University of Birmingham a Powerful New Anomalous Monism

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

University of Birmingham a Powerful New Anomalous Monism View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by University of Birmingham Research Portal University of Birmingham A powerful new Anomalous Monism Taylor, John License: Other (please specify with Rights Statement) Document Version Peer reviewed version Citation for published version (Harvard): Taylor, J 2018, A powerful new Anomalous Monism. in M Guta (ed.), Consciousness and the Ontology of Properties. 1st edn, Routledge, New York, pp. 39-52. Link to publication on Research at Birmingham portal Publisher Rights Statement: Checked for eligibility 15/06/2018 This is an Accepted Manuscript of a book chapter published by Routledge/CRC Press in Consciousness and the Ontology of Properties on 19/07/2018, available online: https://www.routledge.com/Consciousness-and-the-Ontology-of-Properties/Guta/p/book/9781138097865 General rights Unless a licence is specified above, all rights (including copyright and moral rights) in this document are retained by the authors and/or the copyright holders. The express permission of the copyright holder must be obtained for any use of this material other than for purposes permitted by law. •Users may freely distribute the URL that is used to identify this publication. •Users may download and/or print one copy of the publication from the University of Birmingham research portal for the purpose of private study or non-commercial research. •User may use extracts from the document in line with the concept of ‘fair dealing’ under the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988 (?) •Users may not further distribute the material nor use it for the purposes of commercial gain. Where a licence is displayed above, please note the terms and conditions of the licence govern your use of this document. When citing, please reference the published version. Take down policy While the University of Birmingham exercises care and attention in making items available there are rare occasions when an item has been uploaded in error or has been deemed to be commercially or otherwise sensitive. If you believe that this is the case for this document, please contact [email protected] providing details and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate. Download date: 01. Mar. 2020 Henry Taylor A Powerful New Anomalous Monism Henry Taylor This is a draft of a paper that is forthcoming in M. Guta (ed.) The Ontology of Consciousness. (Routledge). Please cite from published version. Abstract I distinguish between two broadly different interpretations of anomalous monism. I then pose problems for both. I argue that one interpretation leads to well known problems concerning epiphenomenalism, whilst the other interpretation is implausible because it fails to give a good account of the role of properties in causation. I then develop a new version of anomalous monism, which can avoid both of these issues. This view draws heavily on the metaphysics of dispositions, as well as work on causation. I conclude that anomalous monism is deserving of a reappraisal. Keywords: Anomalous monism, Properties, Epiphenomenalism, Laws. 1. What is Anomalous monism? Anomalous monism was famously put forward by Donald Davidson (1970a). Three claims lie at its core (Davidson 1970a: 105-106): i) The Principle of Causal Interaction: at least some mental events interact causally with physical events. ii) The Nomological Character of Causality: where there is causality, there must be a law. That is to say, events related as cause and effect fall under strict deterministic laws. iii) The Anomalism of the Mental: there are no strict deterministic laws on the basis of which mental events can be predicted and explained. I will not primarily be concerned with providing motivation for these claims. This is not to say that the motivations for them are unimportant or that the claims are 1 Henry Taylor uncontentious. For example, Davidson describes claim (iii) as ‘true and worth arguing for’ (1993: 3), though many have thought that it is neither true, nor worth arguing for (Crane and Mellor 1990: 196). (i) and (ii) are also controversial: most would accept (i), though its acceptance is by no means universal (Jackson 1982) and some do not believe in laws at all, and so would presumably reject (ii) (Mumford 2004: ch.9, van Frassen 1989). So, it is an important and substantial question whether we should accept (i-iii). Nonetheless, it is not a question that will be considered in this paper. Rather, I am primarily interested in whether there is a view of the mind that can reconcile these claims, rather than with providing the background reasons one might have to accept them.1 Though the motivations for these claims will not be directly addressed, it is worth noting that this paper is still of interest to those unconvinced by (i-iii). This is because once these claims are correctly fleshed out, they turn out to be more anodyne than perhaps they initially appear. This, in turn, may alleviate resistance to them. It is also worth emphasising that anomalous monists may accept weakened versions of these claims. For example, few contemporary thinkers would accept that causes and effects must fall under deterministic laws, as (ii) asserts. However, a view that denies that laws are deterministic, but otherwise accepts (ii) and a suitably modified version of (iii), would clearly still deserve the name ‘anomalous monism’. This paper is not concerned with discussing these minor modifications of claims (i- iii), so I will leave them as they are in what follows. 1 My approach is similar in this way to Davidson’s own, though he does give some reasons to accept (iii), which is the most contentious of the claims (1970a: 118-119). 2 Henry Taylor Davidson’s view has been interpreted in various importantly different ways. In section 2, I divide these interpretations into two broad kinds, which I call the ‘property dualist’ and the ‘nominalist’ interpretations. I outline one objection to each interpretation, and argue that a third version of anomalous monism is required. I develop one in sections 3-5, arguing that this version can avoid both of the problems associated with the other two interpretations. I conclude that this is the best version of anomalous monism. In section 6, I discuss the relation of this view to mind-brain identity theory and in section 7, I discuss what impact the view has on the ontology of events. In this paper, I will take anomalous monism to be any view of the mind that embraces (i-iii), or perhaps some minor modifications of these claims. So, as I use the term, we need not accept all of the claims that Davidson himself accepted in order to be anomalous monists: to be an anomalous monist we just need to preserve the three core claims. Relatedly, I should be clear that I certainly do not claim that the version of anomalous monism that I develop is what Davidson actually had in mind. On the contrary, for reasons that will become clear, I think this is not the case. So, I do not claim that Davidson would be happy with the view, just that it is the most plausible view of the mind that reconciles (i-iii). It may be asked why readers should care about anomalous monism. After all, the view has largely fallen out of favour in the contemporary debate, and is rarely discussed in the metaphysics of mind these days. In response to this, I say that we should examine the strongest version of a position before we dismiss it. It is my contention that the strongest version of anomalous monism has yet to be supplied. The view argued for in this paper can avoid the objections that have been thought by 3 Henry Taylor many to be fatal for anomalous monism. Therefore, if what I say in this paper is correct, then the current unpopularity of anomalous monism is unjustified, and the view is deserving of a reappraisal. 2. Two interpretations, two objections. I divide interpretations of anomalous monism into two broad classes. These classes are distinguished by how they interpret the word ‘property’. Sometimes, ‘property’ is used in a realist sense, to refer to a real constituent of the world, which exists independently of the way we describe it. For example, plausibly the charge of a particular electron is a feature of the electron, which would exist even if humans did not exist, and could not describe it, and is distinct from all of its other properties such as its mass. On this meaning, to say that an object has a property is metaphysically heavyweight: it means that it has some objective, real feature. Conversely, sometimes ‘property’ is used in a less heavyweight sense, where properties are more closely allied with concepts, or predicates, or descriptions. On this use, to say that an object has a certain property just means that a certain predicate (description/concept) applies truly to it, but this does not imply that there must be one single unique property (in the heavyweight sense) that the object has in virtue of which that predicate applies to it. 2 For example, it is certainly true to say of me that I am ‘not the Eiffel Tower’. In the lightweight sense, then, I have the property of being not the Eiffel Tower (because it is true to say of me that I am not the Eiffel Tower). In the more heavyweight sense, though, I do not have a single property of being not the Eiffel 2 This distinction in the way that ‘property’ is used will be familiar to metaphysicians, e.g. Mellor (1991) and Heil (2003: 22-30). 4 Henry Taylor Tower.
Recommended publications
  • Andrew Wong Washington University, St. Louis the Aim of This Paper Is to Support Donald Davidson's Anomalous Monism1 As An
    do E s An o m A l o u s mo n i s m hA v E proper construal of Davidson’s principle Ex p l A n A t o r y fo r ce ? of rationality will show the objection to be misguided. Andrew Wong Washington University, St. Louis “Mental Events” reconciles the paradox which arises from three principles Davidson held ex hypothesi: (1) Mental events interact causally with physical events (Principle of Causal Interaction), (2) Where there is causality, there must be a law (Principle of the Nomological The aim of this paper is to support Donald Character of Causality), and (3) There are no 1 strict deterministic laws on the basis of which Davidson’s Anomalous Monism as an account mental events can be predicted and explained of law-governed mental causation in a world (Principle of the Anomalism of the Mental).4 unfettered by psychophysical laws. To this end, I will attempt to answer one principal objection Tension is apparent in that some mental to the theory: the claim that Anomalous events must interact causally with physical events Monism lacks sufficient “explanatory force.”2 and thereby feature in laws, and that this is an Though not quite the standard objection, I explicit contradiction of the Principle of the believe it to be the most formidable, and hence Anomalism of the Mental. Accepting three the most crucial to address.3 The argument’s further principles, in addition to the three strength is that it need not dispute Davidson’s above, will resolve the tension: (4) Each mental assumptions.
    [Show full text]
  • Minds and Machines Anomalous Monism, Contd
    Minds and Machines spring 2003 Anomalous monism, contd. 1 24.119 spring 03 “Mental events” • a defense of “anomalous monism” • like Dennett, Davidson is a materialist (hence, “monism”, as opposed to “dualism”) • like Dennett, Davidson gives a nonreductive account of the mental (hence, “anomalous” monism) Donald Davidson 2 24.119 spring 03 three principles • causal interaction “every mental event is the cause or effect of some physical event” • the nomological character of causality if c causes e, then there is a (strict) law of the form “A-type events are followed by B- type events”, where c is of type-A, and e is of type-B • the anomalism of the mental there are no strict laws on the basis of which mental events can be predicted and 3 explained 24.119 spring 03 anomalous monism • the token identity theory “Every mental event…is a physical event” (see the “demonstration of identity” on p. 124) and: • the anomalism of the mental there are no strict laws on the basis of which mental events can be predicted and explained 4 24.119 spring 03 lawlike statements • lawlike statements “general statements that support counterfactual and subjunctive claims, and [that] are supported by their instances” e.g., ‘all swans are white’; evidence for this is also evidence for the “counterfactual conditional” ‘if this had been a swan, it would have been white’ (cf. ‘if this dime had been in my pocket, it would have been a quarter’) • ceteris paribus lawlike statements lawlike statements “qualified by generous escape clauses”—‘in normal conditions’, ‘other things being equal’, etc.
    [Show full text]
  • The Causal Efficacy of Consciousness
    entropy Article The Causal Efficacy of Consciousness Matthew Owen 1,2 1 Yakima Valley College, Yakima, WA 98902, USA; [email protected] 2 Center for Consciousness Science, University of Michigan Medical School, Ann Arbor, MI 48109, USA Received: 10 June 2020; Accepted: 17 July 2020; Published: 28 July 2020 Abstract: Mental causation is vitally important to the integrated information theory (IIT), which says consciousness exists since it is causally efficacious. While it might not be directly apparent, metaphysical commitments have consequential entailments concerning the causal efficacy of consciousness. Commitments regarding the ontology of consciousness and the nature of causation determine which problem(s) a view of consciousness faces with respect to mental causation. Analysis of mental causation in contemporary philosophy of mind has brought several problems to the fore: the alleged lack of psychophysical laws, the causal exclusion problem, and the causal pairing problem. This article surveys the threat each problem poses to IIT based on the different metaphysical commitments IIT theorists might make. Distinctions are made between what I call reductive IIT, non-reductive IIT, and non-physicalist IIT, each of which make differing metaphysical commitments regarding the ontology of consciousness and nature of causation. Subsequently, each problem pertaining to mental causation is presented and its threat, or lack thereof, to each version of IIT is considered. While the lack of psychophysical laws appears unthreatening for all versions, reductive IIT and non-reductive IIT are seriously threatened by the exclusion problem, and it is difficult to see how they could overcome it while maintaining a commitment to the causal closure principle.
    [Show full text]
  • Misunderstanding Davidson by Martin Clifford Rule
    MISUNDERSTANDING DAVIDSON BY MARTIN CLIFFORD RULE Submitted to the graduate degree program in Philosophy and the Graduate Faculty of the University of Kansas in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. _________________________________ Chairperson Dr. John Bricke, Professor of Philosophy Emeritus. _________________________________ Ben Eggleston, Professor. _________________________________ Eileen Nutting, Assistant Professor. _________________________________ Clifton L. Pye, Associate Professor. _________________________________ John Symons, Professor. Date Defended: 07/12/2016 ii The Dissertation Committee for Martin Clifford Rule Certifies that this is the approved version of the following dissertation: MISUNDERSTANDING DAVIDSON ________________________________ Chairperson Dr. John Bricke, Professor of Philosophy Emeritus. Date approved: 07/12/2016 iii ABSTRACT The main aim of this dissertation is to offer, and to defend, an interpretation of Donald Davidson’s classic paper “Mental Events” which interpretation I take to be identical to Davidson’s intended interpretation. My contention is that many readers misunderstand this paper. My method for showing this will be, first, to give a brief summary of the surface structure, and the core concepts, of “Mental Events”. I will then begin to canvas exemplars of the main lines of (alleged) objection to what “Mental Events” has been supposed to contend. I intend to argue that these objections misunderstand either Davidson’s conclusions, or his arguments, or they require material additional to the position that Davidson actually lays out and argues for in “Mental Events” in order to follow. In the latter case I shall attempt to show that these additions are not contentions which Davidson shares by referencing further materials from Davidson’s work.
    [Show full text]
  • University of Birmingham a Powerful New Anomalous Monism
    University of Birmingham A powerful new Anomalous Monism Taylor, John License: Other (please specify with Rights Statement) Document Version Peer reviewed version Citation for published version (Harvard): Taylor, J 2018, A powerful new Anomalous Monism. in M Guta (ed.), Consciousness and the Ontology of Properties. 1st edn, Routledge, New York, pp. 39-52. Link to publication on Research at Birmingham portal Publisher Rights Statement: Checked for eligibility 15/06/2018 This is an Accepted Manuscript of a book chapter published by Routledge/CRC Press in Consciousness and the Ontology of Properties on 19/07/2018, available online: https://www.routledge.com/Consciousness-and-the-Ontology-of-Properties/Guta/p/book/9781138097865 General rights Unless a licence is specified above, all rights (including copyright and moral rights) in this document are retained by the authors and/or the copyright holders. The express permission of the copyright holder must be obtained for any use of this material other than for purposes permitted by law. •Users may freely distribute the URL that is used to identify this publication. •Users may download and/or print one copy of the publication from the University of Birmingham research portal for the purpose of private study or non-commercial research. •User may use extracts from the document in line with the concept of ‘fair dealing’ under the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988 (?) •Users may not further distribute the material nor use it for the purposes of commercial gain. Where a licence is displayed above, please note the terms and conditions of the licence govern your use of this document.
    [Show full text]
  • The Mind–Body Problem: an Overview
    The Mind–Body Problem: An Overview Chapter 1 The Mind–Body Problem: An Overview Kirk Ludwig I have said that the soul is not more than the body, And I have said that the body is not more than the soul, And nothing, not God, is greater to one than one’s self is. Walt Whitman 1.1 Introduction Understanding the place of thought and feeling in the natural world is central to that general comprehension of nature, as well as that special self-understanding, which are the primary goals of science and philosophy. The general form of the project, which has exercised scientists and philosophers since the ancient world, is given by the question, ‘What is the relation, in general, between mental and physical phenomena?’ There is no settled agreement on the correct answer. This is the single most important gap in our understanding of the natural world. The trouble is that the question presents us with a problem: each possible answer to it has consequences that appear unacceptable. This problem has traditionally gone under the heading ‘The Mind–Body Problem.’1 My primary aim in this chapter is to explain in what this traditional mind–body problem consists, what its possible solutions are, and what obstacles lie in the way of a resolution. The discussion will develop in two phases. The first phase, sections 1.2–1.4, will be concerned to get clearer about the import of our initial question as a precondition of developing an account of possible responses to it. The second phase, sections 1.5–1.6, explains how a problem arises in our attempts to answer the question we have characterized, and surveys the various solutions that can be and have been offered.
    [Show full text]
  • A Powerful New Anomalous Monism
    Henry Taylor A Powerful New Anomalous Monism Henry Taylor This is a draft of a paper that is forthcoming in M. Guta (ed.) The Ontology of Consciousness. (Routledge). Please cite from published version. Abstract I distinguish between two broadly different interpretations of anomalous monism. I then pose problems for both. I argue that one interpretation leads to well known problems concerning epiphenomenalism, whilst the other interpretation is implausible because it fails to give a good account of the role of properties in causation. I then develop a new version of anomalous monism, which can avoid both of these issues. This view draws heavily on the metaphysics of dispositions, as well as work on causation. I conclude that anomalous monism is deserving of a reappraisal. Keywords: Anomalous monism, Properties, Epiphenomenalism, Laws. 1. What is Anomalous monism? Anomalous monism was famously put forward by Donald Davidson (1970a). Three claims lie at its core (Davidson 1970a: 105-106): i) The Principle of Causal Interaction: at least some mental events interact causally with physical events. ii) The Nomological Character of Causality: where there is causality, there must be a law. That is to say, events related as cause and effect fall under strict deterministic laws. iii) The Anomalism of the Mental: there are no strict deterministic laws on the basis of which mental events can be predicted and explained. I will not primarily be concerned with providing motivation for these claims. This is not to say that the motivations for them are unimportant or that the claims are 1 Henry Taylor uncontentious. For example, Davidson describes claim (iii) as ‘true and worth arguing for’ (1993: 3), though many have thought that it is neither true, nor worth arguing for (Crane and Mellor 1990: 196).
    [Show full text]
  • Introductory Lectures: the Nature and History of Cognitive Science Chapter 4: Philosophy’S Convergence Towards Cognitive Science by Dr
    Introductory Lectures: The Nature and History of Cognitive Science Chapter 4: Philosophy’s Convergence Towards Cognitive Science By Dr. Charles Wallis Last revision: 9/24/2018 Chapter Outline 4.1 Introduction 4.2 The Scientific Explosion of the Early 20th Century 4.3 The Logical and Mathematical Explosion of the Early 20th Century 4.4 The Rise Logical Empiricism 4.5 Logical Behaviorism 4.6 Three Problems for Logical Behaviorism 4.7 Identity Theories: Reduction Through Reference Equivalence Rather Than Meaning Equivalence 4.8 Identity Theories: Type-Type Identity 4.9 Two Arguments For Type-Type Identity Theory 4.10 Identity Theories: Token-Token Identity 4.11 Functionalism 4.12 Computationalism 4.13 Property Dualism 4.14 Eliminative Materialism 4.15 Glossary of Key Terms 4.16 Bibliography The 20th Century and the Semantic Twist 4.1 Introduction Recall that ontological frameworks provide a general framework within which theorists specify domains of inquiry and construct theories to predict, manipulate, and explain phenomena within the domain. Once researchers articulate an ontological framework with sufficient clarity they begin to formulate and test theories. Chapter two ends with the suggestion that oppositional substance dualists face two major challenges in their attempt to transition from the articulation of an ontological framework to the formulation and testing of theories purporting to predict, manipulate, and explain mental phenomena. On the one hand, oppositional substance dualists have problems formulating theories providing explanations, predictions, and manipulations of the continual, seamless interaction between the mental and the physical. Philosophers often call this the interaction problem. On the other hand, the very nature of a mental substance--substance defined so as to share no properties with physical substance--gives rise to additional challenges.
    [Show full text]
  • ANOMALOUS MONISM: OSCILLATING BETWEEN DOGMAS the Aim of This Paper Is to Expose an Inconsistency Within Davidson's Philosophy
    M. DE PINEDO ANOMALOUS MONISM: OSCILLATING BETWEEN DOGMAS ABSTRACT. Davidson’s anomalous monism, his argument for the identity between men- tal and physical event tokens, has been frequently attacked, usually demanding a higher degree of physicalist commitment. My objection runs in the opposite direction: the iden- tities inferred by Davidson from mental causation, the nomological character of causality and the anomaly of the mental are philosophically problematic and, more dramatically, incompatible with his famous argument against the third dogma of empiricism, the separa- tion of content from conceptual scheme. Given the anomaly of the mental and the absence of psychophysical laws, there are no conceptual resources to relate mental and physical predicates. We fall in the third dogma if we claim that the very same token event is mental and physical. One of the premises must be rejected: I will claim that we do not need a law to subsume cause and effect to be entitled to speak of causation. Davidson has never offered an argument to back this premise. Against such a dogma I will sketch some ideas pointing towards a different conception of causality, singularist and undetachable from explanatory practices. 1. The aim of this paper is to expose an inconsistency within Davidson’s philosophy and to argue that his commitment to the nomological character of causality is dogmatic. Davidson famously argues for an identity between tokens of mental events and tokens of physical events. This identity allows him to hold that mental events can have causal powers despite there not being psychological laws nor psychophysical laws and causality being nomological.
    [Show full text]
  • Reconciling Anomalous Monism and Scheme-Content Dualism: Reply to Manuel De Pinedo
    teorema Vol. XXIX/1, 2010, pp. 51-61 [BIBLID 0210-1602 (2010) 29:1; pp. 51-61] Reconciling Anomalous Monism and Scheme-Content Dualism: Reply to Manuel de Pinedo Dwayne Moore RESUMEN El monismo anómalo y el rechazo del dualismo esquema/contenido son dos de las más importantes contribuciones filosóficas de Donald Davidson. Seria sorprenden- te encontrar que estas dos doctrinas están en conflicto. Manuel de Pinedo (2006) ha argüido recientemente que de hecho hay cierta tensión entre ellas. Piensa que el mo- nismo anómalo requiere que los eventos particulares sean extensionales y, por tanto, que estén más allá de cualquier esquema conceptual, en tanto que el rechazo del dua- lismo esquema/contenido no permite tales eventos no-esquematizados. En este trabajo argumento que las reservas de Pinedo están desencaminadas. El monismo anómalo de Davidson requiere eventos particulares extensionales, pero se puede sostener esto sin adoptar un dualismo esquema/contenido. PALABRAS CLAVE: monismo anómalo, dualismo de esquema-contenido, Donald Davidson, triangulación. ABSTRACT Anomalous monism and the repudiation of scheme-content dualism are two of Donald Davidson’s more important philosophical contributions. It would be surpris- ing to discover that these doctrines are in conflict. Manuel de Pinedo (2006) has re- cently argued that there is in fact some tension. He thinks anomalous monism requires token events to be extensional and hence beyond any conceptual framework, whereas the rejection of scheme-content dualism does not permit any such schemeless events. In this paper I argue that Pinedo’s worries are misplaced. Davidson’s anomalous mo- nism does require extensional token events, but these can be invoked without adopting a dualism of scheme and content.
    [Show full text]
  • Causation and Mental Causation Jaegwon Kim
    Causation and Mental Causation Jaegwon Kim I An epistolary event occurred in 1643 that will live in the history of the debate on mental causation. In the May of that year, Princess Elisabeth of Bohemia dispatched to Descartes what must be one of the most celebrated philosophical letters, challenging Descartes to explain: How the mind of a human being can determine the bodily spirits [i.e., the fluids in the nerves, muscles, etc.] in producing voluntary actions, being only a thinKing substance. For it appears that all determination of movement is produced by the pushing of the thing being moved, by the manner in which it is pushed by that which moves it, or else by the qualification and figure of the surface of the latter. Contact is required for the first two conditions, and extension for the third. [But] you entirely exclude the latter from the notion you have of the body, and the former seems incompatible with an immaterial things.1 A need for explanation arises for Elisabeth because she takes contact as a necessary condition for physical causation: the causeat least, the proximate causeof the motion of a material body must be in spatial contact with that body, a condition that plainly cannot be met by an immaterial causal agent outside physical space. The idea that causation requires contact survives even in Hume, a philosopher who is commonly thought to have held a deflationary view of causation as consisting solely in de facto regularities. One of the conditions Hume laid down for causation is that of contiguity in space and time between cause and effect, either direct or mediated by a chain of contiguous cause-effect pairs.
    [Show full text]
  • Mechanisms of Mental Causation: an Examination of the Theories of Anomalous Monism and Direct Realism with Regard to Their Propo
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Sydney eScholarship Mechanisms of mental causation: An examination of the theories of Anomalous Monism and Direct Realism with regard to their proposals concerning the causal role of human mentality in the natural world. A thesis submitted in partial fulfilment of the requirements of Doctor of Philosophy, School of Psychology, Faculty of Science, University of Sydney. June, 2004. 1 Acknowledgements Throughout the process of writing the present thesis, I have been so fortunate as to spend many happy hours in discussing realist philosophy with my supervisors Joel Michell and Terence McMullen, as well as with Fiona Hibberd. I should like to take this opportunity to express my gratitude to each of these good friends, and to acknowledge the positive influence that they have had on my learning experience. I should also like to thank my parents, Faith Charity and Brian Medlow, for their loving support and the encouragement that they have shown me throughout all stages of my education. Most of all I am grateful to James Palethorpe who has been a fellow student and loving companion throughout the whole. Sharon Medlow 2 Abstract One of the most interesting developments in recent psychological theorising has been a growing appreciation of the need for a viable theory of mental causation. Hitherto, the prospects for reconciling what seems to be the uniquely rational character of human thought and action with the non-rational mechanistic workings of the natural world have appeared to be limited or even illusory, and the pursuit of reconciliation of this sort has therefore formerly been dismissed as being either impossible of completion or inappropriate for contemplation.
    [Show full text]