David R. Griffin, "Relativism, Divine Causation, and Biblical Theology."

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

David R. Griffin, From Owen Thomas, ed. God’s Activity in the World: The Contemporary Problem. AAR Studies in Religion 31. Chico, CA: Scholar Press, 1983. 8. RELATIVISM, DIVINE CAUSATION, AND BIBLICAL THEOLOGY David R. Griffin The most influential way among Christian theologians of un- derstanding the relation between divine and nondivine causation has been that based upon the schema of primary and secondary causa- tion. I believe that this schema (besides being unintelligible, and resulting in an insuperable problem of evil for philosophical theology) 1 has unfortunate implications for understanding the re- lation between the work of the biblical scholar, on the one hand, and Christian faith and systematic theology, on the other. In particular, this primary-secondary schema of causation leads to a relativism which renders arbitrary both Christian faith and the practice of devoting special attention to the texts of the biblical tradition. Furthermore, the difficulties inherent in this schema have been instrumental, I believe, in leading many theologians to omit the category of divine causation altogether. In the first part of this paper I will discuss the relativistic implications of the schema of primary and secondary causation. In the second part I will discuss an alternative understanding of the relation of divine and nondivine causation suggested by the process philosophy of Alfred North Whitehead. In the third part I will suggest some implications of this process view for conceiving the task of "biblical theology." I The Schema of Primary and Secondary Causation According to the schema of primary and secondary causation, divine and nondivine causation are on two different "levels." God is not in any sense "one cause among others"; rather, his causation is on a totally different level from that of all the worldly causes. While these worldly causes may be called "natural," they include all the distinctively human, and therefore "histor- ical," influences as well as those of nonhuman nature. All of these worldly or natural causes are termed "secondary" causes, while God is considered the "primary" cause of every event. God's From Encounter 36 (1975): 342-60. Reprinted with permission. 117 118 God's Activity in the World causation is termed "primary" not only out of deference, but also because the “secondary“ causes are instrumentalities of the divine will. In terms of this distinction, it is obvious that a "miracle" could not be simply defined as an "act of God," since God is the (primary) cause of every event. Rather, a miracle differs from non-miraculous events only in that, while God normally uses secon- dary causes to execute his will, in performing a miracle he brings the event about directly, without using any mediating instruments. This notion of two different levels implies that there are different perspectives from which to regard any non-miraculous event. On the one hand, one can regard it in relation to God. When so considered, it must be regarded as totally determined by God. The divine causation is the sufficient cause for its existence and total actuality, down to the most minute detail. Accordingly, reference to the divine causation constitutes a sufficient expla- nation for the event in question. Reference to conditioning non- divine causes is not necessary, since these "causes" were them- selves totally caused by God, and hence exercise no autonomous (from God) causation, but are mere instruments of his purpose. On the other hand, one can regard the non-miraculous event in relation to its nondivine antecedent causes. Regarded from this perspective, no reference to God's causation is needed. A suffi- cient explanation for the event can in principle be found within the realm of "secondary" causation. There are various ways that one can understand nondivine sufficient causation. If one is a radical determinist, the antecedent secondary causes will be re- garded as constituting the sufficient cause for any event. If one is a dualist, the antecedent events will be regarded as constituting sufficient causes for certain types of events (e.g., nonliving ones for a vitalist, or nonhuman ones for a Cartesian dualist), while the sufficient cause for other events (e.g., living, or hu- man) may be regarded as consisting of the antecedent causes plus the self-determination of the event in question. The nondualistic nondeterminist may regard every event as requiring reference both to antecedents and to self-causation for its sufficient explana- tion. But in any case, a sufficient explanation for any non- miraculous event can in principle be found without any reference to divine causation. This understanding of the relation of divine to nondivine causation has been widely accepted by "liberals" and "conservatives" alike. Within the context of the primary-secondary schema, Griffin: Relativism, Divine Causation 119 liberals and conservatives differ only in regard to whether miracles (as defined above) ever occur. Conservatives affirm the occurrence of one or more such events, while liberals deny that they ever 2 occur. At least they deny that there can ever be a sufficiently good reason for affirming that an event has happened without any "natural" (secondary) causes. It is most important to see that this is where the issue lies as long as the schema of primary and secondary causation is pre- supposed. The issue is not between "naturalistic" and "super- naturalistic" explanations, since both groups affirm supernatural causation. Nor is it between those who, while believing that all events have naturalcauses, do and do not think that some or all events require reference to God in order to have a "sufficient" explanation. For, both groups hold that an ultimate explanation for any event requires reference to its primary cause, God. And, most importantly, both groups agree that God is not “one cause among others," to be introduced as a supplementary factor within the context of a discussion of natural causes. The term "divine causation" can never refer to one cause among others; it is either used to refer to the primary sufficient cause, which is on a dif- ferent level from the natural causes, or it is not used at all. Accordingly, the only real item for debate is whether God, who usually employs secondary causes which provide sufficient explana- tions on their own level, always uses these. This schema in its "liberal" form has understandably been widely accepted, more or less self-consciously, by Christian bib- lical scholars. For it allowed them to retain as private citizens faith in divine providence, and yet as public historians to accept without qualification the almost universally accepted convention that historians qua historians do not refer to divine influence as an explanatory category. That is, while they could of course re- port that, for example, Jones believed he was called by God to perform a certain deed, the historian can never affirm that "Jones performed this deed (partly) because he was actually influenced by God to do so." Since the idea of "divine causation" belongs to a different level of discourse from that of “natural (including historical) causation,* this means that "faith" and "history" are separate (but equal) perspectives, never to be merged into a higher synthe- sis of "faithful history." The liberal Christian who is a historian need not and should not suppose that he is privy to an additional causal factor (divine influence) unknown to his secular colleagues. 120 God's Activity in the World For, even though he believes in divine providence, he knows this belief is irrelevant to the task of the historian, since God always provides causes which are sufficient in terms of the level of ex- planation at which historians operate. Hence, he can be as fully secular as his non-believing colleagues. For, unlike the conser- vative Christian historian, he can be fully secular even in regard to the central events of the biblical records. However, while this view has its advantages, it also has un- fortunate consequences, both for Christian faith in general and the role of the biblical scholar in particular. These consequences can be seen by first looking at this view's implications for the use of the terms "special act of God" and "revelation." A. "Specialal Acts of God" and "Revelation." On the basis of some views of the relation between divine and nondivine causation, there would be a meaningful distinction between a "special act of God" and a "revelation." For example, if one accepts some form of popu- lar supernaturalism according to which the world's processes normally go along independently of God's action (except for perhaps some sort of undifferentiated sustaining action), with God only occasionally interrupting those processes by some special action, these occasional interruptive actions could meaningfully be called "special acts of God," whether or not any human beings recognized them as such. In fact, they could have occurred long before any humans appeared on the scene, e.g., the first creation of life could be considered such an act of God. A conservative version of the primary-secondary schema will have essentially the same im- port. God is equally the cause of all non-miraculous or ordinary events, i.e., those with sufficient natural causes, so they are all acts of God, while those events which cannot be explained in natural categories, and must be referred immediately to the divine causation, are extraordinary acts of God. Hence, both the popular supernaturalist and the conservative primary-secondary schematist can refer to certain events in them- selves as "special (or extraordinary) acts of God." As such these past events can be clearly distinguished from divine "revelations," since for an event to become a revelation it must be received as such by someone. By definition, a revelation must be a revelation to someone, whereas an act of God is what it is independently of any person's recognition of it.
Recommended publications
  • The Relativism of Blame and Williams' Relativism of Distance
    ABSTRACT: Bernard Williams is a sceptic about the objectivity of moral value, embracing instead a certain qualified moral relativism—the ‘relativism of distance’. His attitude to blame too is in part sceptical (he thought it often involved a certain ‘fantasy’). I will argue that the relativism of distance is unconvincing, even incoherent; but also that it is detachable from the rest of Williams’ moral philosophy. I will then go on to propose an entirely localized thesis I call the relativism of blame, which says that when an agent’s moral shortcomings by our lights are a matter of their living according to the moral thinking of their day, judgements of blame are out of order. Finally, I will propose a form of moral judgement we may sometimes quite properly direct towards historically distant agents when blame is inappropriate—moral-epistemic disappointment. Together these two proposals may help release us from the grip of the idea that moral appraisal always involves the potential applicability of blame, and so from a key source of the relativist idea that moral appraisal is inappropriate over distance. The Relativism of Blame and Williams’ Relativism of Distance Must I think of myself as visiting in judgement all the reaches of history? Of course, one can imagine oneself as Kant at the court of King Arthur, disapproving of its injustices, but exactly what grip does this get on one’s ethical or political thought?1 Bernard Williams famously argued for a distinctive brand of moral relativism, which he regarded as capturing the truth in relativism, and which he called the relativism of distance.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Coherence of Sartre's Defense of Existentialism Against The
    Untitled 7/12/05 3:41 PM On the Coherence of Sartre’s Defense of Existentialism Against the Essentialist Charge of Ethical Relativism in His “Existentialism and Humanism” Brad Cherry I.Introduction Although its slim volume may suggest otherwise, Jean-Paul Sartre’s “Existentialism and Humanism” treats a wealth of existentialist themes. Indeed, within its pages, Sartre characterizes many of the hallmarks of existentialist thought, including subjectivity, freedom, responsibility, anguish, forlornness, despair, and so on. Perhaps most importantly, however, Sartre’s “Existentialism and Humanism” occasions a defense of existentialism against its most frequently dealt criticisms, particularly the essentialist charge that existentialism necessarily gives rise to ethical relativism. And while this defense may seem convincing at first, in many places, it also seems to abandon, for the sake of its project, the fundamental commitments of existentialism, at least as Sartre understands them. Thus, in this essay, I critically examine the coherence of Sartre’s defense of existentialism against the essentialist charge of ethical relativism. To the extent that that defense relies largely upon his espousal of an existentialist ethics, I examine, in particular, whether that ethics coheres with the fundamental commitments of existentialism as he understands them. Following this examination, I conclude that (a) the fundamental commitments of existentialism preclude Sartre from coherently positing objectively valid normative ethical statements, that (b) because he nonetheless posits such statements in his espousal of an existentialist ethics, his defense of existentialism against the essentialist charge of ethical relativism breaks down, and finally, that (c) although this incoherence presents a substantial problem for Sartre, one may still defend his attempt to espouse an existentialist ethics.
    [Show full text]
  • Moral Relativism
    City University of New York (CUNY) CUNY Academic Works Publications and Research New York City College of Technology 2020 The Incoherence of Moral Relativism Carlo Alvaro CUNY New York City College of Technology How does access to this work benefit ou?y Let us know! More information about this work at: https://academicworks.cuny.edu/ny_pubs/583 Discover additional works at: https://academicworks.cuny.edu This work is made publicly available by the City University of New York (CUNY). Contact: [email protected] 1 The Incoherence of Moral Relativism Abstract This paper is a response to Park Seungbae’s article, “Defence of Cultural Relativism”. Some of the typical criticisms of moral relativism are the following: moral relativism is erroneously committed to the principle of tolerance, which is a universal principle; there are a number of objective moral rules; a moral relativist must admit that Hitler was right, which is absurd; a moral relativist must deny, in the face of evidence, that moral progress is possible; and, since every individual belongs to multiple cultures at once, the concept of moral relativism is vague. Park argues that such contentions do not affect moral relativism and that the moral relativist may respond that the value of tolerance, Hitler’s actions, and the concept of culture are themselves relative. In what follows, I show that Park’s adroit strategy is unsuccessful. Consequently, moral relativism is incoherent. Keywords: Moral relativism; moral absolutism; objectivity; tolerance; moral progress 2 The Incoherence of Moral Relativism Moral relativism is a meta-ethical theory according to which moral values and duties are relative to a culture and do not exist independently of a culture.
    [Show full text]
  • Theory Reflections: Linguistic Determinism/Relativism
    Theory Reflections: Linguistic Determinism/Relativism The Theory The theory of linguistic determinism and relativity presents a two-sided phenomenon: Does the specific language (and culture) we are exposed to in childhood determine, in fact, how we perceive the world, how we think, and how we express ourselves? If this is so, then, it must also be the case that each language (and the culture it represents) necessarily provides its speakers with a specific and differing view of that same world, a different way of thinking, and a different way of expressing. This notion is related to a parallel issue that has existed throughout the centuries—are there also universal absolutes that transcend all linguistic (and cultural) particulars? Recent research suggests there may be elements of both. Linguistic determinism came to the attention of linguists and anthropologists during the 1930s, prompted by the work of Benjamin Lee Whorf. Using prevailing linguistic approaches of his time, Whorf, who studied indigenous languages, found surprising contrasts with European tongues in terms of how they reflected and spoke about reality (e.g., how they segment the time continuum, construct lexical hierarchies and, in short, encode a different view of the world, or Weltanschauung). The Whorf-Sapir hypothesis, as it came to be known (Sapir was his teacher), gained increasing attention and prompted the notion of language determinism/relativity. In other words, the language we are born to has a direct effect upon how we conceptualize, think, interact, and express—a direct relationship between human language and human thinking This notion has remained at the center of a debate for more than half a century.
    [Show full text]
  • The Problem of Relativism.Indb
    Richard Schantz, Markus Seidel The Problem of Relativism in the Sociology of (Scientific) Knowledge P h i l o s o p h i s c h e A n a l y s e P h i l o s o p h i c a l A n a l y s i s Herausgegeben von / Edited by Herbert Hochberg • Rafael Hüntelmann • Christian Kanzian Richard Schantz • Erwin Tegtmeier Band 43 / Volume 43 Richard Schantz, Markus Seidel The Problem of Relativism in the Sociology of (Scientific) Knowledge Bibliographic information published by the Deutsche Nationalbibliothek The Deutsche Nationalbibliothek lists this publication in the Deutsche Nationalbibliografie; detailed bibliographic data are available in the Internet at http://dnb.d-nb.de. North and South America by Transaction Books Rutgers University Piscataway, NJ 08854-8042 [email protected] United Kingdom, Ireland, Iceland, Turkey, Malta, Portugal by Gazelle Books Services Limited White Cross Mills Hightown LANCASTER, LA1 4XS [email protected] Livraison pour la France et la Belgique: Librairie Philosophique J.Vrin 6, place de la Sorbonne; F-75005 PARIS Tel. +33 (0)1 43 54 03 47; Fax +33 (0)1 43 54 48 18 www.vrin.fr 2011 ontos verlag P.O. Box 15 41, D-63133 Heusenstamm www.ontosverlag.com ISBN 978-3-86838-126-9 2011 No part of this book may be reproduced, stored in retrieval systems or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, microfilming, recording or otherwise without written permission from the Publisher, with the exception of any material supplied specifically for the purpose of being entered and executed
    [Show full text]
  • May 03 CI.Qxd
    Philosophy of Chemistry by Eric Scerri Of course, the field of compu- hen I push my hand down onto my desk it tational quantum chemistry, does not generally pass through the which Dirac and other pioneers Wwooden surface. Why not? From the per- of quantum mechanics inadver- spective of physics perhaps it ought to, since we are tently started, has been increas- told that the atoms that make up all materials consist ingly fruitful in modern mostly of empty space. Here is a similar question that chemistry. But this activity has is put in a more sophisticated fashion. In modern certainly not replaced the kind of physics any body is described as a superposition of chemistry in which most practitioners are engaged. many wavefunctions, all of which stretch out to infin- Indeed, chemists far outnumber scientists in all other ity in principle. How is it then that the person I am fields of science. According to some indicators, such as talking to across my desk appears to be located in one the numbers of articles published per year, chemistry particular place? may even outnumber all the other fields of science put together. If there is any sense in which chemistry can The general answer to both such questions is that be said to have been reduced then it can equally be although the physics of microscopic objects essen- said to be in a high state of "oxidation" regarding cur- tially governs all of matter, one must also appeal to rent academic and industrial productivity. the laws of chemistry, material science, biology, and Starting in the early 1990s a group of philosophers other sciences.
    [Show full text]
  • Causes As Explanations: a Critique*
    JAEGWON KIM CAUSES AS EXPLANATIONS: A CRITIQUE* Causes certainly are connected with effects; but this is because our theories connect them, not because the world is held together by cosmic glue. 1 Norwood Russell Hanson ABSTRACT. This paper offers a critique of the view that causation can be analyzed in terms of explanation. In particular, the following points are argued: (1) a genuine explanatory analysis of causation must make use of a fully epistemological-psychological notion of explanation; (2) it is unlikely that the relatively clear-cut structure of the causal relation can be captured by the relatively unstructured relation of explanation; (3) the explanatory relation does not always parallel the direction of causation; (4) certain difficulties arise for any attempt to construct a nonrelativistic relation of caus- ation from the essentially relativistic relation of explanation; and (5) to analyze causation as explanation is to embrace a form of "causal idealism", the view that causal connec- tions are not among the objective features of the world. The paper closes with a brief discussion of the contrast between the two fundamentally opposed viewpoints about causality, namely causal idealism and causal realism. It is little more than a truism to say that causes explain their effects, or that to ask for the cause of an event is to ask for an explanation of why or how the event occurred. This close association between causation and explanation is amply mirrored in language: we answer 'why'-questions with 'becuase'- statements, and surely there is more than an orthographic resemblance between 'cause' and 'because'. The association is also ancient: it goes back to Aristotle, who characterized true, scientific knowledge as knowledge of the 'why' of things, that is, knowledge of the cause that makes a thing what it is and not something else.
    [Show full text]
  • Ethical Relativism by Matt Slick by CARM (Christian Apologetics & Research Ministry)
    Ethical Relativism by Matt Slick By CARM (Christian Apologetics & Research Ministry) Ethical relativism is the position that there are no moral absolutes, no moral right and wrongs. Instead, right and wrong are based on social norms. Such could be the case with "situational ethics," which is a category of ethical relativism. At any rate, ethical relativism would mean that our morals have evolved, that they have changed over time, and that they are not absolute. One advantage of ethical relativism is that it allows for a wide variety of cultures and practices. It also allows people to adapt ethically as the culture, knowledge, and technology change in society. This is a good and valid form of relativism. The disadvantage of ethical relativism is that truth, right and wrong, and justice are all relative. Just because a group of people think that something is right does not make it so. Slavery is a good example of this. Two hundred years ago in America, slavery was the norm and morally acceptable. Now it is not. Relativism also does not allow for the existence of an absolute set of ethics. Logically, if there are no absolute ethics, then there can be no Divine Absolute Ethics Giver. Requiring an absolute set of ethics implies an Absolute Ethics Giver, which can easily be extrapolated as being God. This would be opposed to ethical relativism. Therefore, ethical relativism would not support the idea of an absolute God, and it would exclude religious systems based upon absolute morals; that is, it would be absolute in its condemnation of absolute ethics.
    [Show full text]
  • Objective, Multiplistic, and Relative Truth in Developmental Psychology and Legal Education, 62 Tul
    John Marshall Law School The John Marshall Institutional Repository Faculty Scholarship 1-1-1988 Objective, Multiplistic, and Relative Truth in Developmental Psychology and Legal Education, 62 Tul. L. Rev. 1237 (1988) Paul T. Wangerin John Marshall Law School Follow this and additional works at: http://repository.jmls.edu/facpubs Part of the Legal Education Commons Recommended Citation Paul T. Wangerin, Objective, Multiplistic, and Relative Truth in Developmental Psychology and Legal Education, 62 Tul. L. Rev. 1237 (1988). http://repository.jmls.edu/facpubs/274 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by The oJ hn Marshall Institutional Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Scholarship by an authorized administrator of The oJ hn Marshall Institutional Repository. OBJECTIVE, MULTIPLISTIC, AND RELATIVE TRUTH IN DEVELOPMENTAL PSYCHOLOGY AND LEGAL EDUCATION PAUL T. WANGERIN* INTRODUCTION Two thousand years ago, Protagoras, a teacher of lawyers, began what has since become one of the most enduring and pain- ful philosophic debates in western civilization. "Man is the mea- sure of all things," Protagoras insisted, arguing that everything is relative.1 Since nothing in nature is fixed and certain, Protag- oras urged, human beings must create their own meanings and truths. Plato claimed otherwise.2 Some things, Plato argued, are fixed and certain. Truth itself has an objective meaning which does not vary from time to time or from place to place. * Associate Professor of Law, John Marshall Law School. Many people have read this article and have made helpful comments. My principal debt in this context is to psychologists William Perry, Jane Loevinger, Patricia King, and Norma Haan.
    [Show full text]
  • Moral Relativism Explained
    Moral Relativism Explained Gilbert Harman 1 What Is Moral Relativism? According to moral relativism, there is not a single true morality. There are a variety of possible moralities or moral frames of reference, and whether something is morally right or wrong, good or bad, just or unjust, etc. is a relative matter—relative to one or another morality or moral frame of reference. Something can be morally right relative to one moral frame of reference and 1 morally wrong relative to another. It is useful to compare moral relativism to other kinds of 2 relativism. One possible comparison is with motion relativism. There is no such thing as absolute motion or absolute rest. Whether something is moving or at rest is relative to a spatio- temporal frame of reference. Something may be at rest in one such frame of reference and moving in another. There is no such thing as absolute motion and absolute rest, but we can make do with relative motion and rest. Similarly, moral relativism is the view that, although there is no such thing as absolute right and wrong, we can make do with relative right and wrong. 3 Paul Boghossian suggests a different comparison. When people decided that there were no witches and no such thing as witchcraft, they did not become relativists about witches; they gave up their beliefs about witches. It would have been a mistake for them to conclude that witchcraft is a relative matter, so that someone could be a witch in relation to one witch framework but not in relation to another.
    [Show full text]
  • Motives of Pinker's Criticism of Whorfian
    Sławomir Wacewicz LANGUAGE AND THINKING: MOTIVES OF PINKER’S CRITICISM OF WHORFIAN LINGUISTIC RELATIVISM In The Language Instinct (1995 [1994], henceforth: TLI), a book that despite its popular character has become virtually a classic in discussions concerning the innateness of language, Steven Pinker attacks the broadly understood “Whorfian” standpoint according to which human thinking is influenced in fundamental ways by one’s native language. Due to the status of the author and popularity of the book, it is an influential voice in the ongoing debate on the mutual relation between language and “thought.” Rather than joining this debate, in the present text I would like to examine the construction and integrity of Pinker’s argumentation in TLI. I suggest that this author’s attack on broadly understood interdependence of language and thought is motivated by his general theoretical commitments, rather than by independent evidence. 1. Introduction and the reconstruction of Pinker’s initial position The best way of reconstructing Steven Pinker’s initial position is by situating his views in the general spectrum of approaches present in contemporary Cognitive Science. Pinker’s principal commitments appear to be evolutionary, which is visible in his popular reception, where he is recognised as an evolutionary psychologist much more readily than as a linguist or psycholinguist. Such a theoretical inclination often goes together with two general views: nativism and modularism; views that are separable, but related and mutually supporting. Steven Pinker is an advocate for both nativism and modularism with respect to language, as well as to cognition in general. In crudest terms, nativism is a view according to which human knowledge (or, more generally, the content of the human mind) is in some vital part innate.
    [Show full text]
  • Virtue Theory, Relativism and Survival
    International Journal of Social Science and Humanity, Vol. 3, No. 4, July 2013 Virtue Theory, Relativism and Survival Joseph Grcic there can be no objective or universal knowledge in any Abstract—Virtue theory claims that moral virtues define the human endeavor including ethics. moral person. Moral relativism claims there are no necessary Metaethical relativism is the claim that moral concepts universal moral values-this theory is not rationally sustainable have meaning only within a given cultural framework. Any as a theory of ethics. The necessary functions of social order two different normative systems are incommensurable and and existence require certain moral virtues. There are six main universal moral virtues: wisdom, courage, justice, humanity, one cannot be rationally judged to be superior to the other. temperance, and transcendence. Societies cannot function Relativism in the extreme form conflicts with the fact that efficiently without these core virtues. there are similarities in moral virtues found across all stable cultures. These virtues and values are a function of the Index terms—Moral relativism, social structure, virtue universality of human nature, human needs and the common theory. problems societies must solve to survive. The differences that do exist in moral norms are limited and arise due to different social and historical contexts, ideologies and belief I. INTRODUCTION systems which shape moral norms to some degree. But The realm of ethics seems to be one of the most these differences are secondary when compared to the larger conflicted and uncertain in philosophy and in human history. common foundation of core values based on the common This conflict would be tolerable if it did not have practical problems which must be solved for communities to survive.
    [Show full text]