Discretion and Rights*

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Discretion and Rights* NEIL MACCORMICK DISCRETION AND RIGHTS* The first aim of this paper is to propose an analysis of one, perhaps central, distinction between legal provisions which confer rights and legal provisions which confer merely discretionary benefits. The second is to see whether this distinction may not cast new light on a number of disputed points in contemporary legal theory, while at the same time sharpening awareness of contrasting elements of legal technique. The contrast upon which attention will be focussed appears to have been of great importance historically, yet perhaps to have been obscured in recent debates. 1. CONTRASTING CASES: A PREANALYTICAL SUGGESTION Successful pursuit of the first appointed aim requires the identification of some legal topic in which different legal systems in broadly similar settings provide contrasting solutions to substantially the same prob- * The ideas here stated first took shape at a W. G. Hart Workshop in the Institute for Advanced Legal Studies in London in July 1987 organised by Donald Harris, then became a paper for the Yale Law School's jurisprudence seminar organised by Owen Fiss and Jules Coleman (March 1988), continued under further revision to Risto Hilpinen's conference on rights in the University of Miami at Coral Gables, then became the analytical part of an 'Or 'Emet lecture at Osgoode Hall Law School, Ontario. I received much help from all those named, and from others besides, notably Rob Baldwin, Bruce Ackerman, Joseph Raz, Roberto Vernengo, Leslie Green and Wil Waluchow. Footnotes seemed to me unnecessary in the text, but further reference to the following would be of value to the interested reader: M. C. Meston Succession - Rights or Discretion (1987JurRev 1-11 at p. 7), and the first few sections of the (English) Inheritance (Provisionfor Family and Dependents) Act 1975; George C. Christie's An Essay on Discretion Duke LawJournal, 1986, 747-78; and to Ronald Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously (1978) pp. 31-2. Also David Hume, Essays, Moral Political and Literary. Law and Philosophy 8: 23-36, 1989. ~) 1989 Kluwer Academic Publishers. Printed in the Netkerlands. 24 Nell MacCormick lem. A useful such topic is that of family provision in the law of succession. The question is: if a person dies survived by children and a spouse, does the law entitle these survivors to any share in the deceased's estate, or is it entirely for the deceased to decide what testamentary provisions to make, or is there some intermediate possi- bility (for simplicity, the case of intestate succession is ignored here)? Three jurisdictions might give very different answers, as in fact do Scotland, England and Connecticut (which I understand to resemble in this most of the states of the U.S.A. except Louisiana, where, as in Scotland, civilian principles prevail). In Scots law, surviving children enjoy what are known in the standard speech of Scots lawyers as "legal rights" over one-third of the deceased's moveable estate and the surviving spouse has rights over a further third; only the balance, the "dead's part", is subject to freedom of testation. In English Law the provisions of any valid will left by the deceased govern the distribution of the whole estate; but a spouse or child or other dependant or family member may apply to the High Court with the complaint that the deceased's will does not make reasonable provision for him/her. The court, if satisfied by the applicant that reasonable provision has not been made, may make an order such as will secure what it deems reasonable provision, taking account of an extensive list of statutory factors bearing on the question. In Connecticut no such arrangements of any sort exist in favour of children; they may be wholly disinherited, without any recourse to any judicial remedy; but the surviving spouse has rights which pro tanto defeat the will. As was mentioned, it is a long established legal usage in Scotland to refer by the term "legal rights" to the entitlements of a deceased's children to their shares of the moveable estate. The precision and firmness of the provision in favour of children makes such a usage unsurprising. For any one of n children, that person has a right to one n th of one-third of the free moveable estate, after payment of all prior charges against the estate - i.e., to a 1/3n share thereof. This is a strong entitlement in that it is immune from divesting by the testator or anyone else, and is not dependent on the discretion of any judge or court. A law which allots a fixed share of a determinate or deter- ruinable fund to be paid to each member of a certain class with no possibility of change by anyone else's choice, does seem, at least by the Discretion and Rights 25 test of my linguistic intuition, obviously to give each member of the class a "right" to that share. This could well be taken to be a paradigm case of"having a right". The English statute, by contrast, uses what might be considered an equally paradigmatic case of the technique of judicial discretion in direct preference to that of a conferral of rights. The deceased person's children have not a right but a privilege and power to apply to the court. The court has a duty, upon receiving such an application, to satisfy itself whether or not, having regard to the statutory indicators (set out in section 3 of the Act), "reasonable provision" has or has not been made for the applicant; if the court is satisfied that reasonable provision has not been made, then it has power to make such award as it deems sufficient to make good the want of reasonable provision. This doubtless presupposes some idea that the children or dependents of a deceased person may, in given cases, have some form of moral entitlement to some provision from the deceased's estate. The presup- position is there may be something which it would have been morally right and reasonable for people to have received by the will of the deceased. But the legal remedy devised by English law for correcting a breach of such entitlement, or for bringing about the morally right and reasonable outcome, is a discretionary one. No specific legal right is contrived to match or protect the moral entitlement or even "moral right" in the background; the technique used here is rather that of a discretionary power granted to a judge whereby, if satisfied by a relevant application, he can confer a right such as meets the needs of the case; but the law does not from the start grant any right to persons in general to shares in the estates of their parents. By final contrast, the Connecticut provisions, though they give spouses rights, give children nothing, and in neither case give the court any discretion in anyone's favour or disfavour. It is perhaps a question whether we should then say that there is a legal discretion vested in every owner of property to leave or not leave property to his or her children (if any). I'm inclined not to say so. Morally speaking, it is in a person's discretion to will or not will property to a child - but in law, this is simply an unfettered legal power of testamentary dis- position, not a discretion at all; for nothing is made to be dependent upon the quality of judgement exercised by the testator. Issues of sanity apart, the law raises no question as to the rationality or pro- 26 Neil MacCormick priety of the judgement that led the testator to disinherit the family; testators can make their decisions as arbitrarily as you please, and yet these decisions will be sufficient to be legally dispositive provided only that they have been unequivocally made. That the three cases chosen stand in sharp mutual contrast is surely indubitable; nor does it seem too far out to classify the cases respec- tively as a case of rights, a case of discretion, and a case of no right and no discretion (I do not follow Hohfeld into a hyphenation of the negatives). The contrast can perhaps usefully be pointed up this way: the Scots law ascribes to the deceased's child a certain benefit that the child shall have at law regardless of anyone's opinion as to whether or not that is what any particular child ought to have. Therefore, if any child should be denied this and make complaint over it, the duty of officials is to secure it for her or him. The English law does not ascribe to the child anything to be held or enjoyed without regard to a prior judgement of what that particular child ought to have. Only on the basis of an official's judgement of what this specific person ought to have been given by the deceased is the child legally entitled to anything, and then the entitlement is to a judgement-dependent share, that which is deemed "reasonable". The Connecticut law ascribes no compulsory share to the child, nor does it provide any remedy or entitlement contingently on anyone's judgement of what a given child ought to be or have been given. The absence of right or remedy here is judgement-independent, just as their presence in Scots law is judge- ment-independent. The first questions posed by this paper are, then, whether the contrast is clearly and intelligibly drawn; and whether there is any- thing to be said for the preanalytical opinion here stated according to which the three are paradigm cases respectively of right, discretion, and no right, where discretion is the contradictory of right, and no right its contrary.
Recommended publications
  • Robert P Merges What Kind of Rights Are Intellectual Property Rights?
    Robert P Merges What Kind of Rights Are Intellectual Property Rights? Forthcoming in Rochelle C Dreyfuss & Justine Pila (eds), The Oxford Handbook of Intellectual Property Law © RP Merges 2017 Table of Contents 1. Intellectual Property as a Right 1.1 Intellectual Property Rights Are Property Rights 1.2 The Basic Features of Intellectual Property as Property 1.2.1 The Right to Control Uses 1.2.2 The Right to Transfer 1.2.3 The Special Case of Waiver 1.3 Limitations on Intellectual Property Rights 2. What Kind of Rights? Hohfeld and Intellectual Property 2.1 Claim Right/Duty 2.2 Privilege/No Claim 2.3 Power/Liability 2.4 Immunity/Disability 2.5 Hohfeld: Conclusion 3. Obstacles to Conceiving Intellectual Property as Property 3.1 Intellectual Property Acquisition and Misunderstandings About What it Means to be a Right 3.2 What, No Automatic Injunction? That’s Not Property! 3.3 Why Intellectual Property Rights Are Not ‘Regulation’ 3.3.2 The Second Sense of ‘Regulation’ 3.3.3 Freedom and Permission 3.3.4 Freedoms in Historical Perspective 3.4 Intellectual Property Rights as Property Rights: Summing Up 4. Problems With Conceiving Intellectual Property as Property 4.1 Group Ownership 4.2 Intellectual Property As Constitutional Property: The Takings Problem 5. Conclusion 1. Intellectual Property Rights as Rights Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=2959073 The phrase is common enough that it rolls off the tongue: intellectual property rights. It even has a well-known acronym, ‘IPRs.’1 But are they really rights? And if so, what kind of rights? Most importantly, what difference does it make that they are rights – what practical import does this carry? These are the questions I take up here.
    [Show full text]
  • The Concept of Law Revisited
    Michigan Law Review Volume 94 Issue 6 1996 The Concept of Law Revisited Leslie Green Osgoode Hall Law School, York University Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.law.umich.edu/mlr Part of the Public Law and Legal Theory Commons Recommended Citation Leslie Green, The Concept of Law Revisited, 94 MICH. L. REV. 1687 (1996). Available at: https://repository.law.umich.edu/mlr/vol94/iss6/15 This Review is brought to you for free and open access by the Michigan Law Review at University of Michigan Law School Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Michigan Law Review by an authorized editor of University of Michigan Law School Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. IBE CONCEPT OF LAW REVISITED Leslie Green* THE CONCEPT OF LAW. Second Edition. By H.L.A. Hart. With a Postscript edited by Penelope A. Bulloch and Joseph Raz. Oxford: Clarendon Press. 1994. Pp. xii, 315. $26. Law is a social construction. It is a historically contingent fea­ ture of certain societies, one whose emergence is signaled by the rise of a systematic form of social control and elite domination. In one way it supersedes custom, in another it rests on it, for law is a system of primary social rules that direct and appraise behavior, together with secondary social rules that identify, change, and en­ force the primary rules. Law may be beneficial, but only in some contexts and always at a price, at the risk of grave injustice; our appropriate attitude to it is therefore one of caution rather than celebration.
    [Show full text]
  • On Neil Maccormick's ‘Universalisable Particular Thesis’ Jingjing Wu
    Document generated on 09/25/2021 10:28 p.m. Informal Logic Justifying Particular Reasoning in a Legal Context On Neil MacCormick's ‘Universalisable Particular Thesis’ Jingjing Wu Volume 40, Number 3, 2020 Article abstract Particular reasoning is arguably the most common type of legal reasoning. Neil URI: https://id.erudit.org/iderudit/1071501ar MacCormick proposed that, in a legal context, justifiable particular reasoning DOI: https://doi.org/10.22329/il.v40i30.5994 has to be universalizable. This paper aims to: (1) investigate MacCormick’s thesis; (2) explain how a particular can ever be universal by drawing See table of contents inspiration from Scott Brewer’s formula on reasoning by analogy; (3) further comprehend MacCormick’s thesis by considering some of the arguments advanced by its opponents; (4) use the ‘pilot-judgement procedure’ developed Publisher(s) by the European Court of Human Rights as an example to illustrate the relevance of the universalizable particular thesis in today’s legal practices. Informal Logic ISSN 0824-2577 (print) 2293-734X (digital) Explore this journal Cite this article Wu, J. (2020). Justifying Particular Reasoning in a Legal Context: On Neil MacCormick's ‘Universalisable Particular Thesis’. Informal Logic, 40(3), 423–441. https://doi.org/10.22329/il.v40i30.5994 Copyright (c), 2020 Jingjing Wu This document is protected by copyright law. Use of the services of Érudit (including reproduction) is subject to its terms and conditions, which can be viewed online. https://apropos.erudit.org/en/users/policy-on-use/ This article is disseminated and preserved by Érudit. Érudit is a non-profit inter-university consortium of the Université de Montréal, Université Laval, and the Université du Québec à Montréal.
    [Show full text]
  • A Moralistic Case for A-Moralistic Law
    Valparaiso University Law Review Volume 20 Number 1 Fall 1985 pp.1-41 Fall 1985 A Moralistic Case for A-Moralistic Law Neil MacCormick Follow this and additional works at: https://scholar.valpo.edu/vulr Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Neil MacCormick, A Moralistic Case for A-Moralistic Law, 20 Val. U. L. Rev. 1 (1985). Available at: https://scholar.valpo.edu/vulr/vol20/iss1/1 This Lecture is brought to you for free and open access by the Valparaiso University Law School at ValpoScholar. It has been accepted for inclusion in Valparaiso University Law Review by an authorized administrator of ValpoScholar. For more information, please contact a ValpoScholar staff member at [email protected]. MacCormick: A Moralistic Case for A-Moralistic Law ValparaisoUniversity Law Review Volume 20 Fall 1985 Number 1 A MORALISTIC CASE FOR A-MORALISTIC LAW? NEIL MACCORMICK* Two LECTURES ON LAW AND THE ENFORCEMENT OF MORALS The essays presented here were first delivered as the Seegers Lectures at the Valparaiso University School of Law on March 26th and 27th, 1985. Edward A. Seegers has been a generous benefactor of the School, and it is an honor to be invited to present lectures in honor of such a friend of learning; all the more so in that the 1985 lectures in the series followed those of Professors Harold Berman and Tom Shaffer, and are to precede lectures by Professor Eugene V. Rostow, of whom I once had the good fortune to be a junior colleague when he was Eastman Professor at Balliol College, Oxford, and who is himself author of a seminal article' in the field I address here.
    [Show full text]
  • The Many Conceptions of a Legal System
    Edinburgh Research Explorer The Many Conceptions of a Legal System Citation for published version: Maher, G 2012, The Many Conceptions of a Legal System. in N Walker (ed.), MacCormick's Scotland . Edinburgh Studies in Law, Edinburgh University Press. Link: Link to publication record in Edinburgh Research Explorer Document Version: Peer reviewed version Published In: MacCormick's Scotland Publisher Rights Statement: © Maher, G. (2012). The Many Conceptions of a Legal System. In N. Walker (Ed.), Maccormick's Scotland . (Edinburgh Studies in Law). Edinburgh University Press. General rights Copyright for the publications made accessible via the Edinburgh Research Explorer is retained by the author(s) and / or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing these publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. Take down policy The University of Edinburgh has made every reasonable effort to ensure that Edinburgh Research Explorer content complies with UK legislation. If you believe that the public display of this file breaches copyright please contact [email protected] providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim. Download date: 25. Sep. 2021 The Many Conceptions of a Legal System ∗ Gerry Maher Joseph Raz once wrote a book called The Concept of a Legal System, a work intended as an introduction to a general theory of legal system, and as seeking to elucidate the concept of a legal system.1 However, it is not at all obvious that there is such a thing as the concept of legal system. Certainly, in legal discourse the term 'legal system' is used in a variety of contrasting ways.
    [Show full text]
  • Neil Maccormick's Legal Positivism Vittorio Villa
    1 Neil MacCormick’s Legal Positivism Vittorio Villa In this paper I will dwell on one of the most important points in MacCormick’s thought: his conception of legal positivism. The paper will develop in the following way. In the next section I will present my conceptual definition of legal positivism. In the second section, in the light of the proposed definition, I will try to reconstruct, in its various phases, the conception of legal positivism advanced by MacCormick. In the final part of the paper I will develop some critical observations on MacCormick’s thought. 1. A conceptual definition of legal positivism In proposing a conceptual definition of legal positivism, I follow the ‘concept/conceptions’ scheme (used, for instance, by Dworkin 1986, 70-71), in a very peculiar version. This scheme is particularly appropriate in cases in which we are dealing with essentially contested notions (Gallie 1955-56, 167- 198), that is to say, with notions structurally open to divergent interpretations, i.e., conflicting attributions of meaning. The word ‘concept’ is used here with reference to the most consolidated part, to the so-called solid area (Jori 1985, 277) of a determined notion of common or scientific language. Naturally no theory, be it scientific or philosophical, can stop at the threshold of the concept, which only represents the shared starting point, the assumptions that are commonly relied on. Conceptions, precisely, represent the first stage that knowledge goes through as soon as it breaks away from the solid ground of what is ‘deemed certain, to move to the much more slippery terrain of what can be the object of falsifiable conjectures that always run the risk of being confuted.
    [Show full text]
  • Legal Judgment and Moral Reservation Jeremy Waldron1
    For MacCormick conference: Practical Reason panel EUI, May 2010 Legal Judgment and Moral Reservation Jeremy Waldron1 1. Neil MacCormick on Moral Judgment In the fourth book of a quartet on “Law, State and Moral Reasoning”—a book entitled Practical Reason in Law and Morality2—Neil MacCormick considered the interplay of moral opinions and legal judgments. Much of that consideration was focused on an inquiry into the nature of moral reasoning, in the company of philosophers like Adam Smith and Immanuel Kant. “What is moral judgment like?” they asked and MacCormick echoed the question. What is moral judgment like? Is it, as Kant thought, like legislation (for example, legislation for the kingdom of ends)?3 No, MacCormick argues, it is more like common law judgment, working from and elaborating already given principles. “Nobody comes to reflection about right and wrong in the context of practical deliberation save in the context of a learned and inherited practical code” (19-20). True there is “no single authoritative rule-book,”4 which we interpret and apply. But there isn’t any such canonical rule-book in common law either: judges elaborate and apply norms of various sorts that are kind-of given but also kind-of open to further development in the hands of the very people who are applying them, particularly as new and challenging cases come up; and that, MacCormick reckons, is a better analogy to moral reasoning than the idea that we confront all situations with either a quasi- legislative capacity or with something like the sort of canonical rule-book that an umpire has in his back pocket in a football match or in cricket.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy of Law, Reading Course Fall 2014
    Princeton University Department of Politics POL 5** – Philosophy of Law, Reading Course Fall 2014 Keith E. Whittington 240 Corwin Hall, 258-3453 [email protected] An introduction to general jurisprudence and philosophy of law. Requirements: 5 short papers Items marked with * are also on the public law field reading list. Schedule: 1. Starting Points Required: *John Austin, The Province of Jurisprudence Determined, analysis and lectures I-II *Oliver Wendell Holmes, “The Path of the Law,” Harvard Law Review (1897) *Karl Llewellyn, “A Realistic Jurisprudence – The Next Step,” Columbia Law Review (1930) Suggested: *Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologica, I-II Questions 90-97 *Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan, ch. 14, 17-18, 21, 26 *John Locke, The Second Treatise of Government, ch. 8-13 William Blackston, Commentaries on the Laws of Engalnd Jeremy Bentham, Of Laws in General *Benjamin Cardozo, The Nature of the Judicial Process *Roberto Unger, The Critical Legal Studies Movement *Frederick Schauer, Playing by the Rules *Friedrich Hayek, The Constitution of Liberty, ch. 10 Oliver Wendell Holmes, The Common Law Hugo Grotius, On the Law of War and Peace Hans Kelsen, The Pure Theory of Law Karl Llewellyn, The Bramble Bush Karl Llewellyn, “Remarks on the Theory of Appellate Decision” Vanderbilt Law Review (1950) Karl Llewelllyn, “Some Realism about Realism,” Harvard Law Review (1931) Max Radin, “The Theory of Judicial Decision” American Bar Association Journal (1925) Max Radin, “Statutory Interpretation,” Harvard Law Review (1930) Jerome Frank, Law and
    [Show full text]
  • Positivism and Legality: Hart's Equivocal Response To
    \\server05\productn\N\NYU\83-4\NYU407.txt unknown Seq: 1 25-SEP-08 12:34 POSITIVISM AND LEGALITY: HART’S EQUIVOCAL RESPONSE TO FULLER JEREMY WALDRON* Lon Fuller, in his response to H.L.A. Hart’s 1958 Holmes Lecture and elsewhere, argued that principles of legality—formal principles requiring, for example, that laws be clear, general, and prospective—constitute the “internal morality of law.” This Article contends that Hart never offered a clear response. Fuller’s claim sup- poses that observance of the principles of legality is both fundamental to law and inherently moral. In different writings, Hart seems variously to affirm and to deny that legality is a necessary criterion for the existence of law. Likewise, he sometimes suggests and elsewhere scorns the idea that legality has moral significance. This Article proposes that Hart’s apparent inconsistency might actually reflect the com- plexity of the terms. Some degree of legality might be a prerequisite of law, while some failures of legality might not condemn it. Principles of legality might have contingent rather than inherent moral value, might have moral value that is sever- able from their legal value, or might have both positive and negative moral effect. The Article argues, furthermore, that even the conclusion Hart strains to avoid— that legality inevitably links morality and law—is compatible with Hart’s positivism and opens a promising field for positivist jurisprudence. INTRODUCTION One of the most telling observations that Lon Fuller made in his 1958 response to H.L.A. Hart’s Holmes Lecture 1 concerned Hart’s apparently blinkered view of the evils of rule by Hitler and the Nazi party in Germany from 1933 to 1945.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Road to Reconceiving Rights for Children: a Postfeminist Analysis of the Capacity Principle
    DePaul Law Review Volume 42 Issue 3 Spring 1993 Article 3 On the Road to Reconceiving Rights for Children: A Postfeminist Analysis of the Capacity Principle Katherine Hunt Federle Follow this and additional works at: https://via.library.depaul.edu/law-review Recommended Citation Katherine H. Federle, On the Road to Reconceiving Rights for Children: A Postfeminist Analysis of the Capacity Principle , 42 DePaul L. Rev. 983 (1993) Available at: https://via.library.depaul.edu/law-review/vol42/iss3/3 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the College of Law at Via Sapientiae. It has been accepted for inclusion in DePaul Law Review by an authorized editor of Via Sapientiae. For more information, please contact [email protected]. ON THE ROAD TO RECONCEIVING RIGHTS FOR CHILDREN: A POSTFEMINIST ANALYSIS OF THE CAPACITY PRINCIPLE Katherine Hunt Federle* We now breathlessly await the analog to sociology's favorite egg-chicken story (that is, that a chicken is an egg's way of producing another egg): namely, that an adult is a child's way of producing another child.' INTRODUCTION I like this quotation. It may seem whimsical to some, but I think that it provides us with a perspective so obvious and yet so startling that we are forced to reexamine some of our assumptions about our children and their role in society, assumptions that are so deeply embedded they have channeled our dialogue and forced us down cir- cular paths of analysis. Within the children's rights debate, these assumptions collapse around one central, organizing principle: ca- pacity.
    [Show full text]
  • The Relevance of Coherence
    Columbia Law School Scholarship Archive Faculty Scholarship Faculty Publications 1992 The Relevance of Coherence Joseph Raz Columbia Law School, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.columbia.edu/faculty_scholarship Part of the Law and Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Joseph Raz, The Relevance of Coherence, 72 B. U. L. REV. 273 (1992). Available at: https://scholarship.law.columbia.edu/faculty_scholarship/953 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Faculty Publications at Scholarship Archive. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Scholarship by an authorized administrator of Scholarship Archive. For more information, please contact [email protected]. VOLUME 72 NUMBER 2 MARCH 1992 BOSTON UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW THE RELEVANCE OF COHERENCEt JOSEPH RAZ* Coherence is in vogue. Coherence accounts of truth and of knowledge have been in contention for many years. Coherence explanations of morality and of law are a newer breed. I suspect that like so much else in practical philosophy' today they owe much of their popularity to John Rawls. His writings on reflective equilibrium,2 while designed as part of a philosophical strategy which suspends inquiry into the fundamental questions of moral philosophy, had the opposite effect. They inspired much constructive reflec- tion about these questions, largely veering toward coherence as the right interpretation both of reflective equilibrium and of moral philosophy. In legal philosophy, Ronald Dworkin's work contributed to an interest in coherence accounts of law and of judicial reasoning.3 t @ 1992 Joseph Raz. * Professor of the Philosophy of Law, Oxford University, and Fellow of Balliol College, Oxford.
    [Show full text]
  • The Question to Be Faced Is One of Fact: H.L.A. Hart's Legal Theory
    Canadian Journal of Law & Jurisprudence XXXIV No.2 August 2021, 283-295 283 © The Author(s), 2021. This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-ShareAlike licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-sa/), which permits non-commercial re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the same Creative Commons licence is included and the original work is properly cited. The written permission of Cambridge University Press must be obtained for commercial re-use. doi: 10.1017/cjlj.2021.11 The Question To Be Faced Is One of Fact H.L.A. Hart’s Legal Theory Through His View of International Law Giovanni Bisogni H.L.A. Hart says that The Concept of Law is focused on municipal or domestic law because that is the “central case”1 for the usage of the word ‘law.’ At the beginning of thebookhestatesthat“at various points in this book the reader will find discussions of the borderline cases where legal theorists have felt doubts about the application of the expression ‘law’ or ‘legal system,’ but the suggested resolution of these doubts, which he will also find here, is only a secondary concern of the book.”2 Yet among those borderline cases there is one that is rather intriguing, since Hart closely discusses a particular instance of them: it is international law, to which he devotes an entire chap- ter—the final one—of The Concept of Law. My goal in this article is therefore to make clear why the ‘resolution’ of the borderline case of international law is not entirely ‘secondary’ to Hart’s overall project in TheConceptofLawand, in so doing, to show that Chapter X is not as unhappy as many think it is.
    [Show full text]