The Argument for Anomalous Monism, Again

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Argument for Anomalous Monism, Again Erasmus Student Journal of Philosophy Deren Olgun | The Argument for Anomalous Monism, Again ESJP The Argument for Anomalous Monism, Again #1 | 2011 Deren Olgun 1. Introduction predicate dualism only). Thus Davidson is neither a non-reductive physi- calist, nor can he be accused of property epiphenomenalism – properties 31 The main focus of the contemporary debate on mental causation has cen- simply do not enter into his philosophical scheme. tred on whether mental events can cause other events in virtue of their mental properties, or only in virtue of their physical ones. Whilst reduc- This paper is divided into eight sections. The first section introduces tive physicalists maintain that the only properties that exist are physical the mental causation debate by giving a brief outline of its history up to properties, and that any mental or other “higher-level” properties are only the contemporary debate about property epiphenomenalism. The second properties in virtue of their being identical with some physical property, section outlines the argument for anomalous monism. The third sec- non-reductive physicalists maintain that mental or other “higher-level” tion outlines one of the earliest arguments that asserted that anomalous properties are irreducible to physical ones. A common charge that has monism implies property epiphenomenalism. The fourth section out- been levelled against non-reductive physicalists is that if mental proper- lines various non-reductive physicalist responses that attempt to defend ties are irreducible then they must be causally inert or “epiphenomenal” non-reductivism. The fifth section outlines Kim’s influential “overdeter- since it cannot be the case that both mental and physical properties are mination” argument – the claim that non-reductive physicalists must simultaneously causal, a position which the literature has come to call accept either property epiphenomenalism or overdetermination. The sixth property epiphenomenalism. This paper argues that the charge of property section makes the case that anomalous monism cannot imply property epiphenomenalism is misplaced when it is applied to Donald Davidson’s epiphenomenalism. The seventh section deals with Sophie Gibb’s (2006) anomalous monism. Davidson cannot be accused of property epiphenom- criticisms of Davidson’s underlying approach to ontology, as instances of enalism because properties do not feature in his ontology and, therefore, more appropriate criticisms. The final section concludes. play no role in his account of causal relations between events. Davidson’s work and name have become embroiled in the debate about property epi- phenomenalism because he is mistakenly thought to be working in an 2. The Mental Causation Debate old tradition that accepts properties as an ontological category and that maintains that it is only in virtue of their properties that events have the Cartesian dualism is the classic form of substance dualism. Descartes main- effects that they do. Whilst the conceptual irreducibility of mental types tained that there are two kinds of substance, material and mental, and to physical types (predicate dualism), which is the hallmark of non-reduc- that man is a union of a spatially extended, material substance (the body), tive physicalism, is, for non-reductive physicalists, a consequence of an which is incapable of thought or feeling, and a spatially un-extended, men- ontological non-reductivism (property dualism), for Davidson the start tal substance (the mind or soul), which thinks and feels. and end point is the denial of conceptual reduction (i.e. the acceptance of Now, pre-theoretic conceptions of agency hold that the mind and the Erasmus Student Journal of Philosophy Deren Olgun | The Argument for Anomalous Monism, Again body causally interact. When, for example, Alfred summons the waiter Token identity states that any mental event or object is identical with some (by raising his hand, say), we say that his wanting to order caused him physical event or object – accepting token identity implies a rejection of to do so, just as we say that my intention to read Emile Zola’s Germinal substance dualism. Type identity, in contrast, holds that mental event causes my buying of the text. And, in agreement with these common sense types are identical with/reducible to physical event types – “types” here are intuitions, Descartes also maintained that the mind and the body causally generally taken to mean properties, although, as we will later observe, it interact. However, one of the main problems for Cartesian dualism is how can also mean predicates. to marry the possibility of mental-physical causal interaction with the total Accepting both token identity and type identity is a reductive physical- independence of mental and material substances – it is very difficult to see ist position. Reductive physicalists deny mental causation because, as they how an un-extended, immaterial substance with no presence in physical maintain, a mental event only has the causal power it does in virtue of its space could causally influence material bodies that are subject to the laws being identical with some physical event; that it is only because the event is 32 of physics. And indeed, as Kim notes, the ‘inability to explain the possibil- of a certain physical type that it is the cause it is, and its being of a certain ity of “mental causation”, how mentality can make a causal difference to mental type is just a consequence of its being that physical type. the world, doomed Cartesian dualism’ (Kim, 1996: 4). In contrast to the reductive physicalist position, Donald Davidson’s The majority position (see Kim, 1996; Crane 2003) in contempo- anomalous monism (1970, 1993) seeks to defend the possibility of men- rary philosophy of mind rejects Cartesian dualism in favour of a kind tal causation. The idea that reasons are causes of actions is a central part of monism, which argues that there is only one kind of substance. More of Davidson’s philosophy (see Davidson, 1963) and anomalous monism specifically, it is a physicalist or “materialist” monism that has come to represents a stance in the philosophy of mind that combines his position dominate the debate, a position that is generally known as physicalism. on mental causation with other elements of his philosophy, including his Kim defines ontological physicalism as the position that ‘there are no con- views on events (see Davidson, 1969), causation (see Davidson, 1967b) crete existents, or substances, in the spacetime world other than material and semantics (see Davidson, 1967a, 1974a, 1977). Whilst anomalous particles and their aggregates’ (Kim, 1996: 211) and observes that ‘in most monism accepts token identity, it denies type identity (where by “types” contemporary debates, ontological physicalism forms the starting point of Davidson would have in mind predicates rather than properties), holding discussion rather than a conclusion that needs to be established.’ (Ibid.: that mental types are irreducible to physical ones. 211) In response, many critics (e.g., Honderich, 1982; McLaughlin, 1993; However, embracing physicalism does not resolve the problem of Kim 1993a) have argued that anomalous monism is inherently contradic- mental causation that dogged substance dualism: it still remains unclear tory and that the only reasonable way to resolve the contradiction is to as to how mental events or objects (whatever their apparent relation to accept that mental events are epiphenomenal, or rather that mental prop- the physical substance that constitutes them) can causally interact with erties are epiphenomenal – the general argument taking the form that it physical events or objects. The debate has simply shifted its focus from is only in virtue of an event’s being a certain physical type that it has the substances to properties, as Kim notes ‘the most intensely debated issue – effect that it does, and not in virtue of its being a certain mental type, that in fact, the only substantive remaining issue – concerning the mind-body mental events do not cause anything qua mental; a position which we relation has centred on properties – that is, the question how mental and shall call property epiphenomenalism. In response to these criticisms, argu- physical properties are related to each other’ (Ibid.: 211-212 – emphasis in ments in defence of anomalous monism (e.g., LePore & Loewer (1987), original). To make sense of the debate to which Kim refers it will be help- Macdonald & Macdonald (1991), Macdonald (2007)), which are usually ful to draw on the distinction between token identity and type identity. dubbed non-reductive physicalism, have been proposed. These arguments, Erasmus Student Journal of Philosophy Deren Olgun | The Argument for Anomalous Monism, Again in general, contort the positions developed by Davidson’s critics in such a In terms of the discussion of previous section, CI is just the acceptance of way as to (attempt to) restore causal efficacy and relevance to the mental the possibility of what we have been calling mental causation. NCC is, by properties of events. Davidson’s own acknowledgment (Davidson, 1970: 209), unsupported. AOM is defended by appealing to Quine’s argument of the indeterminacy In so far as the debate is one between reductive and non-reductive of translation: it is not possible to formulate strict laws that relate the physicalists, or one between non-reductive physicalists of different stripes, two, distinct, conceptual realms, because mental concepts are not explica- asking whether or not their positions imply property epiphenomenalism ble in physical vocabulary, nor physical concepts in mental vocabulary. As is a reasonable line of inquiry. Where it ceases to become reasonable is Davidson notes: when Davidson’s anomalous monism is made the object of this line of attack either explicitly or because it has been classed, as it frequently is ‘There are no strict psychophysical laws because of the disparate (e.g. Jacob, 2002), as a form of non-reductive physicalism. As Davidson commitments of the mental and physical schemes’ (Davidson, 1970: 33 (1967b, 1980, 1993) maintains, and as is reiterated by Tim Crane (1995) 222).
Recommended publications
  • From Physics to Physicalism
    FROM PHYSICS TO PHYSICALISM a version of this paper is published in Physicalism and its Discontents ed, Gillett and Loewer Cambridge University Press 2001 Introduction Hilary Putnam explains that: The appeal of materialism lies precisely in this, in its claim to be natural metaphysics within the bounds of science. That a doctrine which promises to gratify our ambition (to know the noumenal) and our caution (not to be unscientific) should have great appeal is hardly something to be wondered at. (Putnam (1983), p.210) Materialism says that all facts, in particular all mental facts, obtain in virtue of the spatio- temporal distribution, and properties, of matter. It was, as Putnam says, “metaphysics within the bounds of science”, but only so long as science was thought to say that the world is made out of matter.1 In this century physicists have learned that there is more in the world than matter and, in any case, matter isn’t quite what it seemed to be. For this reason many philosophers who think that metaphysics should be informed by science advocate physicalism in place of materialism. Physicalism claims that all facts obtain in virtue of the distribution of the fundamental entities and properties –whatever they turn out to be- of completed fundamental physics. Later I will discuss a more precise formulation. But not all contemporary philosophers embrace physicalism. Some- and though a minority not a small or un-influential one- think that physicalism is rather the metaphysics for an unjustified scientism; i.e. it is scientistic metaphysics. Those among them that think that physicalism can be clearly formulated think that it characterizes a cold, colorless, unfeeling and uninteresting world and not, they think, the world we live in.
    [Show full text]
  • Leibniz, Bayle and the Controversy on Sudden Change Markku Roinila (In: Giovanni Scarafile & Leah Gruenpeter Gold (Ed.), Paradoxes of Conflicts, Springer 2016)
    Leibniz, Bayle and the Controversy on Sudden Change Markku Roinila (In: Giovanni Scarafile & Leah Gruenpeter Gold (ed.), Paradoxes of Conflicts, Springer 2016) Leibniz’s metaphysical views were not known to most of his correspondents, let alone to the larger public, until 1695 when he published an article in Journal des savants, titled in English “A New System of the Nature and Communication of Substances, and of the Union of the Soul and Body” (henceforth New System).1 The article raised quite a stir. Perhaps the most interesting and cunning critique of Leibniz’s views was provided by a French refugee in Rotterdam, Pierre Bayle (1647−1706) who is most famous for his Dictionnaire Historique et Critique (1697). The fascinating controversy on Leibniz’s idea of pre-established harmony and a number of other topics lasted for five years and ended only when Bayle died. In this paper I will give an overview of the communication, discuss in detail a central topic concerning spontaneity or a sudden change in the soul, and compare the views presented in the communication to Leibniz’s reflections in his partly concurrent New Essays on Human Understanding (1704) (henceforth NE). I will also reflect on whether the controversy could have ended in agreement if it would have continued longer. The New System Let us begin with the article that started the controversy, the New System. The article starts with Leibniz’s objection to the Cartesian doctrine of extension as a basic way of explaining motion. Instead, one should adopt a doctrine of force which belongs to the sphere of metaphysics (GP IV 478).
    [Show full text]
  • Eternity and Immortality in Spinoza's Ethics
    Midwest Studies in Philosophy, XXVI (2002) Eternity and Immortality in Spinoza’s Ethics STEVEN NADLER I Descartes famously prided himself on the felicitous consequences of his philoso- phy for religion. In particular, he believed that by so separating the mind from the corruptible body, his radical substance dualism offered the best possible defense of and explanation for the immortality of the soul. “Our natural knowledge tells us that the mind is distinct from the body, and that it is a substance...And this entitles us to conclude that the mind, insofar as it can be known by natural phi- losophy, is immortal.”1 Though he cannot with certainty rule out the possibility that God has miraculously endowed the soul with “such a nature that its duration will come to an end simultaneously with the end of the body,” nonetheless, because the soul (unlike the human body, which is merely a collection of material parts) is a substance in its own right, and is not subject to the kind of decomposition to which the body is subject, it is by its nature immortal. When the body dies, the soul—which was only temporarily united with it—is to enjoy a separate existence. By contrast, Spinoza’s views on the immortality of the soul—like his views on many issues—are, at least in the eyes of most readers, notoriously difficult to fathom. One prominent scholar, in what seems to be a cry of frustration after having wrestled with the relevant propositions in Part Five of Ethics,claims that this part of the work is an “unmitigated and seemingly unmotivated disaster..
    [Show full text]
  • Identity, Personal Continuity, and Psychological Connectedness Across Time and Over
    1 Identity, Personal Continuity, and Psychological Connectedness across Time and over Transformation Oleg Urminskyi, University of Chicago University of Chicago, Booth School of Business Daniel Bartels, University of Chicago University of Chicago, Booth School of Business Forthcoming, Handbook of Research on Identity Theory in Marketing 2 ABSTRACT: How do people think about whether the person they’ll be in the future is substantially the same person they’ll be today or a substantially different, and how does this affect consumer decisions and behavior? In this chapter, we discuss several perspectives about which changes over time matter for these judgments and downstream behaviors, including the identity verification principle (Reed et al. 2012) — people’s willful change in the direction of an identity that they hope to fulfill. Our read of the literature on the self-concept suggests that what defines a person (to themselves) is multi-faceted and in almost constant flux, but that understanding how personal changes relate to one’s own perceptions of personal continuity, including understanding the distinction between changes that are consistent or inconsistent with people’s expectations for their own development, can help us to understand people’s subjective sense of self and the decisions and behaviors that follow from it. 3 A person’s sense of their own identity (i.e., the person’s self-concept) plays a central role in how the person thinks and acts. Research on identity, particularly in social psychology and consumer behavior, often views a person’s self-concept as a set of multiple (social) identities, sometimes characterized in terms of the category labels that the person believes apply to themselves, like “male” or “high school athlete” (Markus and Wurf 1987).
    [Show full text]
  • 1Jackson (1998) Gives This Necessary Condition on Physicalism. 2Two of the Reasons That Kim Gives for Holding That Supervenience
    For Philosophy and Phenomenolgical Research The main conclusion of Jaegwon Kim’s admirable Mind and the Physical World is that the mind- body problem- Descartes problem of explaining how mental causation is possible- has not yet been solved. In particular, non reductive physicalism (NRP), a metaphysical account of the relationship between mental and physical entities that has become increasingly popular among philosophers of mind and that Kim himself once endorsed, is not a viable solution to the problem. I argue here that Kim’s arguments against non-reductive physicalism are unpersuasive and suggest that they involve assumptions about causation that are implausible in the light of contemporary physics. When these assumptions are rejected NRP lives. NRP is a family of views differing by how they understand “reduction” and “physicalism.” Following Kim I understand the non-reduction as holding that some events and properties are distinct from any physical events and properties. A necessary condition for physicalism is that mental properties, events, and laws supervene on physical ones. Kim allows various understandings of “supervenience” but I think that physicalism requires at least the claim that any minimal physical duplicate of the actual world is a duplicate simpliciter.1 Some complications aside this means that true mental propositions, e.g. Jaegwon is thinking about sailing, are metaphysically entailed by true physical propositions. Kim says that supervenience is too weak to capture the root idea of physicalism that mental property instantiations depend on physical property instantiations so he adds that the mental depends on the physical.2 One way (but not the only way) in which this dependance might be spelled out is that mental properties are higher order functional properties whose instantiations are realized by instantiations of physical properties.
    [Show full text]
  • The No-Self Theory: Hume, Buddhism, and Personal Identity Author(S): James Giles Reviewed Work(S): Source: Philosophy East and West, Vol
    The No-Self Theory: Hume, Buddhism, and Personal Identity Author(s): James Giles Reviewed work(s): Source: Philosophy East and West, Vol. 43, No. 2 (Apr., 1993), pp. 175-200 Published by: University of Hawai'i Press Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/1399612 . Accessed: 20/08/2012 03:38 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. University of Hawai'i Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Philosophy East and West. http://www.jstor.org THE NO-SELF THEORY: HUME, BUDDHISM, AND JamesGiles PERSONAL IDENTITY The problem of personal identity is often said to be one of accounting for Lecturerin Philosophy what it is that gives persons their identity over time. However, once the and Psychologyat Folkeuniversitetet problem has been construed in these terms, it is plain that too much has Aalborg,Denmark already been assumed. For what has been assumed is just that persons do have an identity. To the philosophers who approach the problem with this supposition already accepted, the possibility that there may be no such thing as personal identity is scarcely conceived. As a result, the more fundamental question-whether or not personal identity exists in the first place-remains unasked.
    [Show full text]
  • Is Human Information Processing Conscious?
    CommentaryfVelmans: Consciousness The resistance against a natural-science approach to conscious consciousness is required for it. He considers semantic analysis experience reminds one also of the great debate a century ago of novel word combinations, on-line analysis of speech, learn- between Darwinians and creationists. Darwin's opponents ing, memory, identification, planning and control of complex clearly believed they were attacking not a mere scientific hy- novel action, and others, arguing in each case that these things pothesis, but a conception of human nature that would tear away can be done without consciousnessp. (This survey is the bulk of the last remaining shreds of human dignity. The contemporary his paper.) He concludes that there is no type of information resistance by Velmans and others to a straightforward natural- processing for which consciousnessp is required, and therefore science approach to conscious experience may be driven by a that consciousness plays no causal role in and does not "enter similar anxiety. But Darwin did not deprive us of human into" information processing, and is in that sense dignity; treating conscious experience as a normal topic of epiphenomenal.1 psychology and neuroscience will not do so either. The fallacy of this argument is equally simple. Even if Indeed, one can make the opposite argument: that denial of Velmans is right that consciousnessp is not required for any first-person conscious experience in other people may lead to a particular sort of information processing, it does not follow that profound kind of dehumanization. It comes down to saying that consciousness does not causally enter into information process- other people are not capable of joy or suffering, that as far as the ing.
    [Show full text]
  • Andrew Wong Washington University, St. Louis the Aim of This Paper Is to Support Donald Davidson's Anomalous Monism1 As An
    do E s An o m A l o u s mo n i s m hA v E proper construal of Davidson’s principle Ex p l A n A t o r y fo r ce ? of rationality will show the objection to be misguided. Andrew Wong Washington University, St. Louis “Mental Events” reconciles the paradox which arises from three principles Davidson held ex hypothesi: (1) Mental events interact causally with physical events (Principle of Causal Interaction), (2) Where there is causality, there must be a law (Principle of the Nomological The aim of this paper is to support Donald Character of Causality), and (3) There are no 1 strict deterministic laws on the basis of which Davidson’s Anomalous Monism as an account mental events can be predicted and explained of law-governed mental causation in a world (Principle of the Anomalism of the Mental).4 unfettered by psychophysical laws. To this end, I will attempt to answer one principal objection Tension is apparent in that some mental to the theory: the claim that Anomalous events must interact causally with physical events Monism lacks sufficient “explanatory force.”2 and thereby feature in laws, and that this is an Though not quite the standard objection, I explicit contradiction of the Principle of the believe it to be the most formidable, and hence Anomalism of the Mental. Accepting three the most crucial to address.3 The argument’s further principles, in addition to the three strength is that it need not dispute Davidson’s above, will resolve the tension: (4) Each mental assumptions.
    [Show full text]
  • Studies on Causal Explanation in Naturalistic Philosophy of Mind
    tn tn+1 s s* r1 r2 r1* r2* Interactions and Exclusions: Studies on Causal Explanation in Naturalistic Philosophy of Mind Tuomas K. Pernu Department of Biosciences Faculty of Biological and Environmental Sciences & Department of Philosophy, History, Culture and Art Studies Faculty of Arts ACADEMIC DISSERTATION To be publicly discussed, by due permission of the Faculty of Arts at the University of Helsinki, in lecture room 5 of the University of Helsinki Main Building, on the 30th of November, 2013, at 12 o’clock noon. © 2013 Tuomas Pernu (cover figure and introductory essay) © 2008 Springer Science+Business Media (article I) © 2011 Walter de Gruyter (article II) © 2013 Springer Science+Business Media (article III) © 2013 Taylor & Francis (article IV) © 2013 Open Society Foundation (article V) Layout and technical assistance by Aleksi Salokannel | SI SIN Cover layout by Anita Tienhaara Author’s address: Department of Biosciences Division of Physiology and Neuroscience P.O. Box 65 FI-00014 UNIVERSITY OF HELSINKI e-mail [email protected] ISBN 978-952-10-9439-2 (paperback) ISBN 978-952-10-9440-8 (PDF) ISSN 1799-7372 Nord Print Helsinki 2013 If it isn’t literally true that my wanting is causally responsible for my reaching, and my itching is causally responsible for my scratching, and my believing is causally responsible for my saying … , if none of that is literally true, then practically everything I believe about anything is false and it’s the end of the world. Jerry Fodor “Making mind matter more” (1989) Supervised by Docent Markus
    [Show full text]
  • European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy, XII-2 | 2020 Santayana’S Epiphenomenalism Reconsidered 2
    European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy XII-2 | 2020 Democracy as a Form of Life Santayana’s Epiphenomenalism Reconsidered Robin Weiss Electronic version URL: http://journals.openedition.org/ejpap/2138 DOI: 10.4000/ejpap.2138 ISSN: 2036-4091 Publisher Associazione Pragma Electronic reference Robin Weiss, « Santayana’s Epiphenomenalism Reconsidered », European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy [Online], XII-2 | 2020, Online since 14 December 2020, connection on 15 December 2020. URL : http://journals.openedition.org/ejpap/2138 ; DOI : https://doi.org/10.4000/ ejpap.2138 This text was automatically generated on 15 December 2020. Author retains copyright and grants the European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy right of first publication with the work simultaneously licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution- NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 International License. Santayana’s Epiphenomenalism Reconsidered 1 Santayana’s Epiphenomenalism Reconsidered Robin Weiss 1 Recently, it has become increasingly common to question the extent to which Santayana’s philosophy of mind can and should be identified as a kind of epiphenomenalism, as has traditionally been the case. Most scholars take Santayana’s epiphenomenalism for granted, and either assert or deny that he gives an argument to support it.1 However, others have questioned whether the evident similarities between Santayana’s own views and those of modern-day epiphenomenalists obscure more significant differences. I will argue that, indeed, Santayana’s views are potentially inaccurately captured by the term “epiphenomenalism.” However, I shall argue that this is true for reasons other than other scholars have given for this view. 2 The issue turns on what Santayana means by a “cause” when he denies that ideas are causes of action.
    [Show full text]
  • Causal Closure of the Physical, Mental Causation, and Physics
    Preprint – Accepted for publication in European Journal for Philosophy of Science Causal closure of the physical, mental causation, and physics Dejan R. Dimitrijević Department of Physics Faculty of Sciences and Mathematics University of Niš Abstract The argument from causal closure of the physical (CCP) is usually considered the most powerful argument in favor of the ontological doctrine of physicalism. Many authors, most notably Papineau, assume that CCP implies that physicalism is supported by physics. I demonstrate, however, that physical science has no bias in the ontological debate between proponents of physicalism and dualism. I show that the arguments offered for CCP are effective only against the accounts of mental causation based on the action of the mental forces of a Newtonian nature, i.e. those which manifest themselves by causing accelerations. However, it is conceivable and possible that mental causation is manifested through the redistribution of energy, momentum and other conserved quantities in the system, brought about by altering the state probability distribution within the living system and leading to anomalous correlations of neural processes. After arguing that a probabilistic, interactionist model of mental causation is conceivable, which renders the argument from causal closure of the physical ineffective, I point to some basic features that such a model must have in order to be intelligible. At the same time, I indicate the way that conclusive testing of CCP can be done within the theoretical framework of physics. Keywords: Causal closure of the physical; Mental causation; Second law of thermodynamics; Physics; Probability distribution 2 1 Introduction At the beginning of his influential paper „The Rise of Physicalism‟ (2001), David Papineau, one of the leading proponents of the ontological doctrine of physicalism in our time, made a bold statement that “physical science has come to claim a particular kind of hegemony over other subjects in the second half of [20th] century.
    [Show full text]
  • Divine Idealism As Physicalism? Reflections on the Structural Definition of Physicalism
    DIVINE IDEALISM AS PHYSICALISM? REFLECTIONS ON THE STRUCTURAL DEFINITION OF PHYSICALISM Jon W. Thompson Hempel’s Dilemma remains at the center of the problem of defining phys- icalism. In brief, the dilemma asks whether physicalism should be defined by appeal to current or future physics. If defined by current physics, phys- icalism is almost certainly false. If defined by an ideal future physics, then physicalism has little determinable content. Montero and Papineau have innovatively suggested that the dilemma may be avoided by defining phys- icalism structurally. While their definition is one among many definitions, it is significant in that—if successful—it would break the impasse for defining physicalism. I argue, however, that the structural definition fails because it counts metaphysical frameworks (crucially, versions of divine idealism) as “physicalist”—an unwelcome result for physicalists. This paper thus furthers the debate on the definition of physicalism and sheds light on the relationship between physicalism and idealism. 1. Hempel’s Dilemma Physicalism is often defined as the view that all that exists is what physics studies; but many voices have raised concerns over such a definition. In- deed, the problem of defining physicalism has been with us for some time now.1 “Hempel’s Dilemma” puts the problem in exacting focus: when the physicalist claims that all that exists is physical, is she claiming that [A] All that exists is what is studied by current physics or that [B] All that exists is what is studied by some ideal, perhaps future, physics?2 If the physi- calist intends [A], then physicalism is clearly false.
    [Show full text]