An Analysis of Small Clauses and Perception Verb Complements*

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

An Analysis of Small Clauses and Perception Verb Complements* AN ANALYSIS OF SMALL CLAUSES AND PERCEPTION VERB COMPLEMENTS* TORUSUZUKI Tohoku University This paper presents an analysisof small clauses,which subsumes them under the general clausal structure of English. We propose that small clauses are projected by the INFL head in an analogousway to the other types of clausal projectionswith respect to X-bar theory. It is shown that small clauses allow any lexical phrasal categoriesAP, PP, NP, and VP as their internal predicates,while the other clauses only take VP predicate for principled reasons. The analysis also gives a generalizedaccount of some syntactic pecu- liarities of Perception Verb Complements, in particular, the anomalous behavior of bare infinitive complements in passivization. 0. INTRODUCTION.The aim of this paper is two-fold. First, we will investigate the nature of small clauses and present an analysis of the general clausal structure of English, including tensed clauses, infinitival clauses, Acc-ing clauses and small clauses. Second, based on this ana- lysis, we will give an account of some interesting properties of Perception Verb Complements in English. In section 1, we will survey some theoretical assumptions which are necessary for our proposal, and then develop an analysis of small clauses in which they are treated as projections of INFL head. Our analysis claims that in principle small clauses may have any phrasal categories like AP, PP, NP, and VP as their predicates, in contrast to the other types of clauses projected by INFL. A critical review of a pioneering analysis of small clauses (cf. Stowell 1983) will be given in section 2. In section 3, * This is a revised version of a paper read at the General Meeting of the English Literary Society of Japan held at Chuo University,May 23, 1987. I am indebted to Masaru Nakamura for his valuable suggestionsand comments on the earlier versions of this paper. I would like to thank Dr. Graham McMaster,who kindly acted as an informantand correctedstylistic errors. My thanks alsogo to MakotoYamada for his kind assistance. Lastly I am grateful to two anonymousreviewers of this journal for their critical comments and suggetions. All remaining inadequacies are my own. -54- AN ANALYSIS OF SMALL CLAUSES AND PERCEPTION VERB COMPLEMENTS 55 some syntactic properties peculiar to Perception Verb Complements will be accounted for under our proposal. 1. THE GENERAL CLAUSAL STRUCTURE OF ENGLISH. The bracketed sequences of words below which express a subject-predicate relation are generally taken to be a syntactic constituent called a 'small clause'.1 (1) a. I consider [John very stupid]. b. John believes [her a genius]. c. I expect [Mary in New York]. In this paper, we are to present a unified structural analysis of these small clauses under a restrictive X-bar theory (in a sense to be made clear shortly). Our basic theoretical assumptions are as follows. First, following Chomsky 1986b, we assume throughout this study the X-bar schema in 2, which claims categories S and S' in traditional terms to be analyzed as maximal projections of INFL and COMP, respectively, with the internal structures represented in 3. (2) XP=[Specifier [X' X Complement]] (3) a. S=IP(I")=[NP [I' INFL VP]] b. S'=CP (C")=[...[C' COMP IP]] Here we are assuming a restrictive version of the X-bar theory in that every category, whether lexical or nonlexical, has an isomorphic head- projection structure without exception. Second, we follow Stowell's 1982 arguments for inherent tense in to- infinitives. He proposes that to-infinitives have an inherently fixed tense frame. In 4 and 5 below, the to-infinitives constantly indicate 'unrealized or hypothetical future' with respect to the matrix tense, in contrast to gerund cases where relevant tense interpretation seems to depend on the semantics of matrix verbs. (4) a. Jenny remembered [PRO to bring the wine]. b. Jenny remembered [PRO bringing the wine]. (5) a. Jim tried [PRO to lock the door]. b. Jim tried [PRO locking the door]. (Stowell 1982) Stowell assumes a general condition which is involved in the tense 1 In this paper we will not be concernedwith Williams' 1983analysis which claims that small clauses are to be treatedas non-constituents. For criticismsof his analysis, see Hornstein & Lightfoot 1987and Safir 1983 among others. 56 ENGLISH LINGUISTICS, VOLUME 5 (1988) interpretation process at LF, which is roughly stated below. (6) COMP position is required for the tense interpretation of inherent tense operator in INFL. Condition 6 provides an explanation for the peculiar behavior of so- called Exceptional Case Marking (ECM) constructions in their tense interpretation. It is generally assumed that ECM complements lack COMP position (due to either a rule of 'S-bar deletion' or the verb's direct sub categorization for IP). Condition 6 predicts that the inter- pretation of inherent tense in to-infinitives in ECM structures like 7 is impossible, since the COMP position which is required for the inter- pretation of tense does not seem to be available for the INFL in embedded clauses. Thus, Stowell argues, the resultant tense inter- pretation of the embedded clauses has to depend on the semantics of matrix verbs; in ECM constructions, the embedded tense is always lexically determined by matrix verbs. For instance, the tense of 7a is interpreted as present, that of 7b as future, and that of 7c as past. (7) a. Bill considers himself to be the smartest. b. I expect John to win the race. c. I remember John to be the smartest. (Stowell 1982) Here we follow Stowell's arguments for the presence of inherent tense in to-infinitives and assume that the INFL of to-infinitives is specified for [+Tense] in a parallel way to the INFL of tensed clauses. Third, we adopt the proposal in Reuland 1983 that the verbal suffix-ing in Acc-ing constructions is a realization of INFL with AGR. Reuland argues that the agreement element in INFL is basically nominal in character since it shares features, such as number, gender, person and so on, with the subject of a clause. We further assume that morphologi- cally realizable AGR is represented as [+N] for its basically nominal character. Based on the above assumptions, we propose that INFL consists of at least two independent elements, Tense and AGR, the former specified for the feature [±Tense] and the latter specified for the feature [±N]. The following four types of INFL are available as basic forms of INFL in the English clausal system. (8) a. INFL1=[+Tense, +N] b. INFL2=[+Tense, -N] c. INFL3=[-Tense, +N] d. INFL0=[-Tense, φ] [+Tense] feature in 8 indicates the potential existence of inherent tense AN ANALYSIS OF SMALL CLAUSES AND PERCEPTION VERB COMPLEMENTS 57 (or tense operator), which requires a certain COMP position for its interpretation due to 6, while [-Tense] feature indicates the absence of inherent tense, the relevant tense interpretation consequently depending on the semantics of a matrix verb which governs the projection of the INFL. As for the specification [±N] with respect to AGR, [+N] indicates the existence of AGR, while [-N] indicates the absence of AGR. INFL1 is the core head of tensed clauses (IP) in the usual sense. In the present framework, a tensed clause forms a CP (with or without an overt COMP) and it contains a maximal projection of INFL1, probably due to a selectional property holding between COMP and INFL, which is required for appropriate tense interpretation. The feature specification [+Tense, +N] indicates that INFL1 has its own inherent tense and the feature complex AGR. It phonetically realizes as tense marker (e.g. past -ed) and/or person and number marker (e.g. third-singular-s) on verbal inflection. INFL2 phonetically realizes as to in to-infinitives. Recall that we are taking the position, following Stowell 1982, that to-infinitives are poten- tially equipped with its inherent tense 'unrealized or hypothetical future', though it may fail to be interpreted at LF due to lack of proper COMP position, typically in ECM contexts. The feature [+Tense] reflects the presence of this inherent tense. If a maximal projection of INFL2 is selected by COMP (for or some empty equivalent), thus incorporated into CP, its inherent tense will be properly interpreted. If, on the contrary, it is not selected by any COMP but is directly selected by some other lexical head, presumably V, then the relevant tense interpretation of INFL2 will have to depend on the meaning of the matrix verb, because there is no available COMP position for the interpretation of its inherent tense under 6. The feature [-N] simply indicates the absence of mor- phologically realizable AGR which would be responsible for verbal inflection. The lexical realization of INFL3 is the verbal inflection-ing and its maximal projection is the form of IP with NP-ing structure, known as Acc-ing constructions and, we may presumably include, absolute con- structions, in this type of structure. The feature [-Tense] in INFL3 indicates lack of inherent tense and as a consequence tense interpretation of INFL3 has to depend on the matrix predicate's semantics. The feature [+N] is an indication of AGR as we are assuming following Reuland 1983. The maximal projection of INFL3, unlike that of INFL1 and 58 ENGLISH LINGUISTICS, VOLUME 5 (1988) INFL2, cannot be selected by any kind of COMP, thus never forming CP. This property comes from the assumption that there is no selec- tional relation in terms of tense between COMP and INFL3. Lastly, a maximal projection of INFL0 is the category which we have been calling 'small clause'. This type of IP is similar to the projection of INFL3 in the sense that it does not form CP, that is, its projection will not be selected by COMP.
Recommended publications
  • Against Predp
    AGAINST PREDP ORA MATUSHANSKY SFL (CNRS/Université Paris-8)/UiL OTS/Utrecht University 1xxIntroduction Whereas Stowell 1981, 1983 analyzes small clauses (minimal units of predication) as maximal projections of the head of the predicate (i.e., as APs, PPs, etc.), Bowers 1993, 2001 argues that this is not enough and predication must be mediated by a functional head (Pred°), which has both a semantic and a syntactic function: (1) VP V° PredP = small clause consider DP Pred Marie Pred° AP ø proud of her work Bowers' motivation for this proposal was mostly theoretical, but some empirical evidence was also provided. However, as I will argue below, this conclusion, although widely accepted by now, is not, on closer examination, supported by linguistic evidence that has been adduced in its favor and theory-internal arguments for it either have become obsolete or may be counted by an alternative explanation. 2xxTheoretical Evidence for PredP The first, most frequently cited argument for the existence of a functional head in small clauses comes from coordination. While it is generally impossible to coordinate maximal projections of different lexical heads (a constraint from Chomsky 1957 that Williams 1981 terms the Law of Coordination of Likes), coordination of small-clause predicates is possible (Sag et al. 1985): 83 84 Matushansky (2) a. I consider Fred crazy and a fool. b. I consider Mary both shrewd and in the know. Bowers proposes that the Law of Coordination of Likes can be explained by the impossibility of assigning a label to the constituent formed by the coordination of projections of X° and Y°.
    [Show full text]
  • Serial Verb Constructions Revisited: a Case Study from Koro
    Serial Verb Constructions Revisited: A Case Study from Koro By Jessica Cleary-Kemp A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Linguistics in the Graduate Division of the University of California, Berkeley Committee in charge: Associate Professor Lev D. Michael, Chair Assistant Professor Peter S. Jenks Professor William F. Hanks Summer 2015 © Copyright by Jessica Cleary-Kemp All Rights Reserved Abstract Serial Verb Constructions Revisited: A Case Study from Koro by Jessica Cleary-Kemp Doctor of Philosophy in Linguistics University of California, Berkeley Associate Professor Lev D. Michael, Chair In this dissertation a methodology for identifying and analyzing serial verb constructions (SVCs) is developed, and its application is exemplified through an analysis of SVCs in Koro, an Oceanic language of Papua New Guinea. SVCs involve two main verbs that form a single predicate and share at least one of their arguments. In addition, they have shared values for tense, aspect, and mood, and they denote a single event. The unique syntactic and semantic properties of SVCs present a number of theoretical challenges, and thus they have invited great interest from syntacticians and typologists alike. But characterizing the nature of SVCs and making generalizations about the typology of serializing languages has proven difficult. There is still debate about both the surface properties of SVCs and their underlying syntactic structure. The current work addresses some of these issues by approaching serialization from two angles: the typological and the language-specific. On the typological front, it refines the definition of ‘SVC’ and develops a principled set of cross-linguistically applicable diagnostics.
    [Show full text]
  • Dative Constructions in Romance and Beyond
    Dative constructions in Romance and beyond Edited by Anna Pineda Jaume Mateu language Open Generative Syntax 7 science press Open Generative Syntax Editors: Elena Anagnostopoulou, Mark Baker, Roberta D’Alessandro, David Pesetsky, Susi Wurmbrand In this series: 1. Bailey, Laura R. & Michelle Sheehan (eds.). Order and structure in syntax I: Word order and syntactic structure. 2. Sheehan, Michelle & Laura R. Bailey (eds.). Order and structure in syntax II: Subjecthood and argument structure. 3. Bacskai­Atkari, Julia. Deletion phenomena in comparative constructions: English comparatives in a cross­linguistic perspective. 4. Franco, Ludovico, Mihaela Marchis Moreno & Matthew Reeve (eds.). Agreement, case and locality in the nominal and verbal domains. 5. Bross, Fabian. The clausal syntax of German Sign Language: A cartographic approach. 6. Smith, Peter W., Johannes Mursell & Katharina Hartmann (eds.). Agree to Agree: Agreement in the Minimalist Programme. 7. Pineda, Anna & Jaume Mateu (eds.). Dative constructions in Romance and beyond. ISSN: 2568­7336 Dative constructions in Romance and beyond Edited by Anna Pineda Jaume Mateu language science press Pineda, Anna & Jaume Mateu (eds.). 2020. Dative constructions in Romance and beyond (Open Generative Syntax 7). Berlin: Language Science Press. This title can be downloaded at: http://langsci-press.org/catalog/book/258 © 2020, the authors Published under the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 Licence (CC BY 4.0): http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/ ISBN: 978-3-96110-249-5 (Digital) 978-3-96110-250-1
    [Show full text]
  • William Snyder the Compounding Parameter (TCP)
    To appear in Violeta Demonte and Louise McNally (eds.) Telicity, Change, and State . Oxford: OUP. 1 PARAMETER THEORY AND MOTION PREDICATES William Snyder The Compounding Parameter (TCP) of (Snyder 1995, 2001) has been linked to a number of the same points of cross-linguistic variation that Leonard Talmy (1985, 1991, 2000) addresses in his well-known verb-framed / satellite-framed typology. Talmy differentiates between languages in which path-of-motion is normally encoded in the main verb of a clause ("verb-framed" languages), and those in which path-of-motion is more commonly expressed outside the verb ("satellite-framed" languages). Both the English type of verb-particle construction (where the particle can be separated from the verb by a phrasal constituent, as in Mary pulled the lid off ) and the English adjectival resultative construction ( John wiped the table clean ) have been argued to depend on the positive setting of TCP (e.g. Snyder 2001, Sugisaki & Isobe 2000); and both are typical of Talmy's satellite-framed languages (e.g. Talmy 1985:68,104). Likewise, researchers have argued that a spatial PP (such as under the bridge ) can convert a pure manner-of-motion activity predicate (Sue swam for/*in 15 minutes ) into an accomplishment ( Sue swam under the bridge in 15 minutes ) only in [+ TCP] languages (Beck & Snyder 2001, Gehrke 2008), and only in satellite-framed languages (cf. Aske 1989:6-7). This chapter examines the precise role of TCP in the linguistic expression of motion events. One of my central claims will be that TCP should be understood as the availability, or unavailability, of a specific rule of semantic composition, which I term To appear in Violeta Demonte and Louise McNally (eds.) Telicity, Change, and State .
    [Show full text]
  • MR Harley Miyagawa Syntax of Ditransitives
    Syntax of Ditransitives Heidi Harley and Shigeru Miyagawa (in press, Oxford Research Encyclopedia of Linguistics) July 2016 Summary Keywords 1. Structure for the Two Internal Arguments 2. Underlying Order 3. Meaning Differences 4. Case, Clitic 5. The Structure of Ditransitives 6. Nominalization Asymmetries 6.1. A Morphological Account of the Nominalization Asymmetry 6.2. –kata Nominalization in Japanese and Myer’s Generalization 6.3 Selectional Accounts of the Nominalization Asymmetry 6.4 Applicative vs Small Clause Approaches to the DOC. 7. Constraints on the Dative/DOC Alternation 7.1 Morphological Constraints 7.2 Lexical Semantic Constraints 7.3 Information-Structural and Sentential Prosody Constraints 8. Overview and Prospects Further Reading References Summary Ditransitive predicates select for two internal arguments, and hence minimally entail the participation of three entities in the event described by the verb. Canonical ditranstive verbs include give, show and teach; in each case, the verb requires an Agent (a giver, shower or teacher, respectively), a Theme (the thing given, shown or taught) and a Goal (the recipient, viewer, or student). The property of requiring two internal arguments makes ditransitive verbs syntactically unique. Selection in generative grammar is often modelled as syntactic sisterhood, so ditranstive verbs immediately raise the question of whether a verb might have two sisters, requiring a ternary-branching structure, or whether one of the two internal arguments is not in a sisterhood relation with the verb. Another important property of English ditransitive constructions is the two syntactic structures associated with them. In the so-called “Double Object Construction”, or DOC, the Goal and Theme both are simple NPs and appear following the verb in the order V-Goal-Theme.
    [Show full text]
  • The Structure of Small Clause Predication
    173 Azusa Yokogoshi The Structure of Small Clause Predication The Textual Functions of Their Heads Azusa YOKOGOSHI 1. Introduction The structure of small clauses, which are exemplified in the italicized portions of (1), has been one of the most controversial topics in generative grammar. (1) a. We consider Mary honest. b. We want Mary happy. Various analyses have been proposed for the structure of small clauses. It is widely assumed that small clauses have the same categorial status and internal architecture regardless of the matrix verbs selecting them. However, as recently discussed by Contreras (1995), Baker (1997), and Basilico (2003) among others, there is good reason to argue that the structure of small clauses should not be treated uniformly. However, their analyses differ considerably as to the classification of small clauses. Apparently, the matrix verbs in (1) seem to select small clauses with the same structure. As will be shown, however, small clauses selected by consider and want differ in their syntactic and semantic properties and therefore should be treated as having different structures. The verbs which behave like consider and want are given in (2a,b), respectively. (2) a. believe, consider, find, imagine, judge, perceive, prove, regard, suspect, take, ... b. expect, fear, hate, like, love, need, want, ... (cf. Declerck (1991)) The selection of small clauses of the matrix verbs is textual in the sense that it is determined not only by syntactic but also semantic factors.1 It will be argued that the 1 The concept of “text” would not only include discourse but also some other factors. Readers refer to Halliday (1978) as to the notion of text, although I would not strictly follow the framework of Halliday’s systemic functional grammar here.
    [Show full text]
  • Exceptional Case Marking in Japanese and Optional Feature Transmission*
    EXCEPTIONAL CASE MARKING IN JAPANESE AND OPTIONAL FEATURE TRANSMISSION* Hajime Takeuchi Nanzan University 1. Introduction In this paper, I present an analysis of exceptional Case marking (ECM) in Japanese. A typical example is shown in (1). (1) a. Taroo-wa [Yuki-ga baka da to] omot-teiru. T-TOP [Y-NOM stupid COP COMP think-PROG ‘Taro thinks that Yuki is stupid.’ b. Taroo-wa [Yuki-o baka da to] omot-teiru [[ T-TOP [Y-ACC stupid COP COMP think-PROG ‘Taro thinks that Yuki is stupid.’ A certain class of verbs in Japanese takes a clausal complement with an overt complementizer, to, and the subject in the embedded clause can be marked with either nominative or accusative Case without any semantic difference. There are two major analyses for the Japanese ECM in the literature. One is the obligatory raising analysis initially proposed in Kuno (1976) and examined in detail in Authier (1991), Tanaka (1992), and Ura (1994). The other is the optional raising analysis discussed in Bruening (2001), Hiraiwa (2001, 2005) and Tanaka (2002). In this latter analysis, the accusative Case on the embedded subject is licensed via Agree. The proposal herein pursues the latter and aims for making it more precise. Crucial for the analysis presented in this paper is the proposal by Chomsky (2008) that a phase head transmits its features to its complement. Thus, C transmits its phi-features and edge feature (EF) to T, and only then does T become capable of licensing nominative Case. I argue that feature transmission (FT) is optional in certain limited cases, and that this makes * An earlier version of the material of this paper was presented in the 8th Workshop of the International Research Project on the Comparative Syntax and Language Acquisition, held at Nanzan University in March, 2010 and in Generative Lyceum, held at Kwansei Gakuin University in May, 2010.
    [Show full text]
  • Against the Predp Theory of Small Clauses Ora Matushansky
    Against the PredP Theory of Small Clauses Ora Matushansky Since Bowers 1993, it has been accepted that nonverbal small clauses are headed by a functional head, Pred0, whose function is to obligato- rily mediate all nonverbal predication. I argue against this hypothesis by critically reanalyzing the original syntactic arguments for PredP, examining possible semantic support for mediated predication, and reviewing the putative crosslinguistic evidence for overt equivalence of Pred0. I first demonstrate that the facts originally taken as motivating a functional head in small clauses can now be accounted for by inde- pendently needed assumptions. I then show that standard Montagovian semantics treating NPs, APs, and PPs as unsaturated functions requires no mediating projection and that suggested alternative meanings for Pred0 either fail or cannot be used as motivation for its existence. Finally, I provide evidence that the syntax of copular particles and other “overt predicators” is different from that expected of Pred0 in such ways that they cannot be taken as prima facie evidence for it either. I sketch an alternative theory linking the use of predicative particles to nominal predication and provide evidence for it from cross- linguistic lexicalization patterns of copular particles. In sum, neither theoretical nor empirical considerations require a mediating functional head in small clauses, and therefore the PredP hypothesis should be abandoned. Keywords: small clause, PredP, copular particles, predication, copulas 1 The Structure of the Small Clause: An Introduction Since Williams 1975 and Stowell 1981, 1983, it has been assumed that predication is possible in the absence of a verb in examples like (1a–c), but also those like (2a–b).
    [Show full text]
  • A Look at Tesniere's E19 Elements Through the Lens of Modern
    A Look at Tesnière’s Éléments through the Lens of Modern Syntactic Theory Timothy Osborne 615 6th Street Apt. 110 Kirkland, WA 98033 USA [email protected] Abstract nent theoretician to have rejected the binary di- vision of the clause into a subject and predicate A recent project to produce a much belated and to have replaced this division with verb cen- English translation of Lucien Tesnière’s trality. The placement of the verb as the root of Éléments de syntaxe structurale has provided all syntactic structure was the all-important nov- the opportunity for an in depth look at elty (and the main act of genius) in his theory. Tesnière’s theory of syntax. This contribu- Given verb centrality, the theory of syntax that tion examines a few aspects of Tesnière’s Tesnière was proposing could not help but be work through the lens of modern syntactic theory. Tesnière’s understandings of constit- construed as a DG. uents and phrases, auxiliary verbs, preposi- Despite the fact that Tesnière is widely tions, gapping, right node raising, proposi- acknowledged as the father of an entire stream tional infinitives, and exocentric structures of syntactic theory, most syntacticians and are all briefly considered. Concerning some grammarians lack exposure to his work. Few of these areas, we see that Tesnière was vi- grammarians have actually read Tesnière’s Élé- sionary with his analysis, whereas in other ments de syntaxe structurale, largely because an areas, modern syntactic theory now rejects English translation of the Éléments is absent his account. Of particular interest is the fact from the world of linguistics.
    [Show full text]
  • Approaches to the Structure of English Small Clauses Vivien Tomacsek
    Approaches to the Structure of English Small Clauses Vivien Tomacsek 1 Introduction1 The topic of small clauses did not become a target of much research until the 1980s — before that, predicative [NP XP] sequences occurring after main verbs were not really tackled by linguists. Within the Government and Binding framework, two main opposing ideas were formulated concerning small clauses, but there is disagreement from many aspects even among those working in the same theoretical framework. Small Clause theorists claim that the [NP XP] string in [V NP XP] constructions should be considered a single constituent; however, there has been no conclusion on the categorial status of small clauses. Various proposals have been made to solve the issue and provide a synthesised resolution to this problematic issue; however, none of them has been accepted entirely yet. The general aim of this paper is to demonstrate the complexity of the small clause construction analysed in frameworks which rely mostly on the Government and Binding and earlier frameworks, before the rise of Minimalism. The thesis attempts to represent both the theory that supports the existence of small clauses and the one that rejects it in chapter 2. This part will also argue for the acceptability of the clausal interpretation of the postverbal [NP XP] strings where the NP and the XP are in a subject-predicate relationship, and then chapter 3 will review the major proposals for the categorial status of small clauses, providing counterarguments for each. Finally, chapter 4 will summarise the most important points of the paper. 1I would like to acknowledge the expert guidance of my former Syntax lecturer, Krisztina Szécsényi, who encouraged and supported me to deal with Syntax in greater depth.
    [Show full text]
  • Criterial Freezing in Small Clauses and the Cartography of Copular Constructions
    Ur Shlonsky and Luigi Rizzi Criterial Freezing in small clauses and the cartography of copular constructions Abstract: Criterial Freezing is a particular instance of freezing arising in criterial configurations, i.e., in configurations dedicated to the expression of scope- discourse properties. Recent proposals (e.g., Rizzi 2015a,b) try to deduce criterial freezing effects from more elementary ingredients of linguistic computations, most notably from the labeling algorithm proposed in Chomsky (2013). In this paper, we explore the consequences of this approach for the syntax of small clauses. This leads us to work out a cartography of small clauses, both in selected domains (as in English and Romance), and as main clauses (as in Hebrew, following Shlonsky 2000). The cartography involves distinct subject positions in the structure of the IP, which are associated with distinct interpretive properties at the interface. Special attention is devoted to the syntax of small clauses with a non-verbal, pronominal copula in Hebrew. Direct and inverse copular sentences are analyzed according to the proposed structural map, and various freezing effects are traced back to the theoretical ingredients introduced at the outset. Keywords: Criterial freezing, copula, Hebrew copular sentence, labeling, Subject Criterion, small clause, subject position(s), PRON, Inverse copular sentence, Focus, Smuggling 1 Introduction Among the various manifestations of freezing phenomena, a case that has attracted significant attention lately is the case of “criterial freezing”.
    [Show full text]
  • English for Practical Purposes 9
    ENGLISH FOR PRACTICAL PURPOSES 9 CONTENTS Chapter 1: Introduction of English Grammar Chapter 2: Sentence Chapter 3: Noun Chapter 4: Verb Chapter 5: Pronoun Chapter 6: Adjective Chapter 7: Adverb Chapter 8: Preposition Chapter 9: Conjunction Chapter 10: Punctuation Chapter 11: Tenses Chapter 12: Voice Chapter 1 Introduction to English grammar English grammar is the body of rules that describe the structure of expressions in the English language. This includes the structure of words, phrases, clauses and sentences. There are historical, social, and regional variations of English. Divergences from the grammardescribed here occur in some dialects of English. This article describes a generalized present-dayStandard English, the form of speech found in types of public discourse including broadcasting,education, entertainment, government, and news reporting, including both formal and informal speech. There are certain differences in grammar between the standard forms of British English, American English and Australian English, although these are inconspicuous compared with the lexical andpronunciation differences. Word classes and phrases There are eight word classes, or parts of speech, that are distinguished in English: nouns, determiners, pronouns, verbs, adjectives,adverbs, prepositions, and conjunctions. (Determiners, traditionally classified along with adjectives, have not always been regarded as a separate part of speech.) Interjections are another word class, but these are not described here as they do not form part of theclause and sentence structure of the language. Nouns, verbs, adjectives, and adverbs form open classes – word classes that readily accept new members, such as the nouncelebutante (a celebrity who frequents the fashion circles), similar relatively new words. The others are regarded as closed classes.
    [Show full text]