Exploring the Nature of Models in Science, Philosophy of Science, and Science Education

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Exploring the Nature of Models in Science, Philosophy of Science, and Science Education EXPLORING THE NATURE OF MODELS IN SCIENCE, PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE, AND SCIENCE EDUCATION BY JEREMY J. BELARMINO Submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Educational Policy Studies in the Graduate College of the University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign, 2017 Urbana, Illinois Doctoral Committee: Professor Nicholas Burbules Associate Professor Christopher Roy Higgins Professor Emeritus William F. Brewer Professor Fouad Abd-El-Khalick, University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill ABSTRACT The term model is ubiquitous in science, philosophy of science, and science education. Although there is no general consensus regarding its definition, the traditional approach in all of these disciplines has always been to view models as some kind of representation of reality. Recently, however, there has been a move towards non- representational and deflationary accounts of modeling that eschew the notion that models must come equipped with both necessary and sufficient conditions. Following the philosophy of the later Wittgenstein, I develop my own narrative concerning modeling called the integration account. The integration account maintains that models are comprised of various elements that are organized in a distinctive way in order to solve scientific problems. Some of these elements include, but are not limited to: theories, laws, theory-ladenness of ideas, choice, funding availability, feasibility, social relationships, and even serendipity. The integration account encounters some difficulty when it is applied to the field of science education, in particular science teaching. The latter’s pedagogical project appears to run contrary to the integration account’s commitment to solving scientific problems. As a result, I propose that pedagogical models and scientific models be viewed as separate kinds of models, each replete with their own separate function. Scientific models should only be used by professional scientists to solve scientific problems and not used as teaching tools by science teachers. The reverse is also true. Pedagogical models can still be used by science teachers even if they have run their course when it comes to solving scientific problems. ii For my wife Amanda Belarmino and my parents Jesus and Nora Belarmino iii ACKNOWLEDGMENTS This project would not have been possible without the guidance and feedback of my Dissertation Committee. Bill, your thought-provoking comments have certainly given me a lot to think about when it comes to the cognitive science of science and how students represent their knowledge. Chris, we have known each other for a long time now. Our discussions on Plato, Aristotle, Arendt, and MacIntyre have been some of the most exhilarating in my life. Fouad, I would like to personally thank you for embracing me into your NOS (Nature of Science) circle. Had we not met, I never would have pursued my interest in philosophy of science, let alone written a dissertation in the field. And last, but certainly not least, I would like to acknowledge Nick Burbules, my advisor and dissertation Chair. Thank you for always believing in this project and me. There were several moments when I had serious reservations about both, but your undeterred confidence in me never allowed me to give up. Most importantly, I need to express my gratitude to my family, especially my wife, Amanda, who has been a constant source of inspiration and reassurance. The completion of this project is a testament of your unrelenting care and support. I would also like to recognize my parents, whose lives were the very embodiment of eudaimonia. May you rest in peace. iv Table of Contents Chapter 1. Introduction ..................................................................................................................... 1 Part I Chapter 2. Three Accounts of Representation ................................................................................ 10 Chapter 3. The Integration Account of Modeling .......................................................................... 43 Chapter 4. Pierre Duhem’s Critique of Modeling .......................................................................... 76 Part II Chapter 5. The Role of Models in Science Education .................................................................... 95 Chapter 6. Three Case Studies on Modeling ................................................................................ 122 Chapter 7. Models Revisited ........................................................................................................ 152 Bibliography ................................................................................................................................. 178 v Chapter 1 Introduction 1.1 Plato’s Model Mythos In Book 7 of the Republic, Plato tells his audience an amazing tale. He welcomes them to use their imaginations to envision a cave that extends far beneath the Earth’s surface. Deep inside this cave, towards the very bottom, there are very unique prisoners. These prisoners are shackled in a way that they are forced to stare at the cave wall in front of them; they cannot move their heads from side to side or even look behind them. Far behind the prisoners, towards the cave’s entrance, is a burning fire. In between the fire and the prisoners there is a slightly elevated path. On this path, there are people carrying various statues of everyday objects from one side of the cave to the other. Now the statue carriers are holding the statues in such a way that the shadows of the statues are visible to the prisoners, but the statues themselves are not. Because the prisoners cannot turn their heads, they do not know who or what is producing the shadows. In fact, from their perspective, they do not even know that they are looking at shadows; for all they know, the shadows are the only genuine reality. One day, however, one of the prisoners breaks free from his shackles. Once unfettered, he immediately turns around and follows a path propelling him towards the entrance of the cave. As he is walking, he is astonished at what he sees; for he sees statues that resemble the ones he has been staring at his entire life. After considering the statues and their likenesses on the wall, he realizes that the two cannot be a coincidence. The objects on the wall are nothing more than the shadows of these statues. At this moment, the prisoner’s entire reality is turned upside down. 1 Everything he thought was real was only a mere likeness, a dismal chimera. For his entire life he had witnessed the most elaborate puppet show ever produced, unfortunately none of it was real. He wants to turn back the hands of time, return to his rightful place in front of the wall, and call out the names of shadows again. But he knows that this is impossible. Instead, he summons up the courage to keep climbing towards the entrance of the cave. As he approaches the entrance, he sees a burning fire and realizes that it is the mechanism that has been perpetuating the farce known as his life. He wants to put it out, but he cannot. So he keeps on climbing. As he gets closer to the entrance to the cave, his vision becomes more and more impaired. For his entire life he had grown accustomed to looking at things in the dark; and now, all of a sudden, he is inundated by light. As he begins to walk outside, his vision gradually returns. At first he is only able to see the shadows of objects on the ground and the reflections of objects on the water’s surface. Eventually he lifts his head and is able to look at the objects themselves, the ones producing the various shadows and reflections. He has never seen anything so beautiful in his entire life. But out of nowhere, he feels a sudden urge, an ineffable compulsion prompting him to gaze up to the heavens above him. And that is when he catches a glimpse of the sun, its radiance extending from one end of the horizon to the other. In that moment, he knows his journey is complete. What began as a day that was a kind of night, has become the one, true day. Those remotely familiar with Plato’s famous Allegory of the Cave recognize the philosophical impact that the myth has had on metaphysics, epistemology, aesthetics, politics, and education. What is rarely recognized, however, is the myth’s influence on philosophy of science, in particular, the philosophy of modeling. The shadows on the 2 wall of the cave are models of the statues being carried along the pathway, whereas the statues themselves are representations of the actual objects outside of the cave. Plato’s point is that the objects outside represent the true Reality, while the shadows on the wall inside the cave are the farthest removed from the realm of immortal, incorporeal, and unchanging Forms. Now there is a great deal of metaphysics in Plato’s myth, which makes it even more ironic that the scientific community, by and large, has adopted his philosophy of modeling. When Plato speaks of his Theory of Forms as being the ultimate Truth, he is referring to the abstract truths of mathematics. For Plato, all physical objects in the natural world are poor representations, or mere shadows, of their mathematical counterparts. Even though Plato developed his view of mathematics in the 4th century B.C.E, consider what Johannes Kepler, one of the most important astronomers to come after Nicholas Copernicus, said in the Mysterium Cosmographicum nearly two thousand years later, “The ideas of quantities have been and are in God from eternity, they are God himself; they are therefore also present as archetypes in all minds created in God’s likeness.”1 Or, more recently, consider the words of theoretical physicist Paul Dirac, one of the pioneers of quantum mechanics, “As time goes on, it becomes increasingly evident that the rules which the mathematician finds interesting are the same as those which Nature has chosen.”2 For Plato, Kepler, Dirac, and many others, mathematics is more than just a mirror of nature—it is the one, True Nature. 1. Johannes Kepler, Mysterium Cosmographicum, in Arther Koestler, The Watershed: A Biography of Johannes Kepler (New York: University Press of America, 1960), 65.
Recommended publications
  • What Is This Thing Called Knowledge?
    what is this thing called knowledge? What is knowledge? Where does it come from? What kinds of knowledge are there? Can we know anything at all? This lucid and engaging introduction grapples with these central questions in the theory of knowledge, offering a clear, non-partisan view of the main themes of epistemology. Both traditional issues and contemporary ideas are discussed in sixteen easily digestible chapters, each of which conclude with a useful summary of the main ideas discussed, study questions, annotated further reading, and a guide to internet resources. Each chapter also features text boxes providing bite-sized summaries of key concepts and major philosophers, and clear and interesting examples are used throughout. The book concludes with an annotated guide to general introductions to epistemology, a glossary of key terms, and a summary of the main examples used in epistemology.This is an ideal first textbook on the theory of knowledge for undergraduates coming to philosophy for the first time. The third edition has been revised and updated throughout and features two new chapters, on religious knowledge and scientific knowledge, as part of a whole new section on what kinds of knowledge there are. In addition, the text as a whole has been refreshed to keep it up to date with current developments. Duncan Pritchard FRSE is Professor of Philosophy at the University of Edinburgh, UK. His main research area is epistemology, and he has published widely in this field, including the books Epistemic Luck (2005), Knowledge (2009), The Nature and Value of Knowledge (with A.Millar and A.Haddock, 2010), and Epistemological Disjunctivism (2012).
    [Show full text]
  • Falsification and Falsificationism
    Available online at www.worldscientificnews.com WSN 51 (2016) 62-71 EISSN 2392-2192 Falsification and falsificationism Karol Kraiński Faculty of Economics and Management, Nicolaus Copernicus University, 13a Gagarina Str., 87-100 Toruń, Poland E-mail address: [email protected] ABSTRACT Falsification is not meant to refute the theory, but only allows you to specify the probability of the truth of posed too. This action can be described as a set of hypotheses that have a researcher to help explain and describe the world around us. Keywords: falsification; falsificationism; counterfeiting; forg ery; fraud 1. INTRODUCTION Falsification (trans. NLC. Falsificatio = counterfeiting, forgery, fraud) ang. falsification; Ger. Falsifikatio. Proceedings aiming to overturn a sentence, that is, an attempt to demonstrate its falsity. Such a procedure usually involves three stages [6]: 1. derivation of appropriate logical consequences of forged hypothesis; those consequences must be sentences observation; 2. execution of relevant experience (observation, experiment, measurement); 3. confrontation with the results derived consequence experience and any decision to reject the hypothesis. Falsifies is usually not a single thesis, but some of their team. Falsification is the criterion on the basis of a scientific conception of science (K. R. Popper), according to which: a) the thesis must be subject to falsification; World Scientific News 51 (2016) 62-71 b) does not attach much importance to the verification procedure, since the assertion can sometimes completely subvert and never can not be completely verified (with the exception of statements regarding finite and relatively not-great number of objects); c) believes that the introduction of science thesis is not even verified valuable than refraining from introducing too insufficiently verified.
    [Show full text]
  • Astronomy As a Science
    Theme 2: Astronomy as a Science 2.1 Astronomy and Astrology For most of their history, up to the 17th century, astronomy and astrology were completely in- tertwined: for example, astronomers devoted much time and effort to compiling tables of pla- netary positions, not only for navigation and time-keeping but also to aid in the casting of horo- scopes. Nowadays, almost everyone would agree that astronomy is a science but astrology is not. Why is this? What do we mean by the statement “astronomy is a science” anyway? Are there any parts of astronomy which are not science (and, conversely, any parts of astrology which are science)? This is the subject matter of philosophers of science, who aim to provide (1) a descriptive ac- count of science (what scientists do), (2) a normative account (what scientists ought to do) and (3) a definition (what distinguishes science from other pursuits). It has to be said that most working scientists do not take philosophers of science seriously—and, indeed, some philoso- phers of science do rather invite this reaction because of the lack of any apparent connection between their descriptions and scientists’ experiences. However, the serious issues around the definition of “science” which have arisen in recent years, particularly in the USA, strongly indi- cate that working scientists should try to develop a clear mental picture of the definition and practice of science, in order to be able to defend it against incursions by pseudoscience. [As far as I know, nobody has yet tried to demand “balanced treatment” for astrology in astronomy courses—but you never know!] 2.2 The Scientific Method If pushed, most scientists would say that science is a process (a way of working and thinking) and not simply a body of knowledge—though the acquisition of a pre-existing body of know- ledge is usually necessary in order to participate in the process of science.
    [Show full text]
  • Copernicanism and the Typicality in Time
    Copernicanism and the Typicality in Time Milan M. Cirkovi´c´ 1;2, Amedeo Balbi3 1 Astronomical Observatory of Belgrade, Volgina 7 11000 Belgrade, Serbia 2 Future of Humanity Institute, Faculty of Philosophy, University of Oxford, Suite 8, Littlegate House, 16/17 St Ebbe's Street, Oxford, OX1 1PT, UK 3 Dipartimento di Fisica, Universit`adi Roma \Tor Vergata", Via della Ricerca Scientifica, 00133 Roma, Italy Abstract. How special (or not) is the epoch we are living in? What is the appropriate reference class for embedding the observations made at the present time? How probable { or else { is anything we observe in the fulness of time? Contemporary cosmology and astrobiology bring those seemingly old-fashioned philosophical issues back into focus. There are several examples of contemporary research which use the assumption of typicality in time (or temporal Copernicanism) explicitly or implicitly, while not truly elaborating upon the meaning of this assumption. The present paper brings attention to the underlying and often uncritically accepted assumptions in these cases. It also aims to defend a more radical position that typicality in time is not { and cannot ever be { well-defined, in contrast to the typicality in space, and the typicality in various specific parameter spaces. This, of course, does not mean that we are atypical in time; instead, the notion of typicality in time is necessarily somewhat vague and restricted. In principle, it could be strengthened by further defining the relevant context, e.g., by referring to typicality within the Solar lifetime, or some similar restricting clause. Keywords: cosmology: theory { extragalactic astronomy { astrobiology { futures studies { history and philosophy of astronomy { Copernicanism { anthropic principle { extraterrestrial intelligence arXiv:1907.08947v1 [physics.hist-ph] 21 Jul 2019 2 I think we agree, the past is over.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 10 Philosophy of Science
    Chapter 10 Philosophy of Science (Alexander Bird, University of Edinburgh) Introduction The central concerns of the philosophy of science as a whole divide into two areas. One of these areas, perhaps the traditionally more dominant side, encompasses such questions as: Is scientific knowledge possible? If so, how? What methods of reasoning do scientists use? What is the role of observation and experiment in scientific reasoning? Are theories justified that concern entities and processes that cannot be observed? This area is where philosophy of science overlaps with epistemology, the theory of knowledge. The second area is situated where philosophy of science overlaps with metaphysics. Here we are concerned not with whether and why our theories amount to knowledge, but instead we focus on what our theories are about—in the most general terms. For example, the world contains laws of nature and is divided up into different kinds of things. Almost all scientific theories concern one or other of these two general features of the world—or at least their subject matter will reflect these features. Associated with features is the fact that most theories attempt to explain some phenomenon or other. These are metaphysical topics. In this chapter we shall look first at the second area, metaphysical philosophy of science, before returning to the first, epistemological philosophy of science. The metaphysics of science I mentioned three key components in the metaphysical part of the philosophy of science: laws of nature, natural kinds, and explanation. We can see these all operating together in John Dalton’s atomic hypothesis. The starting point is the obvious fact that chemists deal with different substances.
    [Show full text]
  • Hypothetisierungstagung 22.-24.2.05
    1 Die Bedeutung des Hypothetischen in den Naturwissenschaften The Significance of the Hypothetical in the Natural Sciences Internationale Konferenz/ International Conference 22. - 24. Februar 2005 Tagungsort/ Place: Fürstenzimmer, Schloß Hohentübingen Gefördert durch/ Sponsored by: http://www.fritz-thyssen-stiftung.de/ Unterstützt und mitorganisiert von/ Supported and co-organized by: Archives Henri Poincaré http://www.univ-nancy2.fr/poincare Université Nancy 2 Kurzfassungen/ Abstracts The Significance of the Hypothetical in the Natural Sciences – Abstracts 2 Andreas Bartels (Bonn) no claims about their actual objects, but only [email protected] serve to guide investigation. They are a rich Hypotheticity and Realism and precious expedient. in Duhem and Popper My historical aim is to show the continuity between Poincaré’s epistemology As a result of Popper´s philosophy on the and of Vaihinger’s conception of simulation: philosophy of science, hypotheticity and in order to solve certain problems, or to realism are not considered mutually discover new facts or new laws, the scientist inconsistent. But, as Pierre Duhem´s work has to behave “as if” certain facts or states of reminds us, the compatibility of hypotheticity things existed, that is, to simulate their and realism is by no means self-evident. existence. The following problem will guide Duhem sharply distinguishes between two my presentation: how is it possible to reach ways of knowing about natural phenomena: truth (in the sense or understanding of our two On the one hand, mechanical models, which authors) through falsity (that is by assuming lend themselves to visualization, are held to facts that one knows are not real, or are even represent the “hidden causes” of phenomena impossible)? and thereby to “explain” them.
    [Show full text]
  • Reconsidering the Foundations of Thermodynamics from an Engineering Perspective
    Portland State University PDXScholar Mathematics and Statistics Faculty Fariborz Maseeh Department of Mathematics Publications and Presentations and Statistics 7-2018 Reconsidering the Foundations of Thermodynamics from an Engineering Perspective Terry Bristol Portland State University Follow this and additional works at: https://pdxscholar.library.pdx.edu/mth_fac Part of the Engineering Commons, and the Physical Sciences and Mathematics Commons Let us know how access to this document benefits ou.y Citation Details Bristol, T. Reconsidering the Foundations of Thermodynamics from an Engineering Perspective. Preprints 2018, 2018070139 (doi: 10.20944/preprints201807.0139.v1). This Pre-Print is brought to you for free and open access. It has been accepted for inclusion in Mathematics and Statistics Faculty Publications and Presentations by an authorized administrator of PDXScholar. Please contact us if we can make this document more accessible: [email protected]. Preprints (www.preprints.org) | NOT PEER-REVIEWED | Posted: 9 July 2018 doi:10.20944/preprints201807.0139.v1 1 Article 2 Reconsidering the Foundations of Thermodynamics 3 from an Engineering Perspective 4 Terry Bristol 5 Institute for Science Engineering and Public Policy, Portland State University; [email protected] 6 Received: date; Accepted: date; Published: date 7 Abstract: Currently, there are two approaches to the foundations of thermodynamics. One, 8 associated with the mechanistical Clausius-Boltzmann tradition, is favored by the physics 9 community. The other, associated with the post-mechanical Carnot tradition, is favored by the 10 engineering community. The bold hypothesis is that the conceptual foundation of engineering 11 thermodynamics is the more comprehensive. Therefore, contrary to the dominant consensus, 12 engineering thermodynamics (ET) represents the true foundation of thermodynamics.
    [Show full text]
  • The Statistical Crisis in Science Stijn Debrouwere (Author), Prof
    The Statistical Crisis in Science Stijn Debrouwere (author), Prof. Dr. Els Goetghebeur (advisor) Preface What can we say about the statistical crisis in science that has not already been said? Eminent scientists like Paul Meehl, Jakob Cohen and John Ioannidis have already done a great job pinpointing the problems with P-values, null hypothesis significance testing, nonreplicable research, sloppy statistics and fishing expeditions. At the other end of the spectrum journalists at The Atlantic, The New Yorker, FiveThirtyEight and The New York Times have done a surprisingly good job of translating these issues to a lay audience. What is left? What is left is the space in between: for many working scientists the arguments in the statistical literature are too abstract and I have a sneaking suspicion that nobody has ever bothered to double-check the somewhat convoluted calculations in John Ioannidis’ otherwise wonderful Why Most Published Research Findings Are False. On the other hand lay accounts do not treat the problem with enough fidelity to satisfy those who might not be statistical experts as such but do regularly have to interpret t-tests and regression analyses. Yet ultimately it is these students and doctors and working scientists who are the key audience for publications about the statistical crisis in science, because they decide what tomorrow’s statistical practices will look like. I have used this dissertation as an exercise in statistical writing for such an audience of not-quite-experts, not-quite-laymen. To the dissertation committee reading this dissertation I therefore ask that you please do not get frustrated when it takes five paragraphs to explain what power or sensitivity or positive predictive value means.
    [Show full text]
  • Falsification and Falsificationism
    Available online at www.worldscientificnews.com WSN 51 (2016) 44-53 EISSN 2392-2192 Falsification and falsificationism Karol Kraiński Faculty of Economics and Management, Nicolaus Copernicus University, 13a Gagarina Str., 87-100 Toruń, Poland E-mail address: [email protected] ABSTRACT Falsification is not meant to refute the theory, but only allows you to specify the probability of the truth of posed too. This action can be described as a set of hypotheses that have a researcher to help explain and describe the world around us. Keywords: falsification, falsificationism, counterfeiting, forg ery, fraud 1. INTRODUCTION Falsification (trans. NLC. Falsificatio = counterfeiting, forgery, fraud) eng. falsification; Ger. Falsifikatio. Proceedings aiming to overturn a sentence, that is, an attempt to demonstrate its falsity. Such a procedure usually involves three stages [6]: 1. derivation of appropriate logical consequences of forged hypothesis; those consequences must be sentences observation; 2. execution of relevant experience (observation, experiment, measurement); 3. confrontation with the results derived consequence experience and any decision to reject the hypothesis. Falsifies is usually not a single thesis, but some of their team. Falsification is the criterion on the basis of a scientific conception of science (K. R. Popper), according to which: a) the thesis must be subject to falsification; World Scientific News 51 (2016) 44-53 b) does not attach much importance to the verification procedure, since the assertion can sometimes completely subvert and never can not be completely verified (with the exception of statements regarding finite and relatively not-great number of objects); c) believes that the introduction of science thesis is not even verified valuable than refraining from introducing too insufficiently verified.
    [Show full text]