Exploring the Nature of Models in Science, Philosophy of Science, and Science Education
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
Load more
Recommended publications
-
What Is This Thing Called Knowledge?
what is this thing called knowledge? What is knowledge? Where does it come from? What kinds of knowledge are there? Can we know anything at all? This lucid and engaging introduction grapples with these central questions in the theory of knowledge, offering a clear, non-partisan view of the main themes of epistemology. Both traditional issues and contemporary ideas are discussed in sixteen easily digestible chapters, each of which conclude with a useful summary of the main ideas discussed, study questions, annotated further reading, and a guide to internet resources. Each chapter also features text boxes providing bite-sized summaries of key concepts and major philosophers, and clear and interesting examples are used throughout. The book concludes with an annotated guide to general introductions to epistemology, a glossary of key terms, and a summary of the main examples used in epistemology.This is an ideal first textbook on the theory of knowledge for undergraduates coming to philosophy for the first time. The third edition has been revised and updated throughout and features two new chapters, on religious knowledge and scientific knowledge, as part of a whole new section on what kinds of knowledge there are. In addition, the text as a whole has been refreshed to keep it up to date with current developments. Duncan Pritchard FRSE is Professor of Philosophy at the University of Edinburgh, UK. His main research area is epistemology, and he has published widely in this field, including the books Epistemic Luck (2005), Knowledge (2009), The Nature and Value of Knowledge (with A.Millar and A.Haddock, 2010), and Epistemological Disjunctivism (2012). -
Falsification and Falsificationism
Available online at www.worldscientificnews.com WSN 51 (2016) 62-71 EISSN 2392-2192 Falsification and falsificationism Karol Kraiński Faculty of Economics and Management, Nicolaus Copernicus University, 13a Gagarina Str., 87-100 Toruń, Poland E-mail address: [email protected] ABSTRACT Falsification is not meant to refute the theory, but only allows you to specify the probability of the truth of posed too. This action can be described as a set of hypotheses that have a researcher to help explain and describe the world around us. Keywords: falsification; falsificationism; counterfeiting; forg ery; fraud 1. INTRODUCTION Falsification (trans. NLC. Falsificatio = counterfeiting, forgery, fraud) ang. falsification; Ger. Falsifikatio. Proceedings aiming to overturn a sentence, that is, an attempt to demonstrate its falsity. Such a procedure usually involves three stages [6]: 1. derivation of appropriate logical consequences of forged hypothesis; those consequences must be sentences observation; 2. execution of relevant experience (observation, experiment, measurement); 3. confrontation with the results derived consequence experience and any decision to reject the hypothesis. Falsifies is usually not a single thesis, but some of their team. Falsification is the criterion on the basis of a scientific conception of science (K. R. Popper), according to which: a) the thesis must be subject to falsification; World Scientific News 51 (2016) 62-71 b) does not attach much importance to the verification procedure, since the assertion can sometimes completely subvert and never can not be completely verified (with the exception of statements regarding finite and relatively not-great number of objects); c) believes that the introduction of science thesis is not even verified valuable than refraining from introducing too insufficiently verified. -
Astronomy As a Science
Theme 2: Astronomy as a Science 2.1 Astronomy and Astrology For most of their history, up to the 17th century, astronomy and astrology were completely in- tertwined: for example, astronomers devoted much time and effort to compiling tables of pla- netary positions, not only for navigation and time-keeping but also to aid in the casting of horo- scopes. Nowadays, almost everyone would agree that astronomy is a science but astrology is not. Why is this? What do we mean by the statement “astronomy is a science” anyway? Are there any parts of astronomy which are not science (and, conversely, any parts of astrology which are science)? This is the subject matter of philosophers of science, who aim to provide (1) a descriptive ac- count of science (what scientists do), (2) a normative account (what scientists ought to do) and (3) a definition (what distinguishes science from other pursuits). It has to be said that most working scientists do not take philosophers of science seriously—and, indeed, some philoso- phers of science do rather invite this reaction because of the lack of any apparent connection between their descriptions and scientists’ experiences. However, the serious issues around the definition of “science” which have arisen in recent years, particularly in the USA, strongly indi- cate that working scientists should try to develop a clear mental picture of the definition and practice of science, in order to be able to defend it against incursions by pseudoscience. [As far as I know, nobody has yet tried to demand “balanced treatment” for astrology in astronomy courses—but you never know!] 2.2 The Scientific Method If pushed, most scientists would say that science is a process (a way of working and thinking) and not simply a body of knowledge—though the acquisition of a pre-existing body of know- ledge is usually necessary in order to participate in the process of science. -
Copernicanism and the Typicality in Time
Copernicanism and the Typicality in Time Milan M. Cirkovi´c´ 1;2, Amedeo Balbi3 1 Astronomical Observatory of Belgrade, Volgina 7 11000 Belgrade, Serbia 2 Future of Humanity Institute, Faculty of Philosophy, University of Oxford, Suite 8, Littlegate House, 16/17 St Ebbe's Street, Oxford, OX1 1PT, UK 3 Dipartimento di Fisica, Universit`adi Roma \Tor Vergata", Via della Ricerca Scientifica, 00133 Roma, Italy Abstract. How special (or not) is the epoch we are living in? What is the appropriate reference class for embedding the observations made at the present time? How probable { or else { is anything we observe in the fulness of time? Contemporary cosmology and astrobiology bring those seemingly old-fashioned philosophical issues back into focus. There are several examples of contemporary research which use the assumption of typicality in time (or temporal Copernicanism) explicitly or implicitly, while not truly elaborating upon the meaning of this assumption. The present paper brings attention to the underlying and often uncritically accepted assumptions in these cases. It also aims to defend a more radical position that typicality in time is not { and cannot ever be { well-defined, in contrast to the typicality in space, and the typicality in various specific parameter spaces. This, of course, does not mean that we are atypical in time; instead, the notion of typicality in time is necessarily somewhat vague and restricted. In principle, it could be strengthened by further defining the relevant context, e.g., by referring to typicality within the Solar lifetime, or some similar restricting clause. Keywords: cosmology: theory { extragalactic astronomy { astrobiology { futures studies { history and philosophy of astronomy { Copernicanism { anthropic principle { extraterrestrial intelligence arXiv:1907.08947v1 [physics.hist-ph] 21 Jul 2019 2 I think we agree, the past is over. -
Chapter 10 Philosophy of Science
Chapter 10 Philosophy of Science (Alexander Bird, University of Edinburgh) Introduction The central concerns of the philosophy of science as a whole divide into two areas. One of these areas, perhaps the traditionally more dominant side, encompasses such questions as: Is scientific knowledge possible? If so, how? What methods of reasoning do scientists use? What is the role of observation and experiment in scientific reasoning? Are theories justified that concern entities and processes that cannot be observed? This area is where philosophy of science overlaps with epistemology, the theory of knowledge. The second area is situated where philosophy of science overlaps with metaphysics. Here we are concerned not with whether and why our theories amount to knowledge, but instead we focus on what our theories are about—in the most general terms. For example, the world contains laws of nature and is divided up into different kinds of things. Almost all scientific theories concern one or other of these two general features of the world—or at least their subject matter will reflect these features. Associated with features is the fact that most theories attempt to explain some phenomenon or other. These are metaphysical topics. In this chapter we shall look first at the second area, metaphysical philosophy of science, before returning to the first, epistemological philosophy of science. The metaphysics of science I mentioned three key components in the metaphysical part of the philosophy of science: laws of nature, natural kinds, and explanation. We can see these all operating together in John Dalton’s atomic hypothesis. The starting point is the obvious fact that chemists deal with different substances. -
Hypothetisierungstagung 22.-24.2.05
1 Die Bedeutung des Hypothetischen in den Naturwissenschaften The Significance of the Hypothetical in the Natural Sciences Internationale Konferenz/ International Conference 22. - 24. Februar 2005 Tagungsort/ Place: Fürstenzimmer, Schloß Hohentübingen Gefördert durch/ Sponsored by: http://www.fritz-thyssen-stiftung.de/ Unterstützt und mitorganisiert von/ Supported and co-organized by: Archives Henri Poincaré http://www.univ-nancy2.fr/poincare Université Nancy 2 Kurzfassungen/ Abstracts The Significance of the Hypothetical in the Natural Sciences – Abstracts 2 Andreas Bartels (Bonn) no claims about their actual objects, but only [email protected] serve to guide investigation. They are a rich Hypotheticity and Realism and precious expedient. in Duhem and Popper My historical aim is to show the continuity between Poincaré’s epistemology As a result of Popper´s philosophy on the and of Vaihinger’s conception of simulation: philosophy of science, hypotheticity and in order to solve certain problems, or to realism are not considered mutually discover new facts or new laws, the scientist inconsistent. But, as Pierre Duhem´s work has to behave “as if” certain facts or states of reminds us, the compatibility of hypotheticity things existed, that is, to simulate their and realism is by no means self-evident. existence. The following problem will guide Duhem sharply distinguishes between two my presentation: how is it possible to reach ways of knowing about natural phenomena: truth (in the sense or understanding of our two On the one hand, mechanical models, which authors) through falsity (that is by assuming lend themselves to visualization, are held to facts that one knows are not real, or are even represent the “hidden causes” of phenomena impossible)? and thereby to “explain” them. -
Reconsidering the Foundations of Thermodynamics from an Engineering Perspective
Portland State University PDXScholar Mathematics and Statistics Faculty Fariborz Maseeh Department of Mathematics Publications and Presentations and Statistics 7-2018 Reconsidering the Foundations of Thermodynamics from an Engineering Perspective Terry Bristol Portland State University Follow this and additional works at: https://pdxscholar.library.pdx.edu/mth_fac Part of the Engineering Commons, and the Physical Sciences and Mathematics Commons Let us know how access to this document benefits ou.y Citation Details Bristol, T. Reconsidering the Foundations of Thermodynamics from an Engineering Perspective. Preprints 2018, 2018070139 (doi: 10.20944/preprints201807.0139.v1). This Pre-Print is brought to you for free and open access. It has been accepted for inclusion in Mathematics and Statistics Faculty Publications and Presentations by an authorized administrator of PDXScholar. Please contact us if we can make this document more accessible: [email protected]. Preprints (www.preprints.org) | NOT PEER-REVIEWED | Posted: 9 July 2018 doi:10.20944/preprints201807.0139.v1 1 Article 2 Reconsidering the Foundations of Thermodynamics 3 from an Engineering Perspective 4 Terry Bristol 5 Institute for Science Engineering and Public Policy, Portland State University; [email protected] 6 Received: date; Accepted: date; Published: date 7 Abstract: Currently, there are two approaches to the foundations of thermodynamics. One, 8 associated with the mechanistical Clausius-Boltzmann tradition, is favored by the physics 9 community. The other, associated with the post-mechanical Carnot tradition, is favored by the 10 engineering community. The bold hypothesis is that the conceptual foundation of engineering 11 thermodynamics is the more comprehensive. Therefore, contrary to the dominant consensus, 12 engineering thermodynamics (ET) represents the true foundation of thermodynamics. -
The Statistical Crisis in Science Stijn Debrouwere (Author), Prof
The Statistical Crisis in Science Stijn Debrouwere (author), Prof. Dr. Els Goetghebeur (advisor) Preface What can we say about the statistical crisis in science that has not already been said? Eminent scientists like Paul Meehl, Jakob Cohen and John Ioannidis have already done a great job pinpointing the problems with P-values, null hypothesis significance testing, nonreplicable research, sloppy statistics and fishing expeditions. At the other end of the spectrum journalists at The Atlantic, The New Yorker, FiveThirtyEight and The New York Times have done a surprisingly good job of translating these issues to a lay audience. What is left? What is left is the space in between: for many working scientists the arguments in the statistical literature are too abstract and I have a sneaking suspicion that nobody has ever bothered to double-check the somewhat convoluted calculations in John Ioannidis’ otherwise wonderful Why Most Published Research Findings Are False. On the other hand lay accounts do not treat the problem with enough fidelity to satisfy those who might not be statistical experts as such but do regularly have to interpret t-tests and regression analyses. Yet ultimately it is these students and doctors and working scientists who are the key audience for publications about the statistical crisis in science, because they decide what tomorrow’s statistical practices will look like. I have used this dissertation as an exercise in statistical writing for such an audience of not-quite-experts, not-quite-laymen. To the dissertation committee reading this dissertation I therefore ask that you please do not get frustrated when it takes five paragraphs to explain what power or sensitivity or positive predictive value means. -
Falsification and Falsificationism
Available online at www.worldscientificnews.com WSN 51 (2016) 44-53 EISSN 2392-2192 Falsification and falsificationism Karol Kraiński Faculty of Economics and Management, Nicolaus Copernicus University, 13a Gagarina Str., 87-100 Toruń, Poland E-mail address: [email protected] ABSTRACT Falsification is not meant to refute the theory, but only allows you to specify the probability of the truth of posed too. This action can be described as a set of hypotheses that have a researcher to help explain and describe the world around us. Keywords: falsification, falsificationism, counterfeiting, forg ery, fraud 1. INTRODUCTION Falsification (trans. NLC. Falsificatio = counterfeiting, forgery, fraud) eng. falsification; Ger. Falsifikatio. Proceedings aiming to overturn a sentence, that is, an attempt to demonstrate its falsity. Such a procedure usually involves three stages [6]: 1. derivation of appropriate logical consequences of forged hypothesis; those consequences must be sentences observation; 2. execution of relevant experience (observation, experiment, measurement); 3. confrontation with the results derived consequence experience and any decision to reject the hypothesis. Falsifies is usually not a single thesis, but some of their team. Falsification is the criterion on the basis of a scientific conception of science (K. R. Popper), according to which: a) the thesis must be subject to falsification; World Scientific News 51 (2016) 44-53 b) does not attach much importance to the verification procedure, since the assertion can sometimes completely subvert and never can not be completely verified (with the exception of statements regarding finite and relatively not-great number of objects); c) believes that the introduction of science thesis is not even verified valuable than refraining from introducing too insufficiently verified.