Not Crying “Peace” the Theological Politics of Herbert Mccabe
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
This is a repository copy of Not Crying “Peace” The Theological Politics of Herbert McCabe. White Rose Research Online URL for this paper: http://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/133232/ Version: Accepted Version Article: Hewitt, S orcid.org/0000-0003-2720-4428 (2018) Not Crying “Peace” The Theological Politics of Herbert McCabe. New Blackfriars, 99 (1084). pp. 740-755. ISSN 0028-4289 https://doi.org/10.1111/nbfr.12401 © 2018 Provincial Council of the English Province of the Order of Preachers. This is the peer reviewed version of the following article: Hewitt, S. (2018), Not Crying “Peace” The Theological Politics of Herbert McCabe. New Blackfriars, 99: 740-755, which has been published in final form at https://doi.org/10.1111/nbfr.12401. This article may be used for non-commercial purposes in accordance with Wiley Terms and Conditions for Self-Archiving. Uploaded in accordance with the publisher's self-archiving policy. Reuse Items deposited in White Rose Research Online are protected by copyright, with all rights reserved unless indicated otherwise. They may be downloaded and/or printed for private study, or other acts as permitted by national copyright laws. The publisher or other rights holders may allow further reproduction and re-use of the full text version. This is indicated by the licence information on the White Rose Research Online record for the item. Takedown If you consider content in White Rose Research Online to be in breach of UK law, please notify us by emailing [email protected] including the URL of the record and the reason for the withdrawal request. [email protected] https://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/ Not crying “peace” The theological politics of Herbert McCabe∗ Simon Hewitt University of Leeds Author accepted draft. Final version in New Blackfriars. Herbert McCabe was, by widespread acclaim, one of the greatest Catholic thinkers in the English speaking world during the final quarter of the last cen- tury. He was also deeply committed to radical left-wing politics. What is the relationship between these two facts? There is a temptation, especially in a climate not favourable to the marriage of radical politics and Christianity, to suggest that they are at best accidentally related. Thus after McCabe’s death one got the impression that he was for many a brilliant theologian and philoso- pher, with numerous important things to say about topics such as creation and the eucharist, who just happened to have rather eccentric political opinions. These, ran the implication, were best passed over in silence.1 This is a mistake. Not only are McCabe’s political ideas interesting in their own right, and an important corrective to current trends in both theology and analytic philosophy, but at crucial points his understanding of central theologi- cal topics (creation, God, idolatry) is emeshed with his politics, such that any attempt to separate the two is bound to distort McCabe’s intentions in writing. In this article, I will lay out what I take to be the key themes in McCabe’s politics before arguing that, in contrast to significant strands in present day political theology, he had a keen sense of the respective roles of faith and reason in guiding political action. This allowed him to commit himself to a politics which was more radical than much of what has followed him, whilst having a clear sense of how Christian faith ought to be allowed to condition political engagement. The article concludes by drawing out lessons from McCabe for thinking about faith and politics. Not least of these is that we ought to avoid the lure, often articulated in terms of the ‘unifying’ role of the Church, to es- chew conflict. At the moment there is a lot of pressure to echo those condemned by the prophet Jeremiah, proclaiming peace where there is no peace.2 McCabe cautions us against this constantly, and for theologically interesting reasons. ∗Thanks to Peter Hunter OP, Rachel Muers, and Tasia Scrutton for discussion of themes covered here. 1Important exceptions here are Denys Turner’s lecture [32], with which I disagree at points (as will become apparent), but which is essential reading, and Terry Eagleton’s enduring interest in McCabe – see especially [4], [3], and [5] for works which show his influence. 2‘They have treated the wound of my people carelessly, saying, “Peace, peace,” when there is no peace.’ Jeremiah 6:14, NRSV. See below for the same theme in Ezekiel. 1 1 God, the gods and oppression Above all else, McCabe was a theologian in the thomist tradition, understanding the purpose of his discipline (whether pursued as a branch of philosophy, or as taking its lead from biblical revelation) as being to speak of God (STh Ia, Q1, a.7). Schooled in analytic philosophy, however, and in particular in the work of Wittgenstein, he was attentive to questions about the limits of sense and was acutely aware that these pressed themselves with particularly urgency around theological language. His particular contribution to the recasting of thomism in the light of analytic philosophy,3 was the description of a way-in to talk of God which made comprehensible the severe limits of our capacity to speak of God. Since McCabe considered the observation of these limits to be of supreme im- portance for politics, it is worth outlining here McCabe’s approach to God-talk. ‘For a large class of cases of employment of the word ‘meaning’ – though not for all - this word can be explained in this way: the meaning of a word is its use in the language’ [34, 43]; thus Wittgenstein in the Philosophical Investigations. In a late 20th century context where the meaningfulness of the word ‘God’ had been the object of doubt,4 McCabe undertook to demonstrate that it had an intelligible use, and therefore a meaning.5 Moreover, his favoured way of do- ing this gives us reason to believe that God exists. In this way, he refashions Thomas’ natural theology for the age of linguistic philosophy. How is the word ‘God’ used?6 For McCabe, in line with the thomist instinct that we talk about God through talking about God’s creatures, its paradigmatic use is in supplying an answer to a question: ‘why is there something rather than nothing at all?’ [19, 5]. So, assuming of course that this question is in good order,7 we are entitled to say that God exists just in case there is something rather than nothing at all, which of course there is. In spite of an appearance of theological bravado, McCabe’s claim here is modest, for God is an answer to the question of existence only in a certain sense. The word ‘God’ has a use in our language, namely designating whatever it is which is the reason why there is something rather than nothing at all. The nature of whatever that may be is hidden from us. As McCabe writes, ‘By ‘creation’ we mean the dependence of all that is, in so far as it is. We do not know what it is that it depends on, we do not know the nature of God’ [20, 10]. Here he is entirely in line with Aquinas’ insistence that we cannot know what God is but only what he is not (STh Ia pr. Q3).8 Behind this apophaticism lies a realisation that in order to adequately an- 3On which, see [27] and [8]. McCabe is often counted part of the loose movement known as ‘grammatical thomism’; see [25] on this, although the details of Mulhall’s exegesis of McCabe are criticised in []. 4For an overview, see [6]. 5Theology, for McCabe, is concerned with ‘trying to stop us talking nonsense’ [16, 215] 6For more details on McCabe’s approach to the word ‘God’ see my [] 7Doubt about this was voiced by Russell in debate with Coppleston [28], which McCabe references. 8In emphasising Aquinas’ apophaticism McCabe, along with other thinkers in the ‘gram- matical thomist’ tradition, such as Burrell and Davies, is an important corrective to the downplaying of its importance by prominent analytic readers of Aquinas, e.g. [30]. 2 swer the question of existence, anything picked out by the word ‘God’ would have to lie beyond the ordinary reach of our language, devised as it is for use within the created order. God ‘is always dressed verbally in second-hand clothes that don’t fit him very well’. In particular, the conditions under which we can assign everyday objects to categories or assert significantly about their internal structure, are never satisfied in the case of God. Moreover inferences that would be routine from claims about creatures are blocked in the case of God, precisely because God is the reason creatures exist over and against nothing: If God is whatever answers our question, how come everything? then evidently he is not to be included amongst everything. God cannot be a thing, an existent among others. It is not possible that God and the universe should add up to make two. Again, if we are to speak of God as causing the existence of everything, it is clear that we must not mean that he makes the universe out of anything. Whatever creation means it is not a process of making. [19, 6] Now: use the word ‘world’ to mean the created order, which we perceive with our senses and grasp with our minds, and which we use our language to navigate our way about.9 God is not an item in the world. This fact is taken by McCabe to be of crucial political importance. The Creator is not an item in the creation: God cannot be contained within our conceptual frameworks and so, if we are to speak of him faithfully, cannot be manipulated with ideological purpose, fitted neatly into an account of the world in order to serve the interests of dominant interests.