Projective Geometry and Pappus' Theorem

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Projective Geometry and Pappus' Theorem Projective Geometry and Pappus' Theorem Kelly McKinnie History Projective Geometry and Pappus' Theorem Pappus' Theorem Geometries Picturing the Kelly McKinnie projective plane Lines in projective geometry March 23, 2010 Back to Pappus' Theorem Proof of Pappus' Theorem Pappus of Alexandria was a Greek mathematician. He lived around the time of the 3rd century AD. Appears to have witnessed a solar eclipse in 320 AD, but there is some confusion about this. Pappus of Alexandria Projective Geometry and Pappus' Theorem Kelly McKinnie History Pappus' Theorem Geometries Picturing the projective plane Lines in projective geometry Back to Pappus' Theorem Proof of Pappus' Theorem He lived around the time of the 3rd century AD. Appears to have witnessed a solar eclipse in 320 AD, but there is some confusion about this. Pappus of Alexandria Projective Geometry and Pappus' Theorem Kelly McKinnie History Pappus' Pappus of Alexandria was a Greek mathematician. Theorem Geometries Picturing the projective plane Lines in projective geometry Back to Pappus' Theorem Proof of Pappus' Theorem Appears to have witnessed a solar eclipse in 320 AD, but there is some confusion about this. Pappus of Alexandria Projective Geometry and Pappus' Theorem Kelly McKinnie History Pappus' Pappus of Alexandria was a Greek mathematician. Theorem He lived around the time of the 3rd century AD. Geometries Picturing the projective plane Lines in projective geometry Back to Pappus' Theorem Proof of Pappus' Theorem Pappus of Alexandria Projective Geometry and Pappus' Theorem Kelly McKinnie History Pappus' Pappus of Alexandria was a Greek mathematician. Theorem He lived around the time of the 3rd century AD. Geometries Picturing the Appears to have witnessed a solar eclipse in 320 AD, but projective plane there is some confusion about this. Lines in projective geometry Back to Pappus' Theorem Proof of Pappus' Theorem His major contribution is a book called Synagoge, also known as \Mathematical Collections". The Mathematical Collections of Pappus in a translation of Federico Commandino (1589). Pappus of Alexandria - Mathematical contributions Projective Geometry and Pappus' Theorem Kelly McKinnie History Pappus' Theorem Geometries Picturing the projective plane Lines in projective geometry Back to Pappus' Theorem Proof of Pappus' Theorem The Mathematical Collections of Pappus in a translation of Federico Commandino (1589). Pappus of Alexandria - Mathematical contributions Projective His major contribution is a book called Synagoge, also known Geometry and Pappus' as \Mathematical Collections". Theorem Kelly McKinnie History Pappus' Theorem Geometries Picturing the projective plane Lines in projective geometry Back to Pappus' Theorem Proof of Pappus' Theorem Pappus of Alexandria - Mathematical contributions Projective His major contribution is a book called Synagoge, also known Geometry and Pappus' as \Mathematical Collections". Theorem Kelly McKinnie History Pappus' Theorem Geometries Picturing the projective plane Lines in projective geometry Back to Pappus' Theorem Proof of Pappus' Theorem The Mathematical Collections of Pappus in a translation of Federico Commandino (1589). Vatican Exhibit of Pappus' Collections Projective Geometry and Pappus' Theorem Kelly McKinnie History Pappus' Theorem Geometries Picturing the projective plane Lines in projective geometry Back to Pappus' Theorem Proof of Pappus' Theorem \Pappus's \Collection," consisting of supplements to earlier treatises on geometry, astronomy, and mechanics, dates from the late third century A.D. and is the last important work of Greek mathematics. This manuscript reached the papal library in the thirteenth century, and is the archetype of all later copies, of which none is earlier than the sixteenth century. " Courtesy of http://www.ibiblio.org Vatican Exhibit of Pappus' Collections Projective Geometry and Pappus' Theorem Kelly Caption on the exhibit: McKinnie History Pappus' Theorem Geometries Picturing the projective plane Lines in projective geometry Back to Pappus' Theorem Proof of Pappus' Theorem Vatican Exhibit of Pappus' Collections Projective Geometry and Pappus' Theorem Kelly Caption on the exhibit: McKinnie History Pappus' Theorem \Pappus's \Collection," consisting of supplements to earlier Geometries treatises on geometry, astronomy, and mechanics, dates from Picturing the projective the late third century A.D. and is the last important work of plane Greek mathematics. This manuscript reached the papal library Lines in projective in the thirteenth century, and is the archetype of all later geometry copies, of which none is earlier than the sixteenth century. " Back to Pappus' Courtesy of http://www.ibiblio.org Theorem Proof of Pappus' Theorem Pappus of Alexandria - Pappus' Theorem Projective Geometry and Pappus' Theorem Kelly McKinnie History Pappus' Theorem One piece of mathematics in "Collection" is a seemingly Geometries original theorem that has since become known as Pappus' Picturing the Theorem. projective plane Lines in projective geometry Back to Pappus' Theorem Proof of Pappus' Theorem C B A Pappus of Alexandria - Pappus' Theorem Projective Geometry and Pappus' Let three points A, B, C be incident to a single straight line Theorem Kelly McKinnie History Pappus' Theorem Geometries Picturing the projective plane Lines in projective geometry Back to Pappus' Theorem Proof of Pappus' Theorem C B A Pappus of Alexandria - Pappus' Theorem Projective Geometry and Pappus' Let three points A, B, C be incident to a single straight line Theorem Kelly McKinnie History Pappus' Theorem Geometries Picturing the projective plane Lines in projective geometry Back to Pappus' Theorem Proof of Pappus' Theorem Pappus of Alexandria - Pappus' Theorem Projective Geometry and Pappus' Theorem Let three points A, B, C be incident to a single straight line 0 0 0 Kelly and another three points A , B , C incident to another straight McKinnie line. History Pappus' Theorem Geometries Picturing the C projective B plane A Lines in projective geometry Back to Pappus' Theorem A' B' C' Proof of Pappus' Theorem Pappus of Alexandria - Pappus' Theorem Projective Geometry and Pappus' Theorem Let three points A, B, C be incident to a single straight line Kelly 0 0 0 McKinnie and another three points A , B , C incident to another straight line. Then the three pairwise intersections AB0 \ A0B History Pappus' Theorem Geometries C Picturing the B projective A plane Lines in projective geometry Back to Pappus' Theorem A' B' C' Proof of Pappus' Theorem Pappus of Alexandria - Pappus' Theorem Projective Geometry and Pappus' Theorem Let three points A, B, C be incident to a single straight line Kelly McKinnie and another three points A0, B0, C 0 incident to another straight 0 0 History line. Then the three pairwise intersections AB \ A B, 0 0 Pappus' AC \ A C Theorem Geometries C Picturing the B projective A plane Lines in projective geometry Back to Pappus' A' B' C' Theorem Proof of Pappus' Theorem Pappus of Alexandria - Pappus' Theorem Projective Geometry and Pappus' Theorem Let three points A, B, C be incident to a single straight line Kelly McKinnie and another three points A0, B0, C 0 incident to another straight 0 0 History line. Then the three pairwise intersections AB \ A B, 0 0 0 0 Pappus' AC \ A C and BC \ B C Theorem Geometries C Picturing the B projective A plane Lines in projective geometry Back to Pappus' A' B' C' Theorem Proof of Pappus' Theorem Pappus of Alexandria - Pappus' Theorem Projective Geometry and Pappus' Theorem Let three points A, B, C be incident to a single straight line Kelly 0 0 0 McKinnie and another three points A , B , C incident to another straight 0 0 History line. Then the three pairwise intersections AB \ A B, 0 0 0 0 Pappus' BC \ C B and AC \ A C are incident to a third straight line. Theorem Geometries C Picturing the B projective A plane Lines in projective geometry Back to Pappus' A' B' C' Theorem Proof of Pappus' Theorem Pappus of Alexandria - Pappus' Theorem Projective Geometry and Pappus' Theorem Let three points A, B, C be incident to a single straight line Kelly 0 0 0 McKinnie and another three points A , B , C incident to another straight 0 0 History line. Then the three pairwise intersections AB \ A B, 0 0 0 0 Pappus' BC \ C B and AC \ A C are incident to a third straight line. Theorem Geometries C Picturing the B projective A plane Lines in projective geometry Back to Pappus' A' B' C' Theorem Proof of Pappus' Theorem Pappus of Alexandria - Pappus' Theorem Projective Geometry and Pappus' Theorem Kelly McKinnie History Pappus' Theorem Java Applet on the web at Geometries http://www.cut-the-knot.org/pythagoras/Pappus.shtml Picturing the projective plane Lines in projective geometry Back to Pappus' Theorem Proof of Pappus' Theorem Let three points A, B, C be incident to a single straight line and another three points A0, B0, C 0 incident to (generally speaking) another straight line. Then the three pairwise intersections AB0 \ A0B, BC 0 \ C 0B and AC 0 \ A0C are incident to a third straight line. Pappus of Alexandria - Pappus' Theorem Projective Geometry and Pappus' Theorem Kelly McKinnie History As you can see from the Java Applet, Pappus' Theorem should Pappus' really read: Theorem Geometries Picturing the projective plane Lines in projective geometry Back to Pappus' Theorem Proof of Pappus' Theorem (generally speaking) another straight line. Then the three pairwise intersections AB0 \ A0B, BC 0 \ C 0B and AC 0 \ A0C are incident to a third straight line. Pappus of Alexandria - Pappus' Theorem
Recommended publications
  • Astronomy and Hipparchus
    CHAPTER 9 Progress in the Sciences: Astronomy and Hipparchus Klaus Geus Introduction Geography in modern times is a term which covers several sub-disciplines like ecology, human geography, economic history, volcanology etc., which all con- cern themselves with “space” or “environment”. In ancient times, the definition of geography was much more limited. Geography aimed at the production of a map of the oikoumene, a geographer was basically a cartographer. The famous scientist Ptolemy defined geography in the first sentence of his Geographical handbook (Geog. 1.1.1) as “imitation through drafting of the entire known part of the earth, including the things which are, generally speaking, connected with it”. In contrast to chorography, geography uses purely “lines and label in order to show the positions of places and general configurations” (Geog. 1.1.5). Therefore, according to Ptolemy, a geographer needs a μέθοδος μαθεματική, abil- ity and competence in mathematical sciences, most prominently astronomy, in order to fulfil his task of drafting a map of the oikoumene. Given this close connection between geography and astronomy, it is not by default that nearly all ancient “geographers” (in the limited sense of the term) stood out also as astronomers and mathematicians: Among them Anaximander, Eudoxus, Eratosthenes, Hipparchus, Poseidonius and Ptolemy are the most illustrious. Apart from certain topics like latitudes, meridians, polar circles etc., ancient geography also took over from astronomy some methods like the determina- tion of the size of the earth or of celestial and terrestrial distances.1 The men- tioned geographers Anaximander, Eudoxus, Hipparchus, Poseidonius and Ptolemy even constructed instruments for measuring, observing and calculat- ing like the gnomon, sundials, skaphe, astrolabe or the meteoroscope.2 1 E.g., Ptolemy (Geog.
    [Show full text]
  • Pappus of Alexandria: Book 4 of the Collection
    Pappus of Alexandria: Book 4 of the Collection For other titles published in this series, go to http://www.springer.com/series/4142 Sources and Studies in the History of Mathematics and Physical Sciences Managing Editor J.Z. Buchwald Associate Editors J.L. Berggren and J. Lützen Advisory Board C. Fraser, T. Sauer, A. Shapiro Pappus of Alexandria: Book 4 of the Collection Edited With Translation and Commentary by Heike Sefrin-Weis Heike Sefrin-Weis Department of Philosophy University of South Carolina Columbia SC USA [email protected] Sources Managing Editor: Jed Z. Buchwald California Institute of Technology Division of the Humanities and Social Sciences MC 101–40 Pasadena, CA 91125 USA Associate Editors: J.L. Berggren Jesper Lützen Simon Fraser University University of Copenhagen Department of Mathematics Institute of Mathematics University Drive 8888 Universitetsparken 5 V5A 1S6 Burnaby, BC 2100 Koebenhaven Canada Denmark ISBN 978-1-84996-004-5 e-ISBN 978-1-84996-005-2 DOI 10.1007/978-1-84996-005-2 Springer London Dordrecht Heidelberg New York British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library Library of Congress Control Number: 2009942260 Mathematics Classification Number (2010) 00A05, 00A30, 03A05, 01A05, 01A20, 01A85, 03-03, 51-03 and 97-03 © Springer-Verlag London Limited 2010 Apart from any fair dealing for the purposes of research or private study, or criticism or review, as permitted under the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988, this publication may only be reproduced, stored or transmitted, in any form or by any means, with the prior permission in writing of the publishers, or in the case of reprographic reproduction in accordance with the terms of licenses issued by the Copyright Licensing Agency.
    [Show full text]
  • Greek Mathematics Recovered in Books 6 and 7 of Clavius’ Geometria Practica
    Introduction – Clavius and Geometria Practica Book 6 and Greek approaches to duplication of the cube Book 7 and squaring the circle via the quadratrix Conclusions Greek Mathematics Recovered in Books 6 and 7 of Clavius’ Geometria Practica John B. Little Department of Mathematics and CS College of the Holy Cross June 29, 2018 Greek Mathematics in Clavius Introduction – Clavius and Geometria Practica Book 6 and Greek approaches to duplication of the cube Book 7 and squaring the circle via the quadratrix Conclusions I’ve always been interested in the history of mathematics (in addition to my nominal specialty in algebraic geometry/computational methods/coding theory, etc.) Want to be able to engage with original texts on their own terms – you might recall the talks on Apollonius’s Conics I gave at the last Clavius Group meeting at Holy Cross (two years ago) So, I’ve been taking Greek and Latin language courses in HC’s Classics department The subject for today relates to a Latin-to-English translation project I have recently begun – working with the Geometria Practica of Christopher Clavius, S.J. (1538 - 1612, CE) Greek Mathematics in Clavius Introduction – Clavius and Geometria Practica Book 6 and Greek approaches to duplication of the cube Book 7 and squaring the circle via the quadratrix Conclusions Overview 1 Introduction – Clavius and Geometria Practica 2 Book 6 and Greek approaches to duplication of the cube 3 Book 7 and squaring the circle via the quadratrix 4 Conclusions Greek Mathematics in Clavius Introduction – Clavius and Geometria Practica Book 6 and Greek approaches to duplication of the cube Book 7 and squaring the circle via the quadratrix Conclusions Clavius’ Principal Mathematical Textbooks Euclidis Elementorum, Libri XV (first ed.
    [Show full text]
  • Geometry in the Age of Enlightenment
    Geometry in the Age of Enlightenment Raymond O. Wells, Jr. ∗ July 2, 2015 Contents 1 Introduction 1 2 Algebraic Geometry 3 2.1 Algebraic Curves of Degree Two: Descartes and Fermat . 5 2.2 Algebraic Curves of Degree Three: Newton and Euler . 11 3 Differential Geometry 13 3.1 Curvature of curves in the plane . 17 3.2 Curvature of curves in space . 26 3.3 Curvature of a surface in space: Euler in 1767 . 28 4 Conclusion 30 1 Introduction The Age of Enlightenment is a term that refers to a time of dramatic changes in western society in the arts, in science, in political thinking, and, in particular, in philosophical discourse. It is generally recognized as being the period from the mid 17th century to the latter part of the 18th century. It was a successor to the renaissance and reformation periods and was followed by what is termed the romanticism of the 19th century. In his book A History of Western Philosophy [25] Bertrand Russell (1872{1970) gives a very lucid description of this time arXiv:1507.00060v1 [math.HO] 30 Jun 2015 period in intellectual history, especially in Book III, Chapter VI{Chapter XVII. He singles out Ren´eDescartes as being the founder of the era of new philosophy in 1637 and continues to describe other philosophers who also made significant contributions to mathematics as well, such as Newton and Leibniz. This time of intellectual fervor included literature (e.g. Voltaire), music and the world of visual arts as well. One of the most significant developments was perhaps in the political world: here the absolutism of the church and of the monarchies ∗Jacobs University Bremen; University of Colorado at Boulder; [email protected] 1 were questioned by the political philosophers of this era, ushering in the Glo- rious Revolution in England (1689), the American Revolution (1776), and the bloody French Revolution (1789).
    [Show full text]
  • Newton's Parabola Observed from Pappus
    Applied Physics Research; Vol. 11, No. 2; 2019 ISSN 1916-9639 E-ISSN 1916-9647 Published by Canadian Center of Science and Education Newton’s Parabola Observed from Pappus’ Directrix, Apollonius’ Pedal Curve (Line), Newton’s Evolute, Leibniz’s Subtangent and Subnormal, Castillon’s Cardioid, and Ptolemy’s Circle (Hodograph) (09.02.2019) Jiří Stávek1 1 Bazovského, Prague, Czech Republic Correspondence: Jiří Stávek, Bazovského 1228, 163 00 Prague, Czech Republic. E-mail: [email protected] Received: February 2, 2019 Accepted: February 20, 2019 Online Published: February 25, 2019 doi:10.5539/apr.v11n2p30 URL: http://dx.doi.org/10.5539/apr.v11n2p30 Abstract Johannes Kepler and Isaac Newton inspired generations of researchers to study properties of elliptic, hyperbolic, and parabolic paths of planets and other astronomical objects orbiting around the Sun. The books of these two Old Masters “Astronomia Nova” and “Principia…” were originally written in the geometrical language. However, the following generations of researchers translated the geometrical language of these Old Masters into the infinitesimal calculus independently discovered by Newton and Leibniz. In our attempt we will try to return back to the original geometrical language and to present several figures with possible hidden properties of parabolic orbits. For the description of events on parabolic orbits we will employ the interplay of the directrix of parabola discovered by Pappus of Alexandria, the pedal curve with the pedal point in the focus discovered by Apollonius of Perga (The Great Geometer), and the focus occupied by our Sun discovered in several stages by Aristarchus, Copernicus, Kepler and Isaac Newton (The Great Mathematician).
    [Show full text]
  • Pappus of Alexandria: Book 4 of the Collection
    Pappus of Alexandria: Book 4 of the Collection For other titles published in this series, go to http://www.springer.com/series/4142 Sources and Studies in the History of Mathematics and Physical Sciences Managing Editor J.Z. Buchwald Associate Editors J.L. Berggren and J. Lützen Advisory Board C. Fraser, T. Sauer, A. Shapiro Pappus of Alexandria: Book 4 of the Collection Edited With Translation and Commentary by Heike Sefrin-Weis Heike Sefrin-Weis Department of Philosophy University of South Carolina Columbia SC USA [email protected] Sources Managing Editor: Jed Z. Buchwald California Institute of Technology Division of the Humanities and Social Sciences MC 101–40 Pasadena, CA 91125 USA Associate Editors: J.L. Berggren Jesper Lützen Simon Fraser University University of Copenhagen Department of Mathematics Institute of Mathematics University Drive 8888 Universitetsparken 5 V5A 1S6 Burnaby, BC 2100 Koebenhaven Canada Denmark ISBN 978-1-84996-004-5 e-ISBN 978-1-84996-005-2 DOI 10.1007/978-1-84996-005-2 Springer London Dordrecht Heidelberg New York British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library Library of Congress Control Number: 2009942260 Mathematics Classification Number (2010) 00A05, 00A30, 03A05, 01A05, 01A20, 01A85, 03-03, 51-03 and 97-03 © Springer-Verlag London Limited 2010 Apart from any fair dealing for the purposes of research or private study, or criticism or review, as permitted under the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988, this publication may only be reproduced, stored or transmitted, in any form or by any means, with the prior permission in writing of the publishers, or in the case of reprographic reproduction in accordance with the terms of licenses issued by the Copyright Licensing Agency.
    [Show full text]
  • A Concise History of the Philosophy of Mathematics
    A Thumbnail History of the Philosophy of Mathematics "It is beyond a doubt that all our knowledge begins with experience." - Imannuel Kant ( 1724 – 1804 ) ( However naïve realism is no substitute for truth [1] ) [1] " ... concepts have reference to sensible experience, but they are never, in a logical sense, deducible from them. For this reason I have never been able to comprehend the problem of the á priori as posed by Kant", from "The Problem of Space, Ether, and the Field in Physics" ( "Das Raum-, Äether- und Feld-Problem der Physik." ), by Albert Einstein, 1934 - source: "Beyond Geometry: Classic Papers from Riemann to Einstein", Dover Publications, by Peter Pesic, St. John's College, Sante Fe, New Mexico Mathematics does not have a universally accepted definition during any period of its development throughout the history of human thought. However for the last 2,500 years, beginning first with the pre - Hellenic Egyptians and Babylonians, mathematics encompasses possible deductive relationships concerned solely with logical truths derived by accepted philosophic methods of logic which the classical Greek thinkers of antiquity pioneered. Although it is normally associated with formulaic algorithms ( i.e., mechanical methods ), mathematics somehow arises in the human mind by the correspondence of observation and inductive experiential thinking together with its practical predictive powers in interpreting future as well as "seemingly" ephemeral phenomena. Why all of this is true in human progress, no one can answer faithfully. In other words, human experiences and intuitive thinking first suggest to the human mind the abstract symbols for which the economy of human thinking mathematics is well known; but it is those parts of mathematics most disconnected from observation and experience and therefore relying almost wholly upon its internal, self - consistent, deductive logics giving mathematics an independent reified, almost ontological, reality, that mathematics most powerfully interprets the ultimate hidden mysteries of nature.
    [Show full text]
  • Pappus of Alexandria and the Mathematics of Late Antiquity
    PAPPUS OF ALEXANDRIA AND THE MATHEMATICS OF LATE ANTIQUITY S. CUOMO ab published by the press syndicate of the university of cambridge The Pitt Building, Trumpington Street, Cambridge, United Kingdom cambridge university press The Edinburgh Building, Cambridge cb22ru, UK http://www.cup.cam.ac.uk 40 West 20th Street, New York, ny 10011-4211, USA http://www.cup.org 10 Stamford Road, Oakleigh, Melbourne 3166, Australia Ruiz de AlarcoÂn 13, 28014 Madrid, Spain ( Faculty of Classics, University of Cambridge 2000 This book is in copyright. Subject to statutory exception and to the provisions of relevant collective licensing agreements, no reproduction of any part may take place without the written permission of Cambridge University Press. First published 2000 Printed in the United Kingdom at the University Press, Cambridge Typeset in Times 11/13pt [ao] Chapter 2 of this book is a revised version of a chapter originally published in Gattungen wissenschaftlicher Literatur in der Antike, ed. by Wolfgang Kullmann, Jochen Altho¨, Markus Asper. TuÈbingen: Narr, 1998 (ScriptOralia, Vol. 95). ( 1998 Gunter Narr Verlag TuÈbingen. A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library Library of Congress cataloguing in publication data Cuomo, S. (Sera®na) Pappus of Alexandria and the mathematics of late antiquity / S. Cuomo. p. cm. ± (Cambridge classical studies) Includes bibliographical references and index. isbn 0 521 64211 6 1. Mathematics, Greek. 2. Pappus, of Alexandria. Mathematical collections. i. Title. ii. Series. qa22.c86 2000
    [Show full text]
  • Conceptual Anachronism--A Case Study from Interpretations of the Conics of Apollonius
    Introduction How Apollonius described and classified the conic sections Different interpretations Conceptual Anachronism–A Case Study from Interpretations of the Conics of Apollonius John B. Little Department of Mathematics and Computer Science College of the Holy Cross June 21 and 22, 2016 John B. Little Conceptual Anachronism Introduction How Apollonius described and classified the conic sections Different interpretations Outline 1 Introduction 2 How Apollonius described and classified the conic sections 3 Different interpretations John B. Little Conceptual Anachronism Introduction How Apollonius described and classified the conic sections Different interpretations Who was Apollonius? Lived ca. 262–190 BCE, born in Perga (south coast of present-day Turkey) Active roughly 75 - 100 years after time of Euclid (ca. 300 BCE); slightly younger than Archimedes (ca. 287–212 BCE) Studied with successors of Euclid at Museum in Alexandria Have lists of his works from later commentaries, but most have not survived Know he did astronomy as well, work incorporated into Claudius Ptolemy’s (90 - 168 CE) geocentric model of solar system with epicycles, etc. John B. Little Conceptual Anachronism Introduction How Apollonius described and classified the conic sections Different interpretations From Taliaferro’s translation – start of Book I A few historical details can be gleaned from prefatory letters at the start of several books of the Conics, e.g. from letter to Eudemus at head of Book I: ... I worked out the plan for these conics at the request of Naucrates, the geometer, at the time he was with us in Alexandria lecturing, and ... on arranging them in eight books, we immediately communicated them in great haste because of his near departure, not revising them but putting down whatever came to us ..
    [Show full text]
  • Pappus. Introductory Paper. 127
    1916.] PAPPUS. INTRODUCTORY PAPER. 127 (1, 3, 4) = - wzwjwx2, (1, 3, 5) = 0, 2 2 2 (1, 3, 6) = w2 /wi , (1, 4, 5) = wsWt/wi , 2 (1, 4, 6) = — W2/W1, (1, 5, 6) = w2Ws/wi , (2, 3, 4) = wi/wi, (2, 3, 5) = — w^w^/wi2, (2, 3, 6) = - w2/wi, (2, 4, 5) = 0, (2, 4, 6) = 1, (2, 5, 6) = - ws/wh (3, 4, 5) = WM2, (3, 4, 6) = 0, (3, 5, 6) = W2W4/W12, (4, 5, 6) = — wjw%. Since the non-vanishing fractions in w\9 • • •, W4 all have second order numerators and a common denominator wi2, the theorem is proved. Substitution of these results in (8) and the results from (8) in I gives the explicit form of the trans­ lation surface <p{w), in a form free from extraneous factors. It is obvious that a complete set of invariants gives, in the present case of the congruence (m, n) or in the previous binary case of (m, 1), a fundamental system of translation surfaces. For the congruence (2, 2), cut by a plane in a quadrilateral, the complete system consists of four surfaces {aa'a")2, (bb'b")2, {aafb)2, (abb')2, all of degree 3 and class 4. UNIVERSITY OF PENNSYLVANIA. PAPPUS. INTRODUCTORY PAPER. BY DR. J. H. WEAVER. (Read before the American Mathematical Society, April 24, 1915.) ONE of the most wholesome tendencies in the study of mathematics today is the desire to give increased attention to the history and genesis of the subject. This tendency has led to a more careful study of the works of the old Greek mathematicians.
    [Show full text]
  • ARCHIMEDES to PAPPUS Dramatis Personae Eudemus (Of Rhodes), fl
    m3hw3.tex Week 3 25-30.1.18 THE GREEKS: ARCHIMEDES TO PAPPUS Dramatis Personae Eudemus (of Rhodes), fl. c. 320 BC: history of mathematics (now lost: W4) Archimedes (of Syracuse, c. 287-212 BC) Apollonius (of Perga, Asia Minor, c.262 { c.190 BC) Aristarchus (of Samos, fl. c. 280 BC) Eratosthenes (of Cyrene, 276-194 BC) Hipparchus (of Nicea, c. 180 { c. 125 BC) Menelaus (of Alexandria, c. 100 AD) Ptolemy (of Alexandria, fl. c. 127-150 AD) Heron (of Alexandria, 3rd C. AD) Diophantus (of Alexandria, fl. c. 250 AD) Pappus (of Alexandria, fl. c. 290 AD) Sources B Ch. 8-11, and other sources for Week 2; E. J. DIJKSTERHUIS, Archimedes, 2nd ed. (with an addendum by W. R. Knorr), PUP 1987 (1st ed. 1938-44, Dutch, Eng. tr. 1957) H. S. M. COXETER, Regular polytopes, 3rd ed., Dover, 1973 (1st ed. 1963). H. M. CUNDY & A. P. ROLLETT, Mathematical models, 2nd ed., OUP, 1961. Archimedes Archimedes lived in Syracuse, SE Sicily, then part of the Hellenistic world. He may have studied at Alexandria, and was in contact with mathematicians there. Syracuse sided with Carthage in the Punic Wars, and fell to Rome in 212 BC. Archimedes played a leading part in the defence of Syracuse during the long siege 214-212 BC, inventing engines of war: catapults to hurl stones, cranes of pull ships from the water and drop them, etc. (the siege is described in details by Plutarch, Livy and Polybius). The Roman general Marcellus admired Archimedes and ordered his life to be spared.
    [Show full text]
  • HISTORY of MATH CONCEPTS Essentials, Images and Memes
    HISTORY OF MATH CONCEPTS Essentials, Images and Memes Sergey Finashin Modern Mathematics having roots in ancient Egypt and Babylonia, really flourished in ancient Greece. It is remarkable in Arithmetic (Number theory) and Deductive Geometry. Mathematics written in ancient Greek was translated into Arabic, together with some mathematics of India. Mathematicians of Islamic Middle East significantly developed Algebra. Later some of this mathematics was translated into Latin and became the mathematics of Western Europe. Over a period of several hundred years, it became the mathematics of the world. Some significant mathematics was also developed in other regions, such as China, southern India, and other places, but it had no such a great influence on the international mathematics. The most significant for development in mathematics was giving it firm logical foundations in ancient Greece which was culminated in Euclid’s Elements, a masterpiece establishing standards of rigorous presentation of proofs that influenced mathematics for many centuries till 19th. Content 1. Prehistory: from primitive counting to numeral systems 2. Archaic mathematics in Mesopotamia (Babylonia) and Egypt 3. Birth of Mathematics as a deductive science in Greece: Thales and Pythagoras 4. Important developments of ideas in the classical period, paradoxes of Zeno 5. Academy of Plato and his circle, development of Logic by Aristotle 6. Hellenistic Golden Age period, Euclid of Alexandria 7. Euclid’s Elements and its role in the history of Mathematics 8. Archimedes, Eratosthenes 9. Curves in the Greek Geometry, Apollonius the Great Geometer 10. Trigonometry and astronomy: Hipparchus and Ptolemy 11. Mathematics in the late Hellenistic period 12. Mathematics in China and India 13.
    [Show full text]