set of three maxims that specify 19 fundamental normative requirements of our cognitive practices (§2). An enlight- 20 enment epistemology, as Kant understands it, gives special emphasis to the notion 21 of cognitive agency—a point that shall prove important in the argument for the 22 apperception principle. I then turn to the text of the Deduction: at first my aim is 23 simply to draw attention to the argumentative distance between the starting point 24 of the Deduction and the apperception principle itself (§3). Then I prepare to 25 reconstruct the argument for the apperception principle, first by considering the 26 two models of thinking that I take to be at issue for Kant: thinking as a certain 27 mode of attention, and thinking as an activity of synthesis. After providing an 28 initial account of why the attention model of thinking should be rejected (§4), and 29 clarifying crucial terminology (§5), I reconstruct Kant’s argument for the 30 apperception principle. This reconstruction is broken down into two main parts: 31 first I explain why Kant supposes that thinking must be conceived as an activity of 32 synthesis (§6), and then I address the crucial claim about apriorisynthesis (§§7–8). 33 34 35 2. The Prospect of an Enlightenment Epistemology 36 37 Kant’s conception of enlightenment is best known through his popular essay, 38 ‘What is Enlightenment?’.
Recommended publications
  • Leibniz on Consciousness and Self-Consciousness Rocco J
    Leibniz on Consciousness and Self-Consciousness Rocco J. Gennaro [Final version in NEW ESSAYS ON THE RATIONALISTS, Oxford U Press, 1999] In this paper I discuss the so-called "higher-order thought theory of consciousness" (the HOT theory) with special attention to how Leibnizian theses can help support it and how it can shed light on Leibniz's theory of perception, apperception, and consciousness. It will become clear how treating Leibniz as a HOT theorist can solve some of the problems he faced and some of the puzzles posed by commentators, e.g. animal mentality and the role of reason and memory in self-consciousness. I do not hold Leibniz's metaphysic of immaterial simple substances (i.e. monads), but even a contemporary materialist can learn a great deal from him. 1. What is the HOT Theory? In the absence of any plausible reductionist account of consciousness in nonmentalistic terms, the HOT theory says that the best explanation for what makes a mental state conscious is that it is accompanied by a thought (or awareness) that one is in that state.1 The sense of 'conscious state' I have in mind is the same as Nagel's sense, i.e. there is 'something it is like to be in that state' from a subjective or first-person point of view.2 Now, when the conscious mental state is a first-order world-directed state the HOT is not itself conscious; otherwise, circularity and an infinite regress would follow. Moreover, when the higher-order thought (HOT) is itself conscious, there is a yet higher-order (or third-order) thought directed at the second-order state.
    [Show full text]
  • Hermann Cohen's History and Philosophy of Science"
    "Hermann Cohen's History and Philosophy of Science" Lydia Patton Department of Philosophy McGill University, Montreal October, 2004 A thesis submitted to McGill University in partial fulfilment of the requirements of the degree ofPh.D. © Lydia Patton 2004 Library and Bibliothèque et 1+1 Archives Canada Archives Canada Published Heritage Direction du Branch Patrimoine de l'édition 395 Wellington Street 395, rue Wellington Ottawa ON K1A ON4 Ottawa ON K1A ON4 Canada Canada Your file Votre référence ISBN: 0-494-06335-1 Our file Notre référence ISBN: 0-494-06335-1 NOTICE: AVIS: The author has granted a non­ L'auteur a accordé une licence non exclusive exclusive license allowing Library permettant à la Bibliothèque et Archives and Archives Canada to reproduce, Canada de reproduire, publier, archiver, publish, archive, preserve, conserve, sauvegarder, conserver, transmettre au public communicate to the public by par télécommunication ou par l'Internet, prêter, telecommunication or on the Internet, distribuer et vendre des thèses partout dans loan, distribute and sell th es es le monde, à des fins commerciales ou autres, worldwide, for commercial or non­ sur support microforme, papier, électronique commercial purposes, in microform, et/ou autres formats. paper, electronic and/or any other formats. The author retains copyright L'auteur conserve la propriété du droit d'auteur ownership and moral rights in et des droits moraux qui protège cette thèse. this thesis. Neither the thesis Ni la thèse ni des extraits substantiels de nor substantial extracts from it celle-ci ne doivent être imprimés ou autrement may be printed or otherwise reproduits sans son autorisation.
    [Show full text]
  • Perception and Representation in Leibniz
    PERCEPTION AND REPRESENTATION IN LEIBNIZ by Stephen Montague Puryear B.S., Mechanical Engineering, North Carolina State University, 1994 M.A., Philosophy, Texas A&M University, 2000 M.A., Philosophy, University of Pittsburgh, 2004 Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of the Department of Philosophy in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy University of Pittsburgh 2006 UNIVERSITY OF PITTSBURGH DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY This dissertation was presented by Stephen Montague Puryear It was defended on December 5, 2005 and approved by Nicholas Rescher University Professor of Philosophy Robert B. Brandom Distinguished Service Professor of Philosophy Stephen Engstrom Associate Professor of Philosophy J. E. McGuire Professor of History and Philosophy of Science Dissertation Director: Nicholas Rescher University Professor of Philosophy ii Copyright °c by Stephen Montague Puryear 2006 iii PERCEPTION AND REPRESENTATION IN LEIBNIZ Stephen Montague Puryear, Ph.D. University of Pittsburgh, 2006 Though Leibniz’s views about perception and representation go to the heart of his philosophy, they have received surprisingly little attention over the years and in many ways continue to be poorly understood. I aim to redress these shortcomings. The body of the work begins with an exploration of Leibniz’s proposed analysis of representation (Chapter 2). Here I argue that on this analysis representation consists in a kind of structural correspondence— roughly an isomorphism—between representation and thing represented. Special attention is given to the application of this analysis to the challenging cases of linguistic and mental representation. The next two chapters concern what I take to be the central issue of the work: the nature of distinct perception.
    [Show full text]
  • Helmholtz's Physiological Psychology1
    Helmholtz’s Physiological Psychology1 Lydia Patton [email protected] In Philosophy of Mind in the Nineteenth Century, ed. S. Lapointe (Routledge, 2018) Author’s copy. Published version available at: https://www.routledge.com/Philosophy-of- Mind-in-the-Nineteenth-Century-The-History-of-the- Philosophy/Lapointe/p/book/9781138243965 Hermann von Helmholtz (1821-1894) contributed two major works to the theory of sensation and perception in the nineteenth century. The first edition of the The Doctrine of the Sensations of Tone was published in 1863, and the first edition of the Handbook of Physiological Optics was published in toto in 1867. These works established results both controversial and enduring: Helmholtz’s analysis of mixed colors and of combination tones, his arguments against nativism, and his commitment to analyzing sensation and perception using the techniques of natural science, especially physiology and physics. This study will focus on the Physiological Optics (hereafter PO), and on Helmholtz’s account of sensation, perception, and representation via “physiological psychology”. Helmholtz emphasized that external stimuli of sensations are causes, and sensations are their effects, and he had a practical and naturalist orientation toward the analysis of phenomenal experience. 1 Above all, I would like to thank Sandra Lapointe for her insight into the configuration and promise of this project, for conceiving of this volume, and for astute and perceptive responses to earlier versions, which shaped the project as it stands now. Clinton Tolley read the penultimate version of the paper and contributed invaluable suggestions, including preventing me from making a most consequential error of translation, for which I am grateful.
    [Show full text]
  • Immanuel Kant: Philosophy of Perception
    Roger Williams University DOCS@RWU Architecture, Art, and Historic Preservation Faculty Publications Architecture, Art, and Historic Preservation 2019 Immanuel Kant: Philosophy of Perception John S. Hendrix Roger Williams University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://docs.rwu.edu/saahp_fp Part of the Architectural History and Criticism Commons, and the Arts and Humanities Commons Recommended Citation Hendrix, John S., "Immanuel Kant: Philosophy of Perception" (2019). Architecture, Art, and Historic Preservation Faculty Publications. 41. https://docs.rwu.edu/saahp_fp/41 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Architecture, Art, and Historic Preservation at DOCS@RWU. It has been accepted for inclusion in Architecture, Art, and Historic Preservation Faculty Publications by an authorized administrator of DOCS@RWU. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Immanuel Kant: Philosophy of Perception John Shannon Hendrix In an early treatise, Attempt to Introduce the Concept of Negative Magni- tudes into Philosophy (Versuch, den Begriff der negative Grössen in die Weltweisheit einzuführen, 1763), Immanuel Kant developed a theory about thoughts that are fleeting, negated or cancelled, obscured or darkened. As certain thoughts become clearer, the other thoughts become less clear and more obscured (Verdunkelt). Kant’s concept was influenced by the petites perceptions of Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz. He invoked Leibniz in establish- ing that only a small portion of the representations which occur in the soul, as the result of sense perception, are clear and enduring.1 Gottfried Leibniz conceived of minute perceptions of objects or ideas which have too little intensity to effect conscious thought. The minute per- ceptions contribute to ordinary perceptions, but they are so small and there are so many of them that they pass unnoticed in the consciousness connected to perception.
    [Show full text]
  • Psychology Old and New
    University of Pennsylvania ScholarlyCommons IRCS Technical Reports Series Institute for Research in Cognitive Science 1-1-2001 Psychology Old and New Gary Hatfield University of Pennsylvania, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.upenn.edu/ircs_reports Part of the Psychology Commons Hatfield, Gary, "Psychology Old and New" (2001). IRCS Technical Reports Series. 23. https://repository.upenn.edu/ircs_reports/23 University of Pennsylvania Institute for Research in Cognitive Science Technical Report No. IRCS-01-07. This paper is posted at ScholarlyCommons. https://repository.upenn.edu/ircs_reports/23 For more information, please contact [email protected]. Psychology Old and New Abstract Psychology as the study of mind was an established subject matter throughout the nineteenth century in Britain, Germany, France, and the United States, taught in colleges and universities and made the subject of books and treatises. During the period 1870-1914 this existing discipline of psychology was being transformed into a new, experimental science, especially in Germany and the United States. The increase in experimentation changed the body of psychological writing, although there remained considerable continuity in theoretical content and non-experimental methodology between the old and new psychologies. This paper follows the emergence of the new psychology out of the old in the national traditions of Britain (primarily England), Germany, and the United States, with some reference to French, Belgian, Austrian, and Italian thinkers. The final section considers some methodological and philosophical issues in these literatures. Disciplines Psychology Comments University of Pennsylvania Institute for Research in Cognitive Science Technical Report No. IRCS-01-07.
    [Show full text]
  • How to Solve the Knowability Paradox with Transcendental Epistemology
    Synthese https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-1822-8 S.I.: THE CURRENT RELEVANCE OF KANT’S METHOD IN PHILOSOPHY How to solve the knowability paradox with transcendental epistemology Andrew Stephenson1 Received: 28 December 2017 / Accepted: 17 May 2018 © The Author(s) 2018 Abstract A novel solution to the knowability paradox is proposed based on Kant’s transcendental epistemology. The ‘paradox’ refers to a simple argument from the mod- erate claim that all truths are knowable to the extreme claim that all truths are known. It is significant because anti-realists have wanted to maintain knowability but reject omniscience. The core of the proposed solution is to concede realism about epistemic statements while maintaining anti-realism about non-epistemic statements. Transcen- dental epistemology supports such a view by providing for a sharp distinction between how we come to understand and apply epistemic versus non-epistemic concepts, the former through our capacity for a special kind of reflective self-knowledge Kant calls ‘transcendental apperception’. The proposal is a version of restriction strategy: it solves the paradox by restricting the anti-realist’s knowability principle. Restriction strate- gies have been a common response to the paradox but previous versions face serious difficulties: either they result in a knowability principle too weak to do the work anti- realists want it to, or they succumb to modified forms of the paradox, or they are ad hoc. It is argued that restricting knowability to non-epistemic statements by conceding realism about epistemic statements avoids all versions of the paradox, leaves enough for the anti-realist attack on classical logic, and, with the help of transcendental epis- temology, is principled in a way that remains compatible with a thoroughly anti-realist outlook.
    [Show full text]
  • Herbart's Philosophy of Pedagogy and Educational
    STUDIA EDUKACYJNE NR 33/2014 MIROSLAV SOMR University of South Bohemia in České Budějovice LENKA HRUŠKOVÁ The Institute of Technology and Business in České Budějovice HERBART’S PHILOSOPHY OF PEDAGOGY AND EDUCATIONAL TEACHING (THE VIEWS AND DIFFERENCES OF OPINION) ABSTRACT. Somr Miroslav, Hrušková Lenka, Herbart’s Philosophy of Pedagogy and Educational Teaching [Herbartowska filozofia pedagogiki i kształcenia]. Studia Edukacyjne nr 33, 2014, Poznań 2014, pp. 413-429. Adam Mickiewicz University Press. ISBN 978-83-232-2879-0. ISSN 1233-6688 Herbart’s scientific educational theory pointed to the fact that the application of pedagogical ideas in educational practices would brought a guaranteed outcome with a regular, mathematical precision. Herbart he was personally aware that this system contains the danger of formalism and unilateral intellectualism and therefore he endeavored, in theory, to overcome the concept of educational learning. This emphasis, however, was neglected by his pupils and followers. Key words: standardization, educational classes, awakening interest, philosophy of education, National Herbart Society Introduction History of Education probably doesn‘t know more contradictory evalua- tion of a philosophical and pedagogical thinker than of Johann Friedrich Herbart. 414 Miroslav Somr, Lenka Hrušková During his lifetime and after his death he was largely positive reviewed. He became a pedagogical theorist who, by his views, influenced educational theory and teaching practice across Europe and America."1 The causes of this response can be seen in the fact that his educational views reflected the social and economic conditions of the time. His call for expansion of elementary education to all strata of the population, and higher education for a relatively larger portion of the youth, was totally accepted.
    [Show full text]
  • GRE ® Psychology Test Practice Book (PDF)
    GRE ® Psychology Test Practice Book This practice book contains ◾ one actual, full-length GRE® Psychology Test ◾ test-taking strategies Become familiar with ◾ test structure and content ◾ test instructions and answering procedures Compare your practice test results with the performance of those who took the test at a GRE administration. www.ets.org/gre Table of Contents Overview ...............................................................................................................3 Test Content .........................................................................................................3 Preparing for the Test ...........................................................................................4 Test-Taking Strategies ..........................................................................................5 What Your Scores Mean .......................................................................................5 Taking the Practice Test .......................................................................................5 Scoring the Practice Test ......................................................................................6 Evaluating Your Performance ...............................................................................6 Practice Test ..........................................................................................................7 Worksheet for Scoring the Practice Test ............................................................43 Score Conversion Table .....................................................................................45
    [Show full text]
  • A Critical Account of the Philosophy of Lotze, the Doctrine of Thought
    3 1822 027054949 Is.:MjS*: ?'). '-.:'^" Br, :V, „:C'; .1'%; •; •) ."'V-A'" "^ / N ^ LIBRARY ^ UMVERSITY OF . SAN DIEGO , ^¥^,iru^^A<^C >^ . .Y- p.F AU FOR Nl A, SAN DIEGO UN ly E RSIT P ^ ^ Y , „, llill ililin III liliiii 111 3 1822 02705 4949 THE PHILOSOPHY OF LOTZE THE DOCTRINE OF THOUGHT PUBLISHtD BY JAMES MACLEHOSE AND SONS, GLASGOW, publishers to the elntbersit;). MACMILLAN AND CO., LONDON AND NEW YORK. London, • • • Simpkin, Hamilton and Co. Cambridge, • - J\Iacmiiian and Solves. Edinburgh, • • Dougias and Foulis. MDCCCXCV. A CRITICAL ACCOUNT OF THE PHILOSOPHY OF LOTZE THE DOCTRIXE OF THOUGHT BV HENRY JONES, M.A. PROFESSOR OK MORAL PHILOSOPHY ,1N THE UNIVERSITY OF GLASGOW AfTHOR OF "browning AS A PHILOSOPHICAL AND RELIGIOUS TEACHER GLASGOW JAMES MACLEHOSE AND SONS J3iiblishcrs to the clnitiErsitg 1895 All rights reserved IS DEDICATED BY ONE OF HIS PUPILS TO THE MEMORY OF ^ ©reat teacher JOHN NICHOL PREFACE In this volume I attempt to give a critical account of Lotze's exposition of the nature of thought. That exposition forms, for Lotze, a part of a larger undertaking. Before he could proceed to his main endeavour, and give a metaphysical account of the nature of Reality, it seemed to him necessary to clear the ground of false pretensions set up for thought, partly by the scientific men of his day but mainly by Hegel and his followers. For these writers, as he understood them, had identified thought with reality, and converted the rich and living world of concrete facts into a fixed system of abstract categories. Lotze, therefore, subjects thought to a most search- ing analysis, with a view of discovering what in reality is its nature and what, if any, are the limits of its powers.
    [Show full text]
  • A Reappraisal of Wilhelm Wundt
    A Reappraisal of Wilhelm Wundt ARTHUR L. BLUMENTHAL University of Massachusetts at Boston Approximately 100 years ago, in an era of intel- of Wundt are in need of serious correction, then lectual ferment, events of marked consequence took one might again ask whether Wundt still turns out place in the history of psychology. It was in the to be irrelevant and of little interest. This article decade of the 1870s that the first handbook of is addressed to that question, and its answers will, experimental psychology appeared, followed soon I suspect, contain some surprises for many readers. by the founding of the first formal laboratory of There is another question that immediately fol- experimental psychology. Both were the achieve- lows upon these claims. It is, How could such ments of Wilhelm Wundt, ever since recognized as historical misinterpretations have arisen? This is experimental psychology's great patron, though surely a fascinating question but one requiring later barred from any role that might remotely separate treatment. For the moment merely take resemble sainthood. Soon after the wave of "new" note that Wundtian anecdotes have long been psychologists spread out from Wundt's laboratory, passed down from author to author without worthy a series of intellectual revolutions largely erased recourse to original sources, and, also, that it is from memory the content of Wundtian psychologi- common in intellectual history for later schools of cal theory. thought to foster distortions and misinterpretations Now that the movement set in motion by Wundt of earlier ones—psychology, of course, offering has come through its first century, it would seem numerous opportunities.
    [Show full text]
  • The Epistemology of Immanuel Kant
    Western Washington University Western CEDAR WWU Honors Program Senior Projects WWU Graduate and Undergraduate Scholarship Spring 1982 The Epistemology of Immanuel Kant David Carl Bratz Western Washington University Follow this and additional works at: https://cedar.wwu.edu/wwu_honors Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Bratz, David Carl, "The Epistemology of Immanuel Kant" (1982). WWU Honors Program Senior Projects. 225. https://cedar.wwu.edu/wwu_honors/225 This Project is brought to you for free and open access by the WWU Graduate and Undergraduate Scholarship at Western CEDAR. It has been accepted for inclusion in WWU Honors Program Senior Projects by an authorized administrator of Western CEDAR. For more information, please contact [email protected]. The Epistemology of Immanuel Kant A Thesis Submitted to the Honors Program In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for Bachelor of Arts with Honors Department of Philosophy By David C. Bratz May 1982 The Epistemology of Immanuel Kant by David C. Bratz Accepted by The Honors Program of Western Washington University in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree Bachelor of Arts with Honors Honors Program Director & Thesis Advisor Table of Contents I. Introduction II. The Pure Intuitions: Space and Time III. The Pure Concepts of the Understanding IV. Connecting Concepts and Intuition: Schematism and Principles V. Conclusion Footnotes Bibliography "All men by nature desire knowledge." -- Aristotle, Metaphysics, bk. 1, ch. 1. It has been the tendency of philosophers in the Twentieth Century to examine the philosophy of Immanuel Kant in parcels, by analyzing key Kantian concepts, arguments, and distinctions without relation to the architectonic to v/hich they belong.
    [Show full text]