Hypothetisierungstagung 22.-24.2.05

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Hypothetisierungstagung 22.-24.2.05 1 Die Bedeutung des Hypothetischen in den Naturwissenschaften The Significance of the Hypothetical in the Natural Sciences Internationale Konferenz/ International Conference 22. - 24. Februar 2005 Tagungsort/ Place: Fürstenzimmer, Schloß Hohentübingen Gefördert durch/ Sponsored by: http://www.fritz-thyssen-stiftung.de/ Unterstützt und mitorganisiert von/ Supported and co-organized by: Archives Henri Poincaré http://www.univ-nancy2.fr/poincare Université Nancy 2 Kurzfassungen/ Abstracts The Significance of the Hypothetical in the Natural Sciences – Abstracts 2 Andreas Bartels (Bonn) no claims about their actual objects, but only [email protected] serve to guide investigation. They are a rich Hypotheticity and Realism and precious expedient. in Duhem and Popper My historical aim is to show the continuity between Poincaré’s epistemology As a result of Popper´s philosophy on the and of Vaihinger’s conception of simulation: philosophy of science, hypotheticity and in order to solve certain problems, or to realism are not considered mutually discover new facts or new laws, the scientist inconsistent. But, as Pierre Duhem´s work has to behave “as if” certain facts or states of reminds us, the compatibility of hypotheticity things existed, that is, to simulate their and realism is by no means self-evident. existence. The following problem will guide Duhem sharply distinguishes between two my presentation: how is it possible to reach ways of knowing about natural phenomena: truth (in the sense or understanding of our two On the one hand, mechanical models, which authors) through falsity (that is by assuming lend themselves to visualization, are held to facts that one knows are not real, or are even represent the “hidden causes” of phenomena impossible)? and thereby to “explain” them. On the other hand, theories give us hypothetical mecha- Nadine de Courtenay (Paris) nisms, which have a purely descriptive status. [email protected] Thus for Duhem, hypotheticity and realism On Assumptions in Boltzmann’s concerning scientific theories must exclude “Principles of Mechanics” each other. Reassessing Popper´s concept of “hypotheticity”, the talk aims to identify the The first chapter of Boltzmann’s Principles of conceptual changes that finally made Mechanics counts, at the turn of the 19th and philosophers of science think that 20th century, amongst the most decided and hypotheticity and realism are compatible. argued statements of the hypothetical character of science. After sketching Christophe Bouriau (Nancy) Boltzmann’s opening views on the [email protected] indispensability of hypothesis, I will examine The Role of the “As If” in the Natural how they contribute to shaping his Sciences : Vaihinger and Poincaré presentation of mechanics. I will contrast his choice to start from Starting from the analyses of Vaihinger and seven “assumptions” with the axiomatic style Poincaré, I want to bring out the decisive role adopted in Hertz’ Mechanics and discuss to of what could be called “working hypotheses” what extent a parallel can be drawn, as was in the natural sciences. In adopting a suggested at the time, between this original hypothesis like this one proceeds as if mode of presentation and the place granted to something existed, without assuming that it assumptions in Meinong’s analysis of actually exists. Hypotheses in the strict sense, knowledge. Turning to the content of in contrast, always have the pretension to Boltzmann’s assumptions, in particular to the truth. one dealing with velocity, I will show how For Vaihinger and Poincaré, the limit they bring out a new understanding of the of an hypothesis in the strict sense, resides in nature of hypothesis and, thus, of the its pretension to explanation : it relies on the conception of scientific activity in general. principle of causality which, for our two authors, is an eminently dubious principle. Working hypotheses, on the other hand, make The Significance of the Hypothetical in the Natural Sciences – Abstracts 3 Moritz Epple (Frankfurt am Main) always several possible scientific theories that [email protected] fit the same evidence, but that contradict one Felix Hausdorff’s “Considered Empiricism” another. Confirmation holism is often combined with semantic holism: the meaning Felix Hausdorff, it seems, turned to research of theoretical terms is not fixed by the in set theory, the field of his main empirical evidence, but consists in inferential mathematical achievements, for philosophical relations among these terms. Furthermore, reasons. In the late 1890’s, he engaged in a semantic holism implies that there is no clear- radical critique of contemporary metaphysical cut distinction between theoretical terms and beliefs in the possibility of ascertaining observational terms. ‘absolute’ structures of time and space. In Against this background, the aim of order to frame his arguments in his main this paper is to argue for two claims: (1) The philosophical monograph, the Chaos in underdetermination thesis together with kosmischer Auslese of 1897, he drew on semantic holism implies that all scientific notions of Cantorian set theory which he had knowledge is hypothetical. In particular, the learned immediately before completing his notion of a final, universal and true theory book. cannot be conceived within this framework. The paper will explore Hausdorff’s Consequently, it cannot be claimed that our arguments in some detail. It will outline how current theories approach such a final theory his critique of metaphysics led him to and that they possess a certain degree of formulate a ‘considered’ version of verisimilitude in comparison to such a theory. empiricism—an empiricism which is aware (2) The underdetermination thesis together that it is necessary in the sciences to use with semantic holism does not prevent a notions (such as time and space but many rational comparison between contradicting others as well) which can be made precise theories of the same domain that were mathematically, but not uniquely. According developed in the history of science or that are to Hausdorff, empirical evidence always put forward at the same time. Such a leaves room for different mathematical comparison can in principle lead to singling conceptions of time, space, etc.; critical out one particular theory as our best candidate mathematical analysis is needed to delineate for a true theory of a given domain at a given the spectrum of possible mathematizations in time. In this case, it is reasonable to adopt a each case. In this way, the conceptual basis of realistic attitude towards such a theory as a empirical science always retains hypothetical whole. This is a pragmatic, hypothetical elements. Examples of such an analysis can realism—in short, a version of Popperian be found in Hausdorff’s lecture course on realism deprived of the idea of approaching a “Time and Space” of 1903/4. Hausdorff’s final theory. ‘considered’ empiricism will briefly be compared to Poincare’s conventionalist views Gerhard Heinzmann (Nancy) and to the later views of the early Vienna [email protected] circle (in particular, to Moritz Schlick’s). Hypotheses and Conventions: From Poincaré to Logical Empiricism. Michael Esfeld (Lausanne) [email protected] What can be the role of experience in Conjectural Realism determining and justifying scientific knowledge? Poincaré’s answer was highly Confirmation holism in the sense of the complex, but the main idea could be Duhem-Quine thesis implies an characterized as follows: the role of underdetermination thesis: empirical evidence experience is above all to guide us in the does not determine scientific theory. There are choice of conventions. Science is not simply The Significance of the Hypothetical in the Natural Sciences – Abstracts 4 worked up out of experience, but produces Holger Lyre (Bonn) itself the very ‘facts of science’ by working [email protected] them up linguistically and conceptually from Theory Underdetermination experience. No judgement is absolutely forced by Empirical Evidence? on us by the data. Indeed, experimental data force us to make a judgement relative to a The thesis of theory underdetermination given language. (TUD) asserts that no given body of empirical It was an important insight of data or evidence uniquely determines a scientists and philosophers at the end of the scientific theory—it is usually seen as one of 19th century that pure data can never actually the most powerful arguments against be reached in the framework of an empirical scientific realism, the doctrine that the approach. If this is right, the truth of theoretical terms in our best and mature statements is rather the expression of their scientific theories genuinely refer. In this adequacy regarding the choice of a scientific paper I shall critically examine the basis of system. This means that truth in science takes the TUD thesis, first by comparing it to and on a hypothetical character in principle. distinguishing it from neighboring theses such Now, if all languages could be as the Duhem-Quine holism thesis, the translated into each other, there would be a conventionality thesis and the problem of universal invariant. The conventional choice induction. Secondly, I shall ask the often of language was also only a matter of neglected question whether there really exist linguistics. If no language could be translated specifiable and convincing examples of the into another, we would have the most radical TUD thesis in modern
Recommended publications
  • What Is This Thing Called Knowledge?
    what is this thing called knowledge? What is knowledge? Where does it come from? What kinds of knowledge are there? Can we know anything at all? This lucid and engaging introduction grapples with these central questions in the theory of knowledge, offering a clear, non-partisan view of the main themes of epistemology. Both traditional issues and contemporary ideas are discussed in sixteen easily digestible chapters, each of which conclude with a useful summary of the main ideas discussed, study questions, annotated further reading, and a guide to internet resources. Each chapter also features text boxes providing bite-sized summaries of key concepts and major philosophers, and clear and interesting examples are used throughout. The book concludes with an annotated guide to general introductions to epistemology, a glossary of key terms, and a summary of the main examples used in epistemology.This is an ideal first textbook on the theory of knowledge for undergraduates coming to philosophy for the first time. The third edition has been revised and updated throughout and features two new chapters, on religious knowledge and scientific knowledge, as part of a whole new section on what kinds of knowledge there are. In addition, the text as a whole has been refreshed to keep it up to date with current developments. Duncan Pritchard FRSE is Professor of Philosophy at the University of Edinburgh, UK. His main research area is epistemology, and he has published widely in this field, including the books Epistemic Luck (2005), Knowledge (2009), The Nature and Value of Knowledge (with A.Millar and A.Haddock, 2010), and Epistemological Disjunctivism (2012).
    [Show full text]
  • Falsification and Falsificationism
    Available online at www.worldscientificnews.com WSN 51 (2016) 62-71 EISSN 2392-2192 Falsification and falsificationism Karol Kraiński Faculty of Economics and Management, Nicolaus Copernicus University, 13a Gagarina Str., 87-100 Toruń, Poland E-mail address: [email protected] ABSTRACT Falsification is not meant to refute the theory, but only allows you to specify the probability of the truth of posed too. This action can be described as a set of hypotheses that have a researcher to help explain and describe the world around us. Keywords: falsification; falsificationism; counterfeiting; forg ery; fraud 1. INTRODUCTION Falsification (trans. NLC. Falsificatio = counterfeiting, forgery, fraud) ang. falsification; Ger. Falsifikatio. Proceedings aiming to overturn a sentence, that is, an attempt to demonstrate its falsity. Such a procedure usually involves three stages [6]: 1. derivation of appropriate logical consequences of forged hypothesis; those consequences must be sentences observation; 2. execution of relevant experience (observation, experiment, measurement); 3. confrontation with the results derived consequence experience and any decision to reject the hypothesis. Falsifies is usually not a single thesis, but some of their team. Falsification is the criterion on the basis of a scientific conception of science (K. R. Popper), according to which: a) the thesis must be subject to falsification; World Scientific News 51 (2016) 62-71 b) does not attach much importance to the verification procedure, since the assertion can sometimes completely subvert and never can not be completely verified (with the exception of statements regarding finite and relatively not-great number of objects); c) believes that the introduction of science thesis is not even verified valuable than refraining from introducing too insufficiently verified.
    [Show full text]
  • Astronomy As a Science
    Theme 2: Astronomy as a Science 2.1 Astronomy and Astrology For most of their history, up to the 17th century, astronomy and astrology were completely in- tertwined: for example, astronomers devoted much time and effort to compiling tables of pla- netary positions, not only for navigation and time-keeping but also to aid in the casting of horo- scopes. Nowadays, almost everyone would agree that astronomy is a science but astrology is not. Why is this? What do we mean by the statement “astronomy is a science” anyway? Are there any parts of astronomy which are not science (and, conversely, any parts of astrology which are science)? This is the subject matter of philosophers of science, who aim to provide (1) a descriptive ac- count of science (what scientists do), (2) a normative account (what scientists ought to do) and (3) a definition (what distinguishes science from other pursuits). It has to be said that most working scientists do not take philosophers of science seriously—and, indeed, some philoso- phers of science do rather invite this reaction because of the lack of any apparent connection between their descriptions and scientists’ experiences. However, the serious issues around the definition of “science” which have arisen in recent years, particularly in the USA, strongly indi- cate that working scientists should try to develop a clear mental picture of the definition and practice of science, in order to be able to defend it against incursions by pseudoscience. [As far as I know, nobody has yet tried to demand “balanced treatment” for astrology in astronomy courses—but you never know!] 2.2 The Scientific Method If pushed, most scientists would say that science is a process (a way of working and thinking) and not simply a body of knowledge—though the acquisition of a pre-existing body of know- ledge is usually necessary in order to participate in the process of science.
    [Show full text]
  • Copernicanism and the Typicality in Time
    Copernicanism and the Typicality in Time Milan M. Cirkovi´c´ 1;2, Amedeo Balbi3 1 Astronomical Observatory of Belgrade, Volgina 7 11000 Belgrade, Serbia 2 Future of Humanity Institute, Faculty of Philosophy, University of Oxford, Suite 8, Littlegate House, 16/17 St Ebbe's Street, Oxford, OX1 1PT, UK 3 Dipartimento di Fisica, Universit`adi Roma \Tor Vergata", Via della Ricerca Scientifica, 00133 Roma, Italy Abstract. How special (or not) is the epoch we are living in? What is the appropriate reference class for embedding the observations made at the present time? How probable { or else { is anything we observe in the fulness of time? Contemporary cosmology and astrobiology bring those seemingly old-fashioned philosophical issues back into focus. There are several examples of contemporary research which use the assumption of typicality in time (or temporal Copernicanism) explicitly or implicitly, while not truly elaborating upon the meaning of this assumption. The present paper brings attention to the underlying and often uncritically accepted assumptions in these cases. It also aims to defend a more radical position that typicality in time is not { and cannot ever be { well-defined, in contrast to the typicality in space, and the typicality in various specific parameter spaces. This, of course, does not mean that we are atypical in time; instead, the notion of typicality in time is necessarily somewhat vague and restricted. In principle, it could be strengthened by further defining the relevant context, e.g., by referring to typicality within the Solar lifetime, or some similar restricting clause. Keywords: cosmology: theory { extragalactic astronomy { astrobiology { futures studies { history and philosophy of astronomy { Copernicanism { anthropic principle { extraterrestrial intelligence arXiv:1907.08947v1 [physics.hist-ph] 21 Jul 2019 2 I think we agree, the past is over.
    [Show full text]
  • Exploring the Nature of Models in Science, Philosophy of Science, and Science Education
    EXPLORING THE NATURE OF MODELS IN SCIENCE, PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE, AND SCIENCE EDUCATION BY JEREMY J. BELARMINO Submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Educational Policy Studies in the Graduate College of the University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign, 2017 Urbana, Illinois Doctoral Committee: Professor Nicholas Burbules Associate Professor Christopher Roy Higgins Professor Emeritus William F. Brewer Professor Fouad Abd-El-Khalick, University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill ABSTRACT The term model is ubiquitous in science, philosophy of science, and science education. Although there is no general consensus regarding its definition, the traditional approach in all of these disciplines has always been to view models as some kind of representation of reality. Recently, however, there has been a move towards non- representational and deflationary accounts of modeling that eschew the notion that models must come equipped with both necessary and sufficient conditions. Following the philosophy of the later Wittgenstein, I develop my own narrative concerning modeling called the integration account. The integration account maintains that models are comprised of various elements that are organized in a distinctive way in order to solve scientific problems. Some of these elements include, but are not limited to: theories, laws, theory-ladenness of ideas, choice, funding availability, feasibility, social relationships, and even serendipity. The integration account encounters some difficulty when it is applied to the field of science education, in particular science teaching. The latter’s pedagogical project appears to run contrary to the integration account’s commitment to solving scientific problems. As a result, I propose that pedagogical models and scientific models be viewed as separate kinds of models, each replete with their own separate function.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 10 Philosophy of Science
    Chapter 10 Philosophy of Science (Alexander Bird, University of Edinburgh) Introduction The central concerns of the philosophy of science as a whole divide into two areas. One of these areas, perhaps the traditionally more dominant side, encompasses such questions as: Is scientific knowledge possible? If so, how? What methods of reasoning do scientists use? What is the role of observation and experiment in scientific reasoning? Are theories justified that concern entities and processes that cannot be observed? This area is where philosophy of science overlaps with epistemology, the theory of knowledge. The second area is situated where philosophy of science overlaps with metaphysics. Here we are concerned not with whether and why our theories amount to knowledge, but instead we focus on what our theories are about—in the most general terms. For example, the world contains laws of nature and is divided up into different kinds of things. Almost all scientific theories concern one or other of these two general features of the world—or at least their subject matter will reflect these features. Associated with features is the fact that most theories attempt to explain some phenomenon or other. These are metaphysical topics. In this chapter we shall look first at the second area, metaphysical philosophy of science, before returning to the first, epistemological philosophy of science. The metaphysics of science I mentioned three key components in the metaphysical part of the philosophy of science: laws of nature, natural kinds, and explanation. We can see these all operating together in John Dalton’s atomic hypothesis. The starting point is the obvious fact that chemists deal with different substances.
    [Show full text]
  • Reconsidering the Foundations of Thermodynamics from an Engineering Perspective
    Portland State University PDXScholar Mathematics and Statistics Faculty Fariborz Maseeh Department of Mathematics Publications and Presentations and Statistics 7-2018 Reconsidering the Foundations of Thermodynamics from an Engineering Perspective Terry Bristol Portland State University Follow this and additional works at: https://pdxscholar.library.pdx.edu/mth_fac Part of the Engineering Commons, and the Physical Sciences and Mathematics Commons Let us know how access to this document benefits ou.y Citation Details Bristol, T. Reconsidering the Foundations of Thermodynamics from an Engineering Perspective. Preprints 2018, 2018070139 (doi: 10.20944/preprints201807.0139.v1). This Pre-Print is brought to you for free and open access. It has been accepted for inclusion in Mathematics and Statistics Faculty Publications and Presentations by an authorized administrator of PDXScholar. Please contact us if we can make this document more accessible: [email protected]. Preprints (www.preprints.org) | NOT PEER-REVIEWED | Posted: 9 July 2018 doi:10.20944/preprints201807.0139.v1 1 Article 2 Reconsidering the Foundations of Thermodynamics 3 from an Engineering Perspective 4 Terry Bristol 5 Institute for Science Engineering and Public Policy, Portland State University; [email protected] 6 Received: date; Accepted: date; Published: date 7 Abstract: Currently, there are two approaches to the foundations of thermodynamics. One, 8 associated with the mechanistical Clausius-Boltzmann tradition, is favored by the physics 9 community. The other, associated with the post-mechanical Carnot tradition, is favored by the 10 engineering community. The bold hypothesis is that the conceptual foundation of engineering 11 thermodynamics is the more comprehensive. Therefore, contrary to the dominant consensus, 12 engineering thermodynamics (ET) represents the true foundation of thermodynamics.
    [Show full text]
  • The Statistical Crisis in Science Stijn Debrouwere (Author), Prof
    The Statistical Crisis in Science Stijn Debrouwere (author), Prof. Dr. Els Goetghebeur (advisor) Preface What can we say about the statistical crisis in science that has not already been said? Eminent scientists like Paul Meehl, Jakob Cohen and John Ioannidis have already done a great job pinpointing the problems with P-values, null hypothesis significance testing, nonreplicable research, sloppy statistics and fishing expeditions. At the other end of the spectrum journalists at The Atlantic, The New Yorker, FiveThirtyEight and The New York Times have done a surprisingly good job of translating these issues to a lay audience. What is left? What is left is the space in between: for many working scientists the arguments in the statistical literature are too abstract and I have a sneaking suspicion that nobody has ever bothered to double-check the somewhat convoluted calculations in John Ioannidis’ otherwise wonderful Why Most Published Research Findings Are False. On the other hand lay accounts do not treat the problem with enough fidelity to satisfy those who might not be statistical experts as such but do regularly have to interpret t-tests and regression analyses. Yet ultimately it is these students and doctors and working scientists who are the key audience for publications about the statistical crisis in science, because they decide what tomorrow’s statistical practices will look like. I have used this dissertation as an exercise in statistical writing for such an audience of not-quite-experts, not-quite-laymen. To the dissertation committee reading this dissertation I therefore ask that you please do not get frustrated when it takes five paragraphs to explain what power or sensitivity or positive predictive value means.
    [Show full text]
  • Falsification and Falsificationism
    Available online at www.worldscientificnews.com WSN 51 (2016) 44-53 EISSN 2392-2192 Falsification and falsificationism Karol Kraiński Faculty of Economics and Management, Nicolaus Copernicus University, 13a Gagarina Str., 87-100 Toruń, Poland E-mail address: [email protected] ABSTRACT Falsification is not meant to refute the theory, but only allows you to specify the probability of the truth of posed too. This action can be described as a set of hypotheses that have a researcher to help explain and describe the world around us. Keywords: falsification, falsificationism, counterfeiting, forg ery, fraud 1. INTRODUCTION Falsification (trans. NLC. Falsificatio = counterfeiting, forgery, fraud) eng. falsification; Ger. Falsifikatio. Proceedings aiming to overturn a sentence, that is, an attempt to demonstrate its falsity. Such a procedure usually involves three stages [6]: 1. derivation of appropriate logical consequences of forged hypothesis; those consequences must be sentences observation; 2. execution of relevant experience (observation, experiment, measurement); 3. confrontation with the results derived consequence experience and any decision to reject the hypothesis. Falsifies is usually not a single thesis, but some of their team. Falsification is the criterion on the basis of a scientific conception of science (K. R. Popper), according to which: a) the thesis must be subject to falsification; World Scientific News 51 (2016) 44-53 b) does not attach much importance to the verification procedure, since the assertion can sometimes completely subvert and never can not be completely verified (with the exception of statements regarding finite and relatively not-great number of objects); c) believes that the introduction of science thesis is not even verified valuable than refraining from introducing too insufficiently verified.
    [Show full text]