A Reappraisal of Wilhelm Wundt

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

A Reappraisal of Wilhelm Wundt A Reappraisal of Wilhelm Wundt ARTHUR L. BLUMENTHAL University of Massachusetts at Boston Approximately 100 years ago, in an era of intel- of Wundt are in need of serious correction, then lectual ferment, events of marked consequence took one might again ask whether Wundt still turns out place in the history of psychology. It was in the to be irrelevant and of little interest. This article decade of the 1870s that the first handbook of is addressed to that question, and its answers will, experimental psychology appeared, followed soon I suspect, contain some surprises for many readers. by the founding of the first formal laboratory of There is another question that immediately fol- experimental psychology. Both were the achieve- lows upon these claims. It is, How could such ments of Wilhelm Wundt, ever since recognized as historical misinterpretations have arisen? This is experimental psychology's great patron, though surely a fascinating question but one requiring later barred from any role that might remotely separate treatment. For the moment merely take resemble sainthood. Soon after the wave of "new" note that Wundtian anecdotes have long been psychologists spread out from Wundt's laboratory, passed down from author to author without worthy a series of intellectual revolutions largely erased recourse to original sources, and, also, that it is from memory the content of Wundtian psychologi- common in intellectual history for later schools of cal theory. thought to foster distortions and misinterpretations Now that the movement set in motion by Wundt of earlier ones—psychology, of course, offering has come through its first century, it would seem numerous opportunities. For now, let us examine fitting to mark the centenary by briefly turning the fundamentals of Wundt's psychology that have, back, reexamining psychology's historical founda- for better or worse, been disguised or lost in the tions, and paying homage to the founding father. course of history's machinations. There is, however, another reason for review, being less ceremonial and clearly more interesting. To Wundt's Method put it simply, the few current Wundt-scholars (and some do exist) are in fair agreement that Wundt The basic premise in Wundtian psychology is that as portrayed today in many texts and courses is the only certain reality is immediate experience. largely fictional and often bears little resemblance Proceeding from this premise, Wundt had accepted to the actual historical figure (cf. Blumenthal, the following goals for all science: the construction 1970; Bringmann, Balance, & Evans, 1975; of explanations of experience and the development Mischel, 1970). of techniques for objectifying experience. By the Naturally, it might be suspected that the above latter, he meant that the scientist attempts to com- radical statement is only the nit-picking of a few municate and reproduce his experiences in others in antiquarians obsessed with minor matters of in- standardized ways; thus it becomes possible to per- terpretation. But alas, such is not the case. These form tests that lead to public agreement about are claims about the very fundamentals of Wundt's phenomena and to agreement about their explana- work, often asserting the opposite of what has been tion. This was commonplace for Wundt and is a standard description prevailing over much of the found at the outset of many of his texts. past century. Yet, if popular historical accounts In the natural sciences, as Wundt continues, it is the attributes of experience derived from ex- ternal objects and energies that' are subjected to tests, explanations, and public agreement. But in This article is a revised and expanded version of a talk presented to the New York Academy of Sciences, New the case of psychology, it is the attributes of ex- York City, October 19, 1974. perience derived from the processes of the ex- Requests for reprints should be sent to Arthur L. periencing subject that are made the object of Blumenthal, 48 Kirkland Street, Cambridge, Massachusetts 02138. tests, explanations, and public agreement. These AMERICAN PSYCHOLOGIST • NOVEMBER 197S • 1081 psychological entities include experienced memory and replicable, in this case for the study of per- and perceptual capacities, fluctuations of attention ception, attention, memory, etc. To be sure, there or alertness, ranges of our sensitivities, etc. In were some disagreements, conflicting data, and un- the jargon of today, we would without hesitation supported speculations in those days, just as there say "human information-processing capacities." are today. Yet it is this subtle division between the physical Wundt's adherence to the canons of experimental and the psychological sciences that has led to in- procedure was so strict that, in fact, it sharply numerable textbook treatments of Wundt as a limited his use of experiments in psychology. Thus, mind-body dualist, and that is one of history's in the case of most "higher" mental processes such glaring distortions. For if you read Wundt, in as language or concept formation, he felt that true almost any of his texts, you will discover that his experiments were not feasible. Instead, these topics rejection of mind-body dualism is as emphatic a must, he argued, be studied through techniques of statement on the matter as you are likely ever to historical and naturalistic observation and also of encounter. He often said that psychology cannot logical analysis. This Wundt did by examining the be denned as the science of the mind because there social-cultural products of human mental activity, are no objects called "minds." that are distinct from making logical inferences about the underlying pro- objects called "bodies," a scenario that appears cesses. In the case of language, for example, he repeatedly in his works. went deeply into the technical study of linguistics Although physiologists and psychologists study (Blumenthal, 1970). So in these ways, a large one and the same organism, Wundt viewed them part of Wundt's psychological work is not experi- as analyzing and objectifying different experiences mental. derived from different vantage points. This is now usually called the "double-aspect" resolution of the Wundt's Theoretical System mind-body problem. And Wundt's use of the phrase "psychophysical parallelism" referred to But so far these are methodological matters and do this same view, though again it unfortunately led not speak to the essence of Wundt's psychological many later reviewers to the mind-body-dualism in- theory. What emerged as the paradigm psycho- terpretation. Rather, it referred to the separate logical phenomenon in his theoretical system would orientations of physiology and psychology where now be described as selective volitional attention. it is separate methodologies, in the sense of separate It is why he identified his psychology as "volun- types of observations, that here run in parallel. taristic" to distinguish it from other schools (see Another serious problem of misinterpretation especially Wundt, 1896b). He did not use the concerns Wundt and introspection. Contrary to label "structuralist" which was proffered and per- frequent descriptions, Wundt was not an intro- petuated by Titchener and James. spectionist as that term is popularly applied today. Mischel (1970) has recently surveyed Wundt's The thrust behind his entire experimental program writings, detailing Wundt's grounding in volitional- was the claim that progress in psychology had been motivational processes. Yet it was with apparent slow because of reliance on casual, unsystematic forceful impact on later historical interpretation introspection, which had led invariably to unre- that Titchener (1908) had given short shrift to solvable debates. In several books and mono- this theme, at the very heart of Wundtian psychol- graphs (in particular, 1888 and 1907) Wundt ogy, because of the overtones of continental idealist argued that armchair introspection could, in princi- philosophy in notions of volition. Titchener's ple, never succeed, being a logical impossibility as longest period of formal education came at Oxford, a scientific technique. The 1907 monograph was and not surprisingly he maintained certain biases a severe critique of the Wiirzburg psychologists for toward the British empiricist-sensationist tradition, their return to an earlier style of unverifiable in- even though that tradition was anathema to trospection. Wundt's views, and more than any other topic the Wundt promoted the cause of experimental brunt of Wundt's polemical writings. psychology more through accomplishments in his Without giving supportive citation, Boring laboratory than through polemics. From its out- (1950) states that Wundt had opposed the implica- set, the Wundtian program followed the general tion of an active volitional agent in psychology. conceptions of experimental science and the re- But now Mischel (1970) with extensive citation quirement that private experience be made public has shown, on the contrary, that volition-motivation 1082 • NOVEMBER 1975 • AMERICAN PSYCHOLOGIST is a central, primary theme in Wundt's psychology. of psychology, especially associationism. His reac- Briefly, that theme runs as follows: To explain a tions against associationism were directed mostly volitional act on the basis of its motives is different at the form it had assumed in mid-19th-century from the explanation of occurrences in the physical Germany in Herbart's psychology. sciences, and "volitional activities are the type in Herbart, you may recall, had atomized mental terms of which all other psychological phenomena processes into elemental ideas that became asso- are to be construed" (Wundt, 1908, Vol. 3, p. 162). ciated into compounds according to classical asso- Wundt's studies of volition, in turn, amounted ciationist descriptions. Wundt considered that ap- to an elaborate analysis of selective and construc- proach to be a mere primitive analogy to systems tive attentional processes (often summarized under of physical mechanics, and he argued at length that the term apperception), which he localized in the those systems teach little about the interrelations brain's frontal lobes.
Recommended publications
  • Leibniz on Consciousness and Self-Consciousness Rocco J
    Leibniz on Consciousness and Self-Consciousness Rocco J. Gennaro [Final version in NEW ESSAYS ON THE RATIONALISTS, Oxford U Press, 1999] In this paper I discuss the so-called "higher-order thought theory of consciousness" (the HOT theory) with special attention to how Leibnizian theses can help support it and how it can shed light on Leibniz's theory of perception, apperception, and consciousness. It will become clear how treating Leibniz as a HOT theorist can solve some of the problems he faced and some of the puzzles posed by commentators, e.g. animal mentality and the role of reason and memory in self-consciousness. I do not hold Leibniz's metaphysic of immaterial simple substances (i.e. monads), but even a contemporary materialist can learn a great deal from him. 1. What is the HOT Theory? In the absence of any plausible reductionist account of consciousness in nonmentalistic terms, the HOT theory says that the best explanation for what makes a mental state conscious is that it is accompanied by a thought (or awareness) that one is in that state.1 The sense of 'conscious state' I have in mind is the same as Nagel's sense, i.e. there is 'something it is like to be in that state' from a subjective or first-person point of view.2 Now, when the conscious mental state is a first-order world-directed state the HOT is not itself conscious; otherwise, circularity and an infinite regress would follow. Moreover, when the higher-order thought (HOT) is itself conscious, there is a yet higher-order (or third-order) thought directed at the second-order state.
    [Show full text]
  • Hermann Cohen's History and Philosophy of Science"
    "Hermann Cohen's History and Philosophy of Science" Lydia Patton Department of Philosophy McGill University, Montreal October, 2004 A thesis submitted to McGill University in partial fulfilment of the requirements of the degree ofPh.D. © Lydia Patton 2004 Library and Bibliothèque et 1+1 Archives Canada Archives Canada Published Heritage Direction du Branch Patrimoine de l'édition 395 Wellington Street 395, rue Wellington Ottawa ON K1A ON4 Ottawa ON K1A ON4 Canada Canada Your file Votre référence ISBN: 0-494-06335-1 Our file Notre référence ISBN: 0-494-06335-1 NOTICE: AVIS: The author has granted a non­ L'auteur a accordé une licence non exclusive exclusive license allowing Library permettant à la Bibliothèque et Archives and Archives Canada to reproduce, Canada de reproduire, publier, archiver, publish, archive, preserve, conserve, sauvegarder, conserver, transmettre au public communicate to the public by par télécommunication ou par l'Internet, prêter, telecommunication or on the Internet, distribuer et vendre des thèses partout dans loan, distribute and sell th es es le monde, à des fins commerciales ou autres, worldwide, for commercial or non­ sur support microforme, papier, électronique commercial purposes, in microform, et/ou autres formats. paper, electronic and/or any other formats. The author retains copyright L'auteur conserve la propriété du droit d'auteur ownership and moral rights in et des droits moraux qui protège cette thèse. this thesis. Neither the thesis Ni la thèse ni des extraits substantiels de nor substantial extracts from it celle-ci ne doivent être imprimés ou autrement may be printed or otherwise reproduits sans son autorisation.
    [Show full text]
  • Perception and Representation in Leibniz
    PERCEPTION AND REPRESENTATION IN LEIBNIZ by Stephen Montague Puryear B.S., Mechanical Engineering, North Carolina State University, 1994 M.A., Philosophy, Texas A&M University, 2000 M.A., Philosophy, University of Pittsburgh, 2004 Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of the Department of Philosophy in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy University of Pittsburgh 2006 UNIVERSITY OF PITTSBURGH DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY This dissertation was presented by Stephen Montague Puryear It was defended on December 5, 2005 and approved by Nicholas Rescher University Professor of Philosophy Robert B. Brandom Distinguished Service Professor of Philosophy Stephen Engstrom Associate Professor of Philosophy J. E. McGuire Professor of History and Philosophy of Science Dissertation Director: Nicholas Rescher University Professor of Philosophy ii Copyright °c by Stephen Montague Puryear 2006 iii PERCEPTION AND REPRESENTATION IN LEIBNIZ Stephen Montague Puryear, Ph.D. University of Pittsburgh, 2006 Though Leibniz’s views about perception and representation go to the heart of his philosophy, they have received surprisingly little attention over the years and in many ways continue to be poorly understood. I aim to redress these shortcomings. The body of the work begins with an exploration of Leibniz’s proposed analysis of representation (Chapter 2). Here I argue that on this analysis representation consists in a kind of structural correspondence— roughly an isomorphism—between representation and thing represented. Special attention is given to the application of this analysis to the challenging cases of linguistic and mental representation. The next two chapters concern what I take to be the central issue of the work: the nature of distinct perception.
    [Show full text]
  • Helmholtz's Physiological Psychology1
    Helmholtz’s Physiological Psychology1 Lydia Patton [email protected] In Philosophy of Mind in the Nineteenth Century, ed. S. Lapointe (Routledge, 2018) Author’s copy. Published version available at: https://www.routledge.com/Philosophy-of- Mind-in-the-Nineteenth-Century-The-History-of-the- Philosophy/Lapointe/p/book/9781138243965 Hermann von Helmholtz (1821-1894) contributed two major works to the theory of sensation and perception in the nineteenth century. The first edition of the The Doctrine of the Sensations of Tone was published in 1863, and the first edition of the Handbook of Physiological Optics was published in toto in 1867. These works established results both controversial and enduring: Helmholtz’s analysis of mixed colors and of combination tones, his arguments against nativism, and his commitment to analyzing sensation and perception using the techniques of natural science, especially physiology and physics. This study will focus on the Physiological Optics (hereafter PO), and on Helmholtz’s account of sensation, perception, and representation via “physiological psychology”. Helmholtz emphasized that external stimuli of sensations are causes, and sensations are their effects, and he had a practical and naturalist orientation toward the analysis of phenomenal experience. 1 Above all, I would like to thank Sandra Lapointe for her insight into the configuration and promise of this project, for conceiving of this volume, and for astute and perceptive responses to earlier versions, which shaped the project as it stands now. Clinton Tolley read the penultimate version of the paper and contributed invaluable suggestions, including preventing me from making a most consequential error of translation, for which I am grateful.
    [Show full text]
  • Immanuel Kant: Philosophy of Perception
    Roger Williams University DOCS@RWU Architecture, Art, and Historic Preservation Faculty Publications Architecture, Art, and Historic Preservation 2019 Immanuel Kant: Philosophy of Perception John S. Hendrix Roger Williams University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://docs.rwu.edu/saahp_fp Part of the Architectural History and Criticism Commons, and the Arts and Humanities Commons Recommended Citation Hendrix, John S., "Immanuel Kant: Philosophy of Perception" (2019). Architecture, Art, and Historic Preservation Faculty Publications. 41. https://docs.rwu.edu/saahp_fp/41 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Architecture, Art, and Historic Preservation at DOCS@RWU. It has been accepted for inclusion in Architecture, Art, and Historic Preservation Faculty Publications by an authorized administrator of DOCS@RWU. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Immanuel Kant: Philosophy of Perception John Shannon Hendrix In an early treatise, Attempt to Introduce the Concept of Negative Magni- tudes into Philosophy (Versuch, den Begriff der negative Grössen in die Weltweisheit einzuführen, 1763), Immanuel Kant developed a theory about thoughts that are fleeting, negated or cancelled, obscured or darkened. As certain thoughts become clearer, the other thoughts become less clear and more obscured (Verdunkelt). Kant’s concept was influenced by the petites perceptions of Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz. He invoked Leibniz in establish- ing that only a small portion of the representations which occur in the soul, as the result of sense perception, are clear and enduring.1 Gottfried Leibniz conceived of minute perceptions of objects or ideas which have too little intensity to effect conscious thought. The minute per- ceptions contribute to ordinary perceptions, but they are so small and there are so many of them that they pass unnoticed in the consciousness connected to perception.
    [Show full text]
  • Psychology Old and New
    University of Pennsylvania ScholarlyCommons IRCS Technical Reports Series Institute for Research in Cognitive Science 1-1-2001 Psychology Old and New Gary Hatfield University of Pennsylvania, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.upenn.edu/ircs_reports Part of the Psychology Commons Hatfield, Gary, "Psychology Old and New" (2001). IRCS Technical Reports Series. 23. https://repository.upenn.edu/ircs_reports/23 University of Pennsylvania Institute for Research in Cognitive Science Technical Report No. IRCS-01-07. This paper is posted at ScholarlyCommons. https://repository.upenn.edu/ircs_reports/23 For more information, please contact [email protected]. Psychology Old and New Abstract Psychology as the study of mind was an established subject matter throughout the nineteenth century in Britain, Germany, France, and the United States, taught in colleges and universities and made the subject of books and treatises. During the period 1870-1914 this existing discipline of psychology was being transformed into a new, experimental science, especially in Germany and the United States. The increase in experimentation changed the body of psychological writing, although there remained considerable continuity in theoretical content and non-experimental methodology between the old and new psychologies. This paper follows the emergence of the new psychology out of the old in the national traditions of Britain (primarily England), Germany, and the United States, with some reference to French, Belgian, Austrian, and Italian thinkers. The final section considers some methodological and philosophical issues in these literatures. Disciplines Psychology Comments University of Pennsylvania Institute for Research in Cognitive Science Technical Report No. IRCS-01-07.
    [Show full text]
  • How to Solve the Knowability Paradox with Transcendental Epistemology
    Synthese https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-1822-8 S.I.: THE CURRENT RELEVANCE OF KANT’S METHOD IN PHILOSOPHY How to solve the knowability paradox with transcendental epistemology Andrew Stephenson1 Received: 28 December 2017 / Accepted: 17 May 2018 © The Author(s) 2018 Abstract A novel solution to the knowability paradox is proposed based on Kant’s transcendental epistemology. The ‘paradox’ refers to a simple argument from the mod- erate claim that all truths are knowable to the extreme claim that all truths are known. It is significant because anti-realists have wanted to maintain knowability but reject omniscience. The core of the proposed solution is to concede realism about epistemic statements while maintaining anti-realism about non-epistemic statements. Transcen- dental epistemology supports such a view by providing for a sharp distinction between how we come to understand and apply epistemic versus non-epistemic concepts, the former through our capacity for a special kind of reflective self-knowledge Kant calls ‘transcendental apperception’. The proposal is a version of restriction strategy: it solves the paradox by restricting the anti-realist’s knowability principle. Restriction strate- gies have been a common response to the paradox but previous versions face serious difficulties: either they result in a knowability principle too weak to do the work anti- realists want it to, or they succumb to modified forms of the paradox, or they are ad hoc. It is argued that restricting knowability to non-epistemic statements by conceding realism about epistemic statements avoids all versions of the paradox, leaves enough for the anti-realist attack on classical logic, and, with the help of transcendental epis- temology, is principled in a way that remains compatible with a thoroughly anti-realist outlook.
    [Show full text]
  • Herbart's Philosophy of Pedagogy and Educational
    STUDIA EDUKACYJNE NR 33/2014 MIROSLAV SOMR University of South Bohemia in České Budějovice LENKA HRUŠKOVÁ The Institute of Technology and Business in České Budějovice HERBART’S PHILOSOPHY OF PEDAGOGY AND EDUCATIONAL TEACHING (THE VIEWS AND DIFFERENCES OF OPINION) ABSTRACT. Somr Miroslav, Hrušková Lenka, Herbart’s Philosophy of Pedagogy and Educational Teaching [Herbartowska filozofia pedagogiki i kształcenia]. Studia Edukacyjne nr 33, 2014, Poznań 2014, pp. 413-429. Adam Mickiewicz University Press. ISBN 978-83-232-2879-0. ISSN 1233-6688 Herbart’s scientific educational theory pointed to the fact that the application of pedagogical ideas in educational practices would brought a guaranteed outcome with a regular, mathematical precision. Herbart he was personally aware that this system contains the danger of formalism and unilateral intellectualism and therefore he endeavored, in theory, to overcome the concept of educational learning. This emphasis, however, was neglected by his pupils and followers. Key words: standardization, educational classes, awakening interest, philosophy of education, National Herbart Society Introduction History of Education probably doesn‘t know more contradictory evalua- tion of a philosophical and pedagogical thinker than of Johann Friedrich Herbart. 414 Miroslav Somr, Lenka Hrušková During his lifetime and after his death he was largely positive reviewed. He became a pedagogical theorist who, by his views, influenced educational theory and teaching practice across Europe and America."1 The causes of this response can be seen in the fact that his educational views reflected the social and economic conditions of the time. His call for expansion of elementary education to all strata of the population, and higher education for a relatively larger portion of the youth, was totally accepted.
    [Show full text]
  • GRE ® Psychology Test Practice Book (PDF)
    GRE ® Psychology Test Practice Book This practice book contains ◾ one actual, full-length GRE® Psychology Test ◾ test-taking strategies Become familiar with ◾ test structure and content ◾ test instructions and answering procedures Compare your practice test results with the performance of those who took the test at a GRE administration. www.ets.org/gre Table of Contents Overview ...............................................................................................................3 Test Content .........................................................................................................3 Preparing for the Test ...........................................................................................4 Test-Taking Strategies ..........................................................................................5 What Your Scores Mean .......................................................................................5 Taking the Practice Test .......................................................................................5 Scoring the Practice Test ......................................................................................6 Evaluating Your Performance ...............................................................................6 Practice Test ..........................................................................................................7 Worksheet for Scoring the Practice Test ............................................................43 Score Conversion Table .....................................................................................45
    [Show full text]
  • A Critical Account of the Philosophy of Lotze, the Doctrine of Thought
    3 1822 027054949 Is.:MjS*: ?'). '-.:'^" Br, :V, „:C'; .1'%; •; •) ."'V-A'" "^ / N ^ LIBRARY ^ UMVERSITY OF . SAN DIEGO , ^¥^,iru^^A<^C >^ . .Y- p.F AU FOR Nl A, SAN DIEGO UN ly E RSIT P ^ ^ Y , „, llill ililin III liliiii 111 3 1822 02705 4949 THE PHILOSOPHY OF LOTZE THE DOCTRINE OF THOUGHT PUBLISHtD BY JAMES MACLEHOSE AND SONS, GLASGOW, publishers to the elntbersit;). MACMILLAN AND CO., LONDON AND NEW YORK. London, • • • Simpkin, Hamilton and Co. Cambridge, • - J\Iacmiiian and Solves. Edinburgh, • • Dougias and Foulis. MDCCCXCV. A CRITICAL ACCOUNT OF THE PHILOSOPHY OF LOTZE THE DOCTRIXE OF THOUGHT BV HENRY JONES, M.A. PROFESSOR OK MORAL PHILOSOPHY ,1N THE UNIVERSITY OF GLASGOW AfTHOR OF "browning AS A PHILOSOPHICAL AND RELIGIOUS TEACHER GLASGOW JAMES MACLEHOSE AND SONS J3iiblishcrs to the clnitiErsitg 1895 All rights reserved IS DEDICATED BY ONE OF HIS PUPILS TO THE MEMORY OF ^ ©reat teacher JOHN NICHOL PREFACE In this volume I attempt to give a critical account of Lotze's exposition of the nature of thought. That exposition forms, for Lotze, a part of a larger undertaking. Before he could proceed to his main endeavour, and give a metaphysical account of the nature of Reality, it seemed to him necessary to clear the ground of false pretensions set up for thought, partly by the scientific men of his day but mainly by Hegel and his followers. For these writers, as he understood them, had identified thought with reality, and converted the rich and living world of concrete facts into a fixed system of abstract categories. Lotze, therefore, subjects thought to a most search- ing analysis, with a view of discovering what in reality is its nature and what, if any, are the limits of its powers.
    [Show full text]
  • The Epistemology of Immanuel Kant
    Western Washington University Western CEDAR WWU Honors Program Senior Projects WWU Graduate and Undergraduate Scholarship Spring 1982 The Epistemology of Immanuel Kant David Carl Bratz Western Washington University Follow this and additional works at: https://cedar.wwu.edu/wwu_honors Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Bratz, David Carl, "The Epistemology of Immanuel Kant" (1982). WWU Honors Program Senior Projects. 225. https://cedar.wwu.edu/wwu_honors/225 This Project is brought to you for free and open access by the WWU Graduate and Undergraduate Scholarship at Western CEDAR. It has been accepted for inclusion in WWU Honors Program Senior Projects by an authorized administrator of Western CEDAR. For more information, please contact [email protected]. The Epistemology of Immanuel Kant A Thesis Submitted to the Honors Program In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for Bachelor of Arts with Honors Department of Philosophy By David C. Bratz May 1982 The Epistemology of Immanuel Kant by David C. Bratz Accepted by The Honors Program of Western Washington University in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree Bachelor of Arts with Honors Honors Program Director & Thesis Advisor Table of Contents I. Introduction II. The Pure Intuitions: Space and Time III. The Pure Concepts of the Understanding IV. Connecting Concepts and Intuition: Schematism and Principles V. Conclusion Footnotes Bibliography "All men by nature desire knowledge." -- Aristotle, Metaphysics, bk. 1, ch. 1. It has been the tendency of philosophers in the Twentieth Century to examine the philosophy of Immanuel Kant in parcels, by analyzing key Kantian concepts, arguments, and distinctions without relation to the architectonic to v/hich they belong.
    [Show full text]
  • Transcendental Apperception in the Critique of Pure Reason: Influence of Previous Philosophical Writings and Their Inherited Reapplication
    TRANSCENDENTAL APPERCEPTION IN THE CRITIQUE OF PURE REASON: INFLUENCE OF PREVIOUS PHILOSOPHICAL WRITINGS AND THEIR INHERITED REAPPLICATION APERCEPÇÃO TRANSCENDENTAL NA CRÍTICA DA RAZÃO PURA: INFLUÊNCIA DOS ESCRITOS FILOSÓFICOS ANTERIORES E A REAPLICAÇÃO DE SUA HERENÇA Thomas Matiolli Machado* Recebido: 06/2016 Aprovado: 10/2016 Abstract: In the Critique of Pure Reason, Kant developed new perspectives on apperception never before contemplated in the history of philosophy. However, not everything that the author of the first Critique wrote was entirely original. Indeed, Kant reapplied much that he had learned from historical philosophy, by which he was deeply influenced, creating innovative new approaches to apperception. This article aims to explain how Kant learned from the philosophers of the past in order to develop the concept of transcendental apperception in the Critique of Pure Reason. Keywords: Critique of Pure Reason, Transcendental apperception, Abidance, Spontaneity. Resumo: Na Crítica da razão pura, Kant desenvolveu novas perspectivas sobre a apercepção nunca contempladas antes na história da filosofia. Mas, nem tudo o que o autor da primeira Crítica escreveu possui raízes originais. Kant reaplicou muito do que aprendeu com o passado histórico-filosófico, pelo qual foi profundamente influenciado, de um modo inovador criando novas abordagens sobre a apercepção. Este artigo tem por objetivo esclarecer como Kant aprendeu com os filósofos do passado para desenvolver o conceito de apercepção transcendental na Crítica da razão pura. Palavras-chave: Crítica da razão pura, Apercepção transcendental, Permanência, Espontaneidade. INTRODUCTION The Critique of Pure Reason1 is considered one of the most important and difficult works of western philosophical literature. Although Kant’s writing style might be laborious, it is usually accepted that the concepts and ideas behind his words are very clear.
    [Show full text]