Mind, Modality, and Meaning: Toward a Rationalist Physicalism

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Mind, Modality, and Meaning: Toward a Rationalist Physicalism UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA Los Angeles Mind, Modality, and Meaning: Toward a Rationalist Physicalism A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy by Gabriel Oak Rabin 2013 c Copyright by Gabriel Oak Rabin 2013 ABSTRACT OF THE DISSERTATION Mind, Modality, and Meaning: Toward a Rationalist Physicalism by Gabriel Oak Rabin Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy University of California, Los Angeles, 2013 Professor Tyler Burge, Chair This dissertation contains four independent essays (chapters) addressing a cluster of related topics in the philosophy of mind. Chapter 1: “Fundamental- ity Physicalism” argues that physicalism can usefully be conceived of as a thesis about fundamentality. The chapter explores a variety of other potential formula- tions of physicalism (particularly modal formulations), contrasts fundamentality physicalism with these theses, and offers reasons to prefer fundamentality phys- icalism over these rivals. Chapter 2:“Modal Rationalism and the Demonstrative Reply to the Master Argument Against Physicalism” introduces the Master Argument Against Physi- calism and investigates its crucial premise: the inference from an a priori gap be- tween the physical and consciousness to a lack of necessitation between the two. ii I argue against the strong form of modal rationalism that underwrites the master argument and offer a more moderate rationalist view. I offer a novel demonstrative reply to the master argument, according to which a connection between conscious experience and demonstratives, not dualism, is the source of the epistemic gap between consciousness and the physical. Chapter 3: “Conceptual Mastery and the Knowledge Argument” argues that Frank Jackson’s famous anti-physicalist knowledge argument featuring Mary, a brilliant neuroscientist raised in a black and white room, founders on a dilemma. Either (i) Mary cannot know the relevant experiential truths because of trivial obstacles that have no bearing on the truth of physicalism or (ii) once the obstacles have been removed, Mary can know the relevant truths. Chapter 4: “Toward a Theory of Conceptual Mastery” investigates the ques- tion “Under what conditions does a thinker fully understand, or have mastery of, a concept?” I argue against three views of conceptual mastery, according to which conceptual mastery is a matter of holding certain beliefs, being disposed to make certain inferences, or having certain intuitions. I propose and respond to objections to my own “meaning postulate view” of the conditions under which a thinker has mastery of a concept. iii The dissertation of Gabriel Oak Rabin is approved. David Chalmers Mark Greenberg Tyler Burge, Committee Chair University of California, Los Angeles 2013 iv with love and gratitude, for my parents, Pia and Marvin v Contents Introduction 1 0.1 Four Essays . .1 0.2 Chapter 1: Fundamentality Physicalism . .3 0.3 Chapter 2: Modal Rationalism and the Demonstrative Reply to the Master Argument Against Physicalism . .4 0.4 Chapter 3: Conceptual Mastery and the Knowledge Argument . .6 0.5 Chapter 4: Toward a Theory of Conceptual Mastery . .8 1 Fundamentality Physicalism 10 1.1 Fundamentality . 11 1.1.1 The Building Blocks of Reality . 11 1.1.2 Two kinds of creation . 14 1.1.3 The Relata of Metaphysical Generation . 16 1.1.4 The Covering Constraint . 17 1.1.5 Generation and Ground . 19 1.2 Fundamentality Physicalism . 23 1.2.1 Fundamentality Physicalism . 23 1.2.2 Fundamentality Physicalism and the Mathematical . 25 1.3 Modal Physicalism . 28 vi 1.3.1 Two Criticisms of Modal Formulations of Physicalism . 34 1.3.2 Fundamentality Physicalism and Modal Physicalism . 35 1.4 Other Physicalisms . 39 1.4.1 Everything is Narrowly or Broadly Physical: A Schema . 39 1.4.2 Applying the Schema to Fundamentality Physicalism . 40 1.4.3 Applying the Schema to Modal Physicalism . 41 1.4.4 Type Identity Physicalism . 42 1.4.5 Realization Physicalism . 43 1.4.6 Nature Physicalism . 45 1.4.7 Explanatory Physicalism . 46 1.4.8 Definition Physicalism . 48 1.4.9 Concept Physicalism . 49 1.4.10 Summary . 52 1.5 Fundamentality Physicalism and Other Physicalisms . 53 1.5.1 Against Nature and Explanatory Physicalism . 53 1.5.2 The Relevance of Fundamentally Non-Physical Worlds . 54 1.5.3 Fundamentally Non-Physical Worlds are Metaphysically Pos- sible . 55 1.5.4 Space and Time . 57 1.5.5 Lessons from the Possibility of Fundamentally Non-Physical Worlds . 58 1.5.6 Fundamentality Physicalism and the Fundamentally Non- Physical . 61 1.6 Conclusion . 62 vii 2 Modal Rationalism and the Demonstrative Reply to the Master Argu- ment Against Physicalism 64 2.1 Introduction . 65 2.2 The Master Argument Against Physicalism . 67 2.2.1 From Fundamentality to Modality to A Priori Implication . 67 2.2.2 The Master Argument . 71 2.2.3 Premise (P3): From Fundamentality to Modality . 72 2.2.4 Premise (P1): The Epistemic Gap . 72 2.2.5 Premise (P2): From an epistemic to a metaphysical gap . 75 2.3 Supplementation . 76 2.3.1 Covering Your Bases . 76 2.3.2 The Interest of the Base . 79 2.3.3 The Supplementation Question . 82 2.3.4 Naive Modal Rationalism . 83 2.3.5 Strong Modal Rationalism . 85 2.4 Return to the Master Argument . 87 2.4.1 The Strong Modal Rationalist’s Test for Fundamentality . 87 2.4.2 Canonical Expression of the Base: Semantic Neutrality . 89 2.4.3 Semantic Neutrality and the Master Argument . 95 2.5 Motivations for Modal Rationalism . 96 2.5.1 Overview . 96 2.5.2 Some Ideas Behind Modal Rationalism . 97 2.5.3 The View From Above . 100 2.5.4 The Strong Modal Rationalist Link and the View From Above102 2.6 Against Strong Modal Rationalism . 102 viii 2.6.1 The Recipe View . 102 2.6.2 The Trench View . 105 2.6.3 The Recipe View and the Strong Modal Rationalist Link . 111 2.7 The Demonstrative Reply to the Master Argument Against Physi- calism . 116 2.7.1 The Demonstrative Reply . 117 2.7.2 Comparison to other Demonstrative Oriented Replies . 121 2.7.3 The Ineliminable Connection Between Phenomenal Con- cepts and Demonstratives . 126 2.7.4 Phenomenal Concepts, Demonstration, and the Experien- tial Requirement . 132 2.7.5 Toward A More Moderate Rationalism: the Moderate Ra- tionalist Link . 133 2.7.6 Objection: The Hard Problem of Cats . 136 2.8 Conclusion . 137 3 Conceptual Mastery and the Knowledge Argument 139 3.1 Introduction . 140 3.2 Physicalism . 140 3.3 The Knowledge Argument . 142 3.4 Roadmap . 145 3.5 The Missing Concept Reply . 148 3.6 The Conceptual Mastery Reply . 151 3.7 Aside: The Phenomenal Concept Strategy . 155 3.8 The Informational Assumption and the Second Horn . 160 3.9 Lonely Mary and the Pincer Argument . 164 ix 3.10 Objections . 171 3.11 Taking Stock . 175 3.12 Conclusion . 179 4 Toward a Theory of Conceptual Mastery 181 4.1 Introduction . 182 4.2 Preliminaries . 183 4.2.1 Terminology and assumptions . 183 4.2.2 Cores and Conceptual Roles . 186 4.2.3 Precisifying the Notion of Conceptual Mastery . 188 4.2.4 Against Skepticism . 190 4.2.5 Four Theories of Conceptual Mastery . 194 4.3 Deviant Masters: Against the Necessity of Belief, Inference, or In- tuition for Conceptual Mastery . 197 4.3.1 Overview . 197 4.3.2 The Argument . 197 4.3.3 Response 1: Agnes remains disposed to infer . 199 4.3.4 Response 2: BOCHE is not a concept . 200 4.3.5 A Counterexample Without a Defective Concept . 201 4.3.6 Extending the argument against the belief and intuition views202 4.4 The Special Status Problem: Against the Sufficiency of Belief, In- ference, or Intuition for Conceptual Mastery . 202 4.4.1 Overview of the Special Status Problem . 202 4.4.2 Not Merely Belief . 203 4.4.3 Sophisticated Views . 204 4.4.4 The All and Only Problem . 205 x 4.4.5 Moving On . 207 4.5 The Meaning Postulate View . 208 4.5.1 From the Failures of Rivals to the Meaning Postulate View . 208 4.5.2 Taking to Govern Use . 209 4.5.3 Governing Use . 212 4.6 Three Objections . 214 4.6.1 Overview of the Objections . 214 4.6.2 Objection 1: Against the notion of “taking a rule to govern the use” . 214 4.6.3 Objection 2: Mastery Without Taking to Govern Use . 216 4.6.4 Objection 3: Taking to Govern Use Without Mastery . 217 4.7 Conclusion . 220 Bibliography 221 xi Acknowledgements This dissertation would not be possible without assistance and support from a wide variety of individuals over the years. First and foremost, I would like to thank my parents, Pia and Marvin, to whom this thesis is dedicated. They never pushed me to become a lawyer or a doctor or to pursue a career more respectable by traditional standards. They supported me in whatever wild endeavour I chose to pursue. When I skipped about from anthropologist to mathematician to wilderness adventurer to poet to ski bum, their support did not waver (even if their eyebrows did). The same held true when I opted for graduate school in philosophy. Thanks Mom and Dad. Other members of my family played important roles in my success as well. My brothers Micah and Noah are two of the best friends and comrades one could ask for. Whatever the occasion required, they were always ready with a sympa- thetic ear, a funny story, or a cold beer. My aunts, uncles, and cousins deserve gratitude as well. I’d particularly like to thank my grandparents Jack and Millie. Their support - both personal and financial - enabled a poor kid from Vermont with big dreams to pursue whatever intellectual pipe dream caught his fancy.
Recommended publications
  • Meanings of Determiners Heading Non-Topic Dps to the Meanings of the Corresponding Topics
    Acknowledgements First of all, I would like to thank my teachers and supervisors Manfred Bierwisch and Reinhard Blutner. Without their sympathetic help in a personally very difficult situation, I would have been unable even to start writing this dissertation. Besides this, they patiently supported me with their advice and experience in every stage of my work. The people that inspired me with discussions and comments are so numerous that there is no hope to mention all of them. Among them are Kai Alter, Daniel Büring, Johannes Dölling, Bernhard Drubig, Hans Martin Gärtner, Edward Göbbel, Michael Herweg, Caroline Heycock, Helen de Hoop, Inga Kohlhof, Manfred Krifka, Annette Lessmöllmann, Christine Maaßen, André Meinunger, Marga Reis, Michal Starke, Markus Steinbach, Wolfgang Sternefeld, Anatoli Strigin, Hubert Truckenbrodt, Enric Vallduví, Ralf Vogel, Chris Wilder, Susanne Winkler, Werner Wolff, Henk Zeevat, and Ede Zimmermann. I am indebted to the "Max-Planck-Gesellschaft" for its financial support. Special thanks go to Elena Demke, Annette Lessmöllmann, Anatoli Strigin, and Chris Wilder for correcting my English. All remaining mistakes are of course subject to my own responsibility. Last but not least, I thank my parents and my brother for everything. Table of Contents 1 Introduction . 1 2 The Dynamic Framework . 5 2.1 Donkey Sentences and Cross-sentential Anaphora . 5 2.2 Montague Semantics and File Change Semantics: A Comparison . 7 2.2.1 Montague Semantics: The General Picture . 7 2.2.2 File Change Semantics: An Overview . 11 2.2.2.1 The Strategy . 11 2.2.2.2 Files . 13 2.2.2.3 LF-Construal . 13 2.2.2.4 The Interpretation of LF .
    [Show full text]
  • Lecture 5. Formal Semantics and the Lexicon. Meaning Postulates And
    Topics in Formal Semantics, Lecture 5 Topics in Formal Semantics, Lecture 5 B.H. Partee, MGU, March 22, 2005 B.H. Partee, MGU, March 22, 2005 Lecture 5. Formal semantics and the lexicon. Ideally, this abstraction should mirror a “real” abstraction which our “language faculty” Meaning postulates and the lexicon. Adjective meanings. imposes on the real world, “natural language metaphysics” or “naïve picture of the world” (naivnaja kartina mira in the terminology of Moscow semantic school). We will discuss this later when considering the integration of formal and lexical semantics. 1. The Lexicon in Model-theoretic Semantics. .................................................................................................1 1.1. Languages, world, models. Axioms.............................................................................................................1 In Montague’s formal semantics the simple predicates of the language of intensional 1.2. Axioms and theories. ..................................................................................................................................2 logic (IL), like love, like, kiss, see, etc., are regarded as symbols (similar to the “labels” of 2. Integrating formal semantics, lexical semantics, natural language metaphysics ...............................................4 PC) which could have many possible interpretations in many different models, their “real 2.1. Formal semantics in the broader setting of natural language use. ...............................................................4
    [Show full text]
  • Semantic and Metasemantic Notions of Analyticity
    Asian Social Science; Vol. 10, No. 22; 2014 ISSN 1911-2017 E-ISSN 1911-2025 Published by Canadian Center of Science and Education Semantic and Metasemantic Notions of Analyticity Artur Ravilevich Karimov1 & Valentina Alexandrovna Kazakova2 1 Kazan Federal University, Russian Federation 2 Kazan State University of Architecture and Engineering, Russian Federation Correspondence: Artur Ravilevich Karimov, Kazan Federal University, 420008, Kremlevskaya 18, Kazan, Russian Federation. E-mail: [email protected] Received: August 1, 2014 Accepted: August 18, 2014 Online Published: October 30, 2014 doi:10.5539/ass.v10n22p285 URL: http://dx.doi.org/10.5539/ass.v10n22p285 Abstract In this article the evolution of main conceptions of analyticity is analyzed. Kant’s criteria for analytic/synthetic distinction are discussed. Frege and Carnap notions of analyticity are set out. It is shown that Frege and Carnap shifted the criteria of analyticity to the justificatory status of judgments. The notion of truth in virtue of meaning and its criticism is exposed. Critical arguments against analyticity by W. V. O. Quine are discussed. Williamson’s arguments against traditional notions of analyticity are formulated. Williamson maintains that analytic truths are reduced to truths of other base classes-necessary, semantic or logical. It is shown that the stipulative definition of analyticity is vulnerable to Williamson’s argument. Russell’s conception of truth in virtue of reference determiner is exposed and evaluated. It is defended that the notion of truth in virtue of reference determiner is immune to many standard objections against analyticity. Keywords: analyticity, meaning, stipulation, reference 1. Introduction Analyticity is one the most controversial concepts in the history of analytic philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • Three Approaches of Word Sentence Meaning in Translation of English Slang Word Into Indonesian in the Novel “The Adventure of Oliver Twist”
    THREE APPROACHES OF WORD SENTENCE MEANING IN TRANSLATION OF ENGLISH SLANG WORD INTO INDONESIAN IN THE NOVEL “THE ADVENTURE OF OLIVER TWIST” Ni Putu Wintia Sunny Kumara Sakti Villa Jln. Suweta Banjar Sambahan Ubud Phone: +62 361 437806 , Celular Phone: +62 89685689099 [email protected] ABSRACT The slang expression means coming to democratic atmosphere in language since the meaning embodied is not absolute. It depends upon who uses it, in which group the users belong to, and in what situation slang word occur. Having knowledge of slang, it means the user is bilingual, or even multilingual. The question emerged is how the user of slang employ slang in their daily communication. Their choice of certain slang replacing the standard may have a certain purposes. Therefore, it is really difficult to translate it in Indonesian. How to transfer the meaning of slang that contains senses about culture, habit, and identity of specific group of people is a complex undertaking. The form of English slang used in the novel "The Adventure of Oliver Twist” by Charles Dickens is generally in the form of primary slang. There were sixteen primary slang words uttered by the character in the novel. However, there was only four secondary slang words found in the novel. So the primary slang more common used by the character in novel. There are three approaches that can be used to find the conceptual meaning of word in the process of translation. There are reference theory, componential analysis, and meaning postulate. Keywords: slang word, reference theory, componential analysis, meaning postulate. ABSTRAK Kata Slang merupakan expresi demokratis dalam bahasa yang menganduk makna tidak mutlak.
    [Show full text]
  • Problems in the Representation of the Logical Form of Generics, Plurals, and Mass Nouns
    12 Problems in the Representation of the Logical Form of Generics, Plurals, and Mass Nouns LENHART K. SCHUBERT FRANCIS JEFFRY PELLETIER Department of Computing Science University of Alberta INTRODUCTION We wish to discuss some problems involved in representing the 'logical form' of sentences whose subjects are generics, (bare) plurals and mass terms. We shall not here have much to say about the syntax of such sentences, except occasionally to refer to such (arguably) syntactic features as [ ±stative]. We shall also not get embroiled in such issues as exactly what information should be counted as part of the 'logical form' of a sentence in general. We will, for example, remain agnostic on the question of the proper place for (Montague-style) meaning postulates, the proper place for Quantifier Raising, and the proper place for the representation of certain ambiguities involving quantifiers and other logical operations. Instead, om concern is with the final representation of certain natural language sentences, a represe11tation which is immediately correlated with the truth conditions of the original sentence. We take this to be more-or-less first­ order quantification theory augmented with certain operators, but feel free to bring in Montagovian intensional logic, expecial!y when discussing those 385 NEW DIREcnONS IN SEMANTICS Copyright© 1987. by Academic Press Inc. (London) Ltd. A I! ..;~1.•~ ~f ••~•...,.1.,.-.;~n ;" ~nv fn~ ••~•~, • .-1 386 L. K. Schubert and F. J~ Pelletier theorists who make it central in their account. To give a feel for what level our concerns lie at, consider (1) (a) Whales are mammals Now, there are many 'levels of representation' that different theorists have proposed for such a sentence.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Semantics of Propositional Attitude Reports
    GOTHENBURG MONOGRAPHS IN LINGUISTICS 13 ON THE SEMANTICS OF PROPOSITIONAL ATTITUDE REPORTS Mats DahllofÈ ¡¢ £ ¤ Department of Linguistics GoteborÈ g University, Sweden 1995 ABSTRACT This is a study on the truth-conditional semantics of propositional attitude attribution statements. It is suggested that attitude contents should be characterized in terms of abstract concepts, which are connected by way of a number of basic logical relations derived from a version of Quinean predicate-functor logic. This allows us to handle all logical relationships de®nable by ®rst-order predicate calculus in a way that does not exploit variable-like entities. Individual, predicate, and propositional concepts are recognized. These concepts provide the relata of various mental attitude relations and may denote (or may fail to denote) other kinds of object. The resulting framework is itself formalized in ®rst-order predicate calculus. This proposal is intended to give an account that is to a high degree independent of any particular view of the metaphysical, psychological or epistemological status of propositional attitude reports. An overview of different kinds of propositional and other conceptual attitude report constructions in English is given and it is suggested how the framework proposed can be applied to them. KEY WORDS: Meaning, Semantics, Logic, Propositional Attitudes, Truth Conditions, Intentions, Concepts, Reference, Predicate-Functor Logic, Intentionality Published by: The Department of Linguistics, GoteborÈ g University, 412 98 GoteborÈ g, Sweden.
    [Show full text]
  • Meaning Postulates That Constrain the Class of Models in Which Such Sent- Ences Are Evaluated
    Facta Philosophica 5, 2003: xx–xx © Peter Lang, Switzerland Meaning-Postulates, Inference, and the Relational/ Notional Ambiguity1 Graeme Forbes This paper is a draft of work in progress. Please do not cite without first checking with me. 11/9/02 1 What notional readings mean Some attitude ascriptions use quantified or possessive noun phrases (qnp’s or pnp’s) in the specification of the content of the attitude being ascribed. When the ascription is propositional, this gives rise to an ambiguity Quine (1955) labelled “re- lational/notional”. For example, (1) Oedipus wants to marry a member of his family can be understood relationally, to mean, as we might naively put it, that for some (non-descriptive) singular np denoting a member of his family, Oedipus has the at- titude of desiring-to-make-true towards the proposition he would literally express with (his words for) I marry np. In this case, he stands in the wanting-to-marry relation to a “specific” or “particular” individual. But an alternative understanding of (1) is available, the notional one, on which it says that Oedipus has the attitude of desiring-to-make-true towards the proposition he would literally express with (his words for) ‘I marry a memberRAFT of my family’. Here we are to suppose3 that he 1 This paper is a successor to (Forbes 2000) and (Forbes 2002), though it can be read independently. In addition to those acknowledged in (Forbes 2002) I thank Michael Martin, Daniel Nolan and Diana Raffman for comments and discussion at meetings of the Society for Exact Philosophy (where one lets one’sD inner logical positivist rock and roll) and the Joint Session.
    [Show full text]
  • Functional Structure, Quantifiers, and Meaning Postulates Author(S): Jerry A
    Functional Structure, Quantifiers, and Meaning Postulates Author(s): Jerry A. Fodor and Janet Dean Fodor Source: Linguistic Inquiry, Vol. 11, No. 4 (Autumn, 1980), pp. 759-770 Published by: The MIT Press Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/4178191 Accessed: 04-03-2017 02:01 UTC JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://about.jstor.org/terms The MIT Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Linguistic Inquiry This content downloaded from 146.96.24.37 on Sat, 04 Mar 2017 02:01:10 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms Remarks and Replies Functional Structure, Quantifiers, and Meaning Postulates* Jerry A. Fodor, Janet Dean Fodor Bresnan (1978) considers the familiar fact that John ate entails John ate something (though John slept does not entail *John slept something), and asks: "How are the logical argument structures of verbs related to their syntactic contexts?" She rejects the answer that John ate contains a syntactically intransitive verb eat whose object has been deleted. Her proposal is that John ate is syntactically intransitive, just as it appears to be; eat is transitive only at the level of functional structure. The relation between the intransitive syntactic structure and the transitive functional structure is specified by the lexical mapping rule (1).
    [Show full text]
  • Meaning Postulates and Deference*
    Meaning Postulates and Deference* RICHARD HORSEY July 2000 Abstract Fodor (1998) argues that most lexical concepts have no internal structure. He rejects what he calls Inferential Role Semantics (IRS), the view that primitive concepts are constituted by their inferential relations, on the grounds that this violates the compositionality constraint and leads to an unacceptable form of holism. In rejecting IRS, Fodor must also reject meaning postulates. I argue, contra Fodor, that meaning postulates must be retained, but that when suitably constrained they are not susceptible to his arguments against IRS. This has important implications for the view that certain of our concepts are deferential. A consequence of the arguments I present is that deference is relegated to a relatively minor role in what Sperber (1997) refers to as reflective concepts; deference has no important role to play in the vast majority of our intuitive concepts. 1 Introduction In his 1998 book Concepts: Where Cognitive Science Went Wrong, Jerry Fodor makes a plausible case for conceptual atomism. On this view, nearly all lexical concepts (that is, concepts expressed by monomorphemic lexical items) have no internal structure. He rejects alternative views—that concepts are definitions or prototypes or ‘theories’—largely for the following reason: they hold that concepts are constituted at least in part by their inferential relations. He calls any theory of this kind an Inferential Role Semantics (IRS). Fodor has a general argument which he takes to indicate that inferential relations cannot be content constitutive, and hence that any version of IRS is untenable. Basically, his argument is that IRS is incompatible with a fundamental aspect of thought—its compositionality.
    [Show full text]
  • Lecture 4. Formal Semantics and the Lexicon: Introduction to Issues and History, and a Case Study of Adjectives
    Formal Semantics and Lexical Semantics, Lecture 4 Barbara H. Partee, MGU, March 28, 2013 Lecture 4. Formal Semantics and the Lexicon: Introduction to Issues and History, and a Case Study of Adjectives 1. The Lexicon in Model-theoretic Semantics. .................................................................................................... 1 1.1. Introduction and historical overview ............................................................................................................. 1 1.2. Language-World-Models. Natural language metaphysics. ........................................................................... 3 1.3. Meaning postulates. History and examples. ................................................................................................. 4 1.3.1. Meaning postulates - history. .............................................................................................................. 4 1.3.2. Meaning postulates - examples. ........................................................................................................... 5 2. Differences between lexical and compositional semantics ................................................................................. 6 2.1. Is the “semantics of syntax” autonomous? .................................................................................................... 6 2.2. How much lexical semantics does formal semantics “need”? ...................................................................... 7 3. What does formal semantics have to offer to lexical
    [Show full text]
  • Meaning Postulates
    Meaning Postulates by RUDOLF CARNAP University of Chicago 1. The Problem of Truth Based upon Meaning Philosophers have often distinguished two kinds of truth: the truth of some statements is logical, necessary, based upon meaning, while that of other statements is empirical, contingent, dependent upon the facts of the world. The following two statements belong to the first kind: (1) ‘Fido is black or Fido is not black’ (2) ‘If Jack is a bachelor, then he is not married’ In either case it is sufficient to understand the statement in order to establish its truth; knowledge of (extra-linguistic) facts is not involved. However, there is a difference. To ascertain the truth of (1), only the meanings of the logical particles (‘is,’ ‘or,’ ‘not’) are required; the meanings of the descriptive (i.e., nonlogical) words (‘Fido,’ ‘black’) are irrelevant (except that they must belong to suitable types). For (2), on the other hand, the Editors’ Note. In printing this paper, it has been necessary to substitute boldface type for the German Gothic which Professor Carnap uses for metalinguistic symbols. 65 66 PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES meanings of some descriptive words are involved, viz., those of ‘bachelor’ and ‘married.’ Quinel has recently emphasized the distinction; he uses the term ‘analytic’ for the wider kind of statement to which both examples belong, and ‘logically true’ for the narrower kind to which (1) belongs but not (2). I shall likewise use these two terms for the explicanda. But I do not share Quine’s skepticism; he is doubtful whether an explication of analyticity, especially one in semantics, is possible, and even whether there is a sufficiently clear explicandum, especially with respect to natural languages.
    [Show full text]
  • Loebnersubcompositionality Formatiert
    Sub-compositionality ABSTRACT. It is commonly held in most accounts of sentence semantics that semantic com- position is homomorphous to syntactic composition. Consequently, rules of semantic compos- ition are defined in terms of syntactic categories of expressions. The paper argues that this assumption is not a necessary consequence of the Principle of Compositionality, and in fact in need of revision. There appear to be types of syntactic constructions where semantic sub-rules of composition apply to mere semantic sub-types of the construction. Such constructions are called sub-compositional. Accounts in the tradition of Montague’s were able to avoid sub- compositionality, and thereby adhere to homomorphy, only at the expense of ‘generalizing to the worst case’. It is argued that this method is not in accordance with the aims of an approp- riate theory of composition. Rather such a theory should properly acknowledge differences in compositional properties among semantic types of expressions. Using the example of German verb gradation with sehr ‘very’, it is argued that the compositional analysis of certain sub- compositional constructions may require deep decomposition of lexical meanings. Although the general assumption of homomorphy is therefore no longer rigidly tenable, this does not mean that the Principle of Compositionality is to be abandoned or modified. 1 Rules in compositional semantics 1.1 The Principle of Compositionality This article will be based on the following version of the Principle of Compositionality (PC): Principle of Compositionality The meaning of a complex expression is a function of the lexical meanings of its com- ponents and the syntactic structure of the whole.
    [Show full text]