Jefferson's Medialist View of History

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Jefferson's Medialist View of History American Studies in Scandinavia, 47:1 (2015), pp. 3-21. Published by the Nordic Association for American Studies (NAAS). Differences of Circumstance, Differences of Fact: Jefferson’s Medialist View of History M. Andrew Holowchak University of the Incarnate Word, Texas Abstract: It is often assumed that Jefferson—acquainted with the writings of Scottish thinkers such as Adam Ferguson, Anne Robert Jacques Turgot, Lord Kames, Adam Smith, and John Millar—was a stadialist of some persuasion, as several of his writ- ings are at least consistent with stadialism. If so, was he a cyclicalist, committed to a society having a life-cycle, or a linearist, committed to the possibility of continued convergence toward some ideal of perfection? An important letter to William Ludlow and several writings where Jefferson writes of human progress as imprescriptible suggest linear stadialism. Numerous other writings, point to urbanization as a stage of social decay, and suggest cyclicalism. The correct answer, I argue, is that Jefferson was neither a linearist nor a cyclicalist, but a medialist. He viewed movement toward increased urbanization as symptomatic of social decline, but always believed any so- ciety, by rooting itself in an agrestic manner—a normative mean between the excesses of subsistence living and urbanization—could avert decline and even work toward continued advance. Key Words: Jefferson, progress, cyclical stadialism, lineal stadialism, medial stadialism A “philosophic observer” on a trip from the Rocky-Mountain west to the eastern sea-coast, Jefferson writes in a letter to William Ludlow (6 Sept. 1824), would see a temporal survey of “the progress of man from the in- fancy of creation to the present day.” Seeing lawless savages in the West, 4 American Studies in Scandinavia, 47:1 he would come to see frontiersmen, farmers, and finally seaport citizens.1 The letter to Ludlow betrays a purchase of stadialism—the notion that societies pass through fairly well-defined stages. Stadialism was popular in the late eighteenth century and early nineteenth century and can be found in some measure in the writings of coetaneous Scottish thinkers. Cyclical stadialists, on analogy with living organisms, assume that societies have a life cycle—from birth and growth to decline and death. Linear stadialists, in contrast, merely assume the possibility of continual convergence toward an ideal of perfection. It is often assumed that Jefferson, acquainted with the writings of each Scottish thinker, was a stadialist of some persuasion, as several of his writ- ings are at least consistent with stadialism. If so, was he a cyclicalist or a linearist? The letter to Ludlow and several writings where Jefferson writes of human progress as imprescriptible suggest linear stadialism. Numerous other writings, point to urbanization as a stage of social decay, and suggest cyclicalism. Yet Jefferson, I argue, was neither a linearist nor a cyclicalist, but a medialist. He viewed movement toward increased urbanization as symptomatic of social decline, but always believed any society, by rooting itself in an agrestic manner—a normative mean between the excesses of subsistence living and urbanization—could avert decline and even work toward continued improvement. Stadialism and Conjectural History The view Jefferson expresses in his letter to Ludlow is in keeping with the tenor of eighteenth-century Scottish-Enlightenment thinking, characterized by the push for agricultural improvement, the creation of public spaces for scientific societies and clubs, and in general, the belief in the advance of all sciences, even politics, and religion. The unswerving belief in the ad- vance of scientific institutions gave birth to conjectural history—a “back- projection of documented social trends combined with the comparative eth- nography of primitive societies.”2 Conjectural history enabled historians to draw inferences about the past beyond the safe limits of “reliable historical 1 I would like to thank the journal’s two reviewers, Csaba Lévai and Aki Kalliomäki for aidful comments concerning a prior draft of this paper. 2 Colin Kidd, “Subscription, the Scottish Enlightenment and the Moderate Interpretation of History,” The Journal of Ecclesiastical History, Vol. 55, No. 3, 2004, 507–8. DIFFERENCES OF Circumstance 5 evidence” in an effort to “explain” and serve present-day normative needs, which included foremost moral progress. Thus, history was not merely a descriptive discipline, whose aim was veridical narrative, it was also a nor- mative discipline, whose aim was moral improvement. In the main, the nor- mative aim of stadialists trumped the descriptive aim, and so they believed that theoretical economy that served a moral purpose in the writing of his- tory was preferable to trying to be true to the actual anfractuous course of nature. In that regard, veridicality was an ancillary concern. Conjectural history is characteristically linked with stadialism—the no- tion, in Jefferson’s day, that a state and its parts passed through stages, mostly, though not always, well defined. Stadialism, with roots in antiquity (e.g., Plato for whom every poleis had a life-cycle3), was birthed in Scot- land and held by Scottish and French thinkers4—e.g., Adam Smith,5 David Hume,6 Adam Ferguson,7 John Millar,8 Lord Kames,9 William Robertson,10 Claude-Adrien Helvétius,11 and Anne-Robert-Jacques Turgot12—in the 3 Plato’s argument is based in the imperfection of the material world, in which all things are generated and destroyed. Thus, even the best polis with the best constitution must decay (R., 546a). Plato, Republic, trans. G.M.A. Grube (Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, 1992). 4 “That stadialism arose in Scotland was not coincidental,” writes Neil Hargraves, “[as] 18th century Scotland was in many ways a museum of archaic social forms, from the ‘barbarous’ highlanders to the feudal remnants of the lowlands.” Neil Hargraves, “Enterprise, Adventure and Industry: The formation of ‘Commercial Char- acter’ in William Robertson’s History of America,” History of European Ideas, Vol. 29, 2003, 35. 5 Adam Smith, Lectures on Jurisprudence, ed. R.L. Meek, D.D. Rapheale, and P.G. Stein (Oxford University Press, 1990), LJ(A) I.26–35 and 19–30 and LJ(B) 149–51. 6 David Hume, “Origin of Government,” Essays: Moral, Political, and Literary, ed. Eugene F. Miller (India- napolis: Liberty Fund, 1987), 40, and “The British Government,” Essays: Moral, Political, and Literary, 51. 7 Ferguson, unlike his fellow Scots, was disinclined to view human progress as removal from the state of nature. “If we admit that man is susceptible of improvement, and has in himself a principle of progression, and a desire of perfection, it appears improper to say, that he has quitted the state of his nature, when he has begun to proceed; or that he finds a station for which he was not intended, while, like other animals, he only follows the disposition, and employs the powers that nature has given.” Adam Ferguson, An Essay on the History of Civil Society, fifth ed. (London, 1782), 13. 8 John Millar, The Origins of the Distinction of Ranks: Or, An Inquiry into the Circumstances which Give Riser to Influence and Authority, in the Different Members of Society, Fourth Edition (Edinburgh, 1806), 5–6. 9 Henry Home [Lord Kames], Sketches of the History of Man, vol. 3 (Edinburgh, [1774] 1813), 159–65 and 176, and The Gentleman Farmer, being an Attempt to Improve Agriculture by Subjecting It to the Test of Rational Principles, 4th edition (Edinburgh: 1798), xix–xx. 10 William Robertson, The History of the Discovery and Settlement of America (New York: Harper & Broth- ers, 1855), 131. 11 Claude Adrien Helvétius, Treatise on Man: His Intellectual Faculties and his Education, transl. W. Hooper, M. D., (London: Albion Press, 1810). 12 Anne-Robert-Jacques Turgot, A Philosophical Review of the Successive Advances of the Human Mind, in Turgot on Progress, Sociology and Economics, ed. R.L. Meek (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, [1750] 1973). 6 American Studies in Scandinavia, 47:1 modes sketched below, and by others, in more deviant forms.13 Writes Guy Reynolds: The Stadialist saw the progress of civilizations as a steady upward movement through a series of distinct stages—from early pastoralism through a society of trade toward the modern industrial order. … Intellectuals and writers built on late eighteenth-century philosophies of history to create detailed models of progress that informed the broader culture. From James Fenimore Cooper’s historical fictions to Thomas Cole’s series of paintings, The Course of Empire, nineteenth-century Americans envisaged distinctive representations of the relations between “civilization” and “savagism,” and they embed- ded their images or narrative within a theory of progress.14 There is no one-size-fits-all definition of “stadial history” that applies to all stadialists, and that is probably because stadialism was, faute de mieux, more of a methodological heuristic used by conjectural historians to link human barbarism to the modern man of the eighteenth century than a meth- od, aiming to replace traditional narrative approaches to history.15 It might have been more complementary to than frictional with traditional narrative approaches to history. The number of stages for stadialists was generally a matter of unobjec- tionable disagreement, although many—e.g., Smith and Ferguson—agreed on four stages (hunting, pasturage, agriculture, and commerce).16 Etiologi- cal conveniency, not etiological correctness, was often the chief desidera- tum.17 As Dugald Stewart wrote in a preface to Adam Smith’s The Theory of 13 Karen O’Brien, “Between Enlightenment and Stadial History: William Robertson on the History of Eu- rope”, Journal of Eighteenth-Century Studies, Vol. 16, No. 1, 1993, 53–54. 14 Guy Reynolds, Apostles of Modernity: American Writers in the Age of Development (Lincoln, NE: Univer- sity of Nebraska Press, 2008), 16. 15 H.M. Höpfl, “From Savage to Scotsman: Conjectural History in the Scottish Enlightenment,” Journal of British Studies, Vol.
Recommended publications
  • Writing the Global: the Scottish Enlightenment As Literary Practice
    Writing the Global: The Scottish Enlightenment as Literary Practice Yusuke Wakazawa PhD University of York English and Related Literature September 2018 2 Abstract This thesis presents the Scottish Enlightenment as a literary practice in which Scottish thinkers deploy diverse forms of writing---for example, philosophical treatise, essay, autobiography, letter, journal, and history---to shape their ideas and interact with readers. After the unsuccessful publication of A Treatise of Human Nature (1739-40), David Hume turns to write essays on moral philosophy, politics and commerce, and criticism. I argue that other representatives of the Scottish Enlightenment such as Adam Smith, Adam Ferguson, and William Robertson also display a comparable attention to the choice and use of literary forms. I read the works of the Scottish Enlightenment as texts of eighteenth-century literature rather than a context for that literature. Since I argue that literary culture is an essential component of the Scottish Enlightenment, I include James Boswell and Tobias Smollett as its members. In diverse literary forms, Scottish writers refer to geographical difference, and imagine the globe as heterogenous and interconnected. These writers do not treat geography as a distinctive field of inquiry. Instead, geographical reference is a feature of diverse scholarly genres. I suggest that literary experiments in the Scottish Enlightenment can be read as responding to the circulation of information, people, and things beyond Europe. Scottish writers are interested in the diversity of human beings, and pay attention to the process through which different groups of people in distant regions encounter each other and exchange their sentiments as well as products.
    [Show full text]
  • Utilitarianism in the Age of Enlightenment
    UTILITARIANISM IN THE AGE OF ENLIGHTENMENT This is the first book-length study of one of the most influential traditions in eighteenth-century Anglophone moral and political thought, ‘theological utilitarianism’. Niall O’Flaherty charts its devel- opment from its formulation by Anglican disciples of Locke in the 1730s to its culmination in William Paley’s work. Few works of moral and political thought had such a profound impact on political dis- course as Paley’s Principles of Moral and Political Philosophy (1785). His arguments were at the forefront of debates about the constitution, the judicial system, slavery and poverty. By placing Paley’s moral thought in the context of theological debate, this book establishes his genuine commitment to a worldly theology and to a programme of human advancement. It thus raises serious doubts about histories which treat the Enlightenment as an entirely secular enterprise, as well as those which see English thought as being markedly out of step with wider European intellectual developments. niall o’flaherty is a Lecturer in the History of European Political Thought at King’s College London. His research focuses on eighteenth- and nineteenth-century moral, political and religious thought in Britain. He has published articles on William Paley and Thomas Robert Malthus, and is currently writing a book entitled Malthus and the Discovery of Poverty. ideas in context Edited by David Armitage, Richard Bourke, Jennifer Pitts and John Robertson The books in this series will discuss the emergence of intellectual traditions and of related new disciplines. The procedures, aims and vocabularies that were generated will be set in the context of the alternatives available within the contemporary frameworks of ideas and institutions.
    [Show full text]
  • Progress According to David Hume and Adam Smith Ecem Okan
    Between history and analysis : progress according to David Hume and Adam Smith Ecem Okan To cite this version: Ecem Okan. Between history and analysis : progress according to David Hume and Adam Smith. Eco- nomics and Finance. Université Panthéon-Sorbonne - Paris I, 2018. English. NNT : 2018PA01E050. tel-03041539 HAL Id: tel-03041539 https://tel.archives-ouvertes.fr/tel-03041539 Submitted on 5 Dec 2020 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. Université Paris 1 Panthéon­Sorbonne École d’Économie de la Sorbonne PHARE ENTRE HISTOIRE ET ANALYSE : LE PROGRÈS SELON DAVID HUME ET ADAM SMITH / BETWEEN HISTORY AND ANALYSIS: PROGRESS ACCORDING TO DAVID HUME AND ADAM SMITH Thèse pour l’obtention du titre de Docteure en Sciences Économiques Présentée et soutenue publiquement le 4 décembre 2018 par Ecem Okan Sous la direction d’André Lapidus Professeur à l’Université Paris 1 Panthéon­Sorbonne COMPOSITION DU JURY : Daniel Diatkine, Professeur Émérite à l’Université d’Evry/ Paris­Saclay Laurent Jaffro, Professeur à l’Université Paris 1 Panthéon­Sorbonne André Lapidus, Professeur Émérite à l’Université Paris 1 Panthéon­Sorbonne (Directeur de recherche) Spencer Pack, Professeur au Connecticut College, États­Unis (Rapporteur) Nathalie Sigot, Professeure à l’Université Paris 1 Panthéon­Sorbonne Michel Zouboulakis, Professeur à l’Université de Thessalie, Grèce (Rapporteur) L’Université Paris 1 Panthéon­Sorbonne n’entend donner aucune approbation ni désapprobation aux opinions émises dans cette thèse ; ces opinions doivent être considérées comme propres à leur auteur.
    [Show full text]
  • The Conjectural History of Language in the Scottish Enlightenment
    The Conjectural History of Language in the Scottish Enlightenment By Christopher H. Badenoch Department of History Submitted in partid fulfilment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts Faculty of Graduate Studies The University of Western Ontario London, Ontario September, 1999 @ ~hristopher& Badenoch, 1999 National Library BiiliaWque nationale du Canada Acquisitions and Acquisitions et Bibliographic Services services bibliognphiques 395 Weflington Street 395. rue Wdingtm Otrawa ON KIA ON4 OtrawaON K1AONQ Canada Canada The author has granted a non- L'auteur a accorde me licence non exclusive licence allowing the exclusive permettant a la National Library of Canada to Bibliotheque nationale du Canada de reproduce, loan, distri'bute or sell reproduire, priiter, districbuer ou copies of this thesis in microform, vendre des copies de cette these sous paper or electronic formats. la forme de microfiche/iih, de reproduction sur papier ou sur format electronique. The author retains ownership of the L'auteur conserve la propriete du copyright in this thesis. Neither the droit d'auteur qui protege cette these. thesis nor substantial extracts from it Ni la these ni des extraits substantiels may be printed or otheMrise de celle-ci ne doivent &e imprimes reproduced without the author's ou autrement reproduits sans son permission. autorisation, ABSTRACT This thesis examines the secular conjectural histories of language offered by the men of the Scottish Enlightenment. The institutional nature of language led the Scots philosophers to
    [Show full text]
  • Bernard De Mandeville and the Shaping of Conjectural History In
    Frank Palmeri (University of Miami) Bernard de Mandeville and the Shaping of Conjectural History In the seventeenth century, Natural Law theorists of the origins of human society such as Thomas Hobbes and John Locke posited that at some unspecified point in the distant past, human beings emerged from a primitive condition and formed themselves into a society by means of a contract entered into among themselves. A century later, conjectural history had become a prominent and distinctive Enlightenment genre exemplified in works of Jean-Jacques Rousseau (Discourse Concerning Inequality), David Hume (Natural History of Religion), Adam Smith (Wealth of Nations, Book 4), and Adam Ferguson (Essay on the Origin of Civil Society). Tracing the origins of society back before the existence of documents and other evidence, conjectural history, unlike natural law theory, focuses on long historical development rather than a single founding moment of contract. Conjectural narratives presume that human actions often have unintended consequences, that humans make their history but without knowing in advance what course that history will take. The form adopts a naturalistic, non-providential explanation of early social forms that usually falls into stages. I will argue in this paper that Bernard de Mandeville first made the shift from Natural Law to conjectural history, bringing together the major elements of the new form in a single work, The Fable of the Bees. Mandeville revises and greatly expands his account of the origins of social institutions from Part 1 of the Fable of the Bees (1714), in the dialogues between Cleomenes and Horatio that constitute Part 2 of the Fable (1729).
    [Show full text]
  • Positivism, Natural Law and Conjectural History in Seventeenth- and Eighteenth-Century English Legal Thought
    Michael Lobban Theory in history: positivism, natural law and conjectural history in seventeenth- and eighteenth-century English legal thought Book section Original citation: Originally published in Del Mar, Maksymilian and Lobban, Michael, (eds.) Law in Theory and History: New Essays on a Neglected Dialogue. Hart Publishing, Oxford, UK. ISBN 9781849467995 © 2016 Hart Publishing This version available at: http://eprints.lse.ac.uk/69172/ Available in LSE Research Online: January 2017 LSE has developed LSE Research Online so that users may access research output of the School. Copyright © and Moral Rights for the papers on this site are retained by the individual authors and/or other copyright owners. Users may download and/or print one copy of any article(s) in LSE Research Online to facilitate their private study or for non-commercial research. You may not engage in further distribution of the material or use it for any profit-making activities or any commercial gain. You may freely distribute the URL (http://eprints.lse.ac.uk) of the LSE Research Online website. This document is the author’s submitted version of the book section. There may be differences between this version and the published version. You are advised to consult the publisher’s version if you wish to cite from it. 12 Theory in History: Positivism, Natural law and Conjectural History in Seventeenth- and Eighteenth- Century English Legal Thought Michael Lobban Contemporary jurisprudence can be very tribal. Rival schools compete with each other to show that they have the best answers to fundamental questions about the nature of law and legal reasoning.
    [Show full text]
  • What Is Ancient History?
    What is Ancient History? Ian Morris & Walter Scheidel Abstract: Every society has told stories about ancient times, but contemporary ancient history was the prod- uct of two main developments. The first was the invention of writing, which made scholarly study of the past possible, and the second was the explosion of knowledge about the world from the eighteenth century on- Downloaded from http://direct.mit.edu/daed/article-pdf/145/2/113/1830927/daed_a_00381.pdf by guest on 30 September 2021 ward. Europeans responded to this explosion by inventing two main versions of antiquity: the first, an evo- lutionary model, was global and went back to the origins of humanity; and the second, a classical model, treated Greece and Rome as turning points in world history. These two views of antiquity have competed for two hundred and fifty years, but in the twenty-first century, the evidence and methods available to -an cient historians are changing faster than at any other time since the debate began. We should therefore ex- pect the balance between the two theories to shift dramatically. We close by considering some possible areas of engagement. Ancient history is the study of beginnings, and is thus organized around two central questions: 1) how to define the subject matter whose beginning is be- ing studied; and 2) what that beginning means for the world that the studiers live in. Across the centu- ries, the answers ancient historians have offered to these questions have changed significantly, largely in response to new evidence and new methods. But now, in the twenty-first century, the evidence and IAN MORRIS is the Jean and Re­ methods available are changing faster than at any becca Willard Professor of Clas­ sics at Stanford University and a time since the eighteenth century, and we should Fellow of the Stanford Archaeol­ expect the answers ancient historians offer to do the ogy Center.
    [Show full text]
  • Adam Smith on the Early and Rude State of Society and the Age of Hunters Ecem Okan
    How did it all begin? Adam Smith on the early and rude state of society and the age of hunters Ecem Okan To cite this version: Ecem Okan. How did it all begin? Adam Smith on the early and rude state of society and the age of hunters. European Journal of the History of Economic Thought, Taylor & Francis (Routledge), 2017, 24 (6), pp.1247-1276. 10.1080/09672567.2017.1381134. hal-03171143 HAL Id: hal-03171143 https://hal.univ-lorraine.fr/hal-03171143 Submitted on 16 Mar 2021 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. How did it all begin? Adam Smith on the early and rude state of society and the age of hunters Abstract: Scholars tend to examine Smith’s historical approach as a whole from the perspective of the four stages theory. This leads to a neglect of Smith’s ability to use history in different ways as his different purposes require. This article distinguishes Smith’s recourse to primitive society with respect to his purposes in Wealth of Nations and in Lectures on Jurisprudence. In the former, Smith analyses the capitalist economy, thereby laying emphasis on capital and the division of labour in his account of wealth.
    [Show full text]
  • Conjecturalism in the Historical Writings of John Millar
    A LIKELY STORY: CONJECTURALISM IN THE HISTORICAL WRITINGS OF JOHN MILLAR by STEPHEN DAVID TAKAHASHI B.A., The University of Victoria, 1999 A THESIS SUBMITTED IN PARTIAL FULFILMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF MASTER OF ARTS in THE FACULTY OF GRADUATE STUDIES (Department of History) We accept this thesis as conforming to the required standard THE UNIVERSITY OF BRITISH COLUMBIA August 2001 © Stephen David Takahashi, 2001 In presenting this thesis in partial fulfilment of the requirements for an advanced degree at the University of British Columbia, I agree that the Library shall make it freely available for reference and study. I further agree that permission for extensive copying of this thesis for scholarly purposes may be granted by the head of my department or by his or her representatives. It is understood that copying or publication of this thesis for financial gain shall not be allowed without my written permission. Department of History The University of British Columbia Vancouver, Canada ABSTRACT John Millar's historical works have not, since the era of their original publication, been viewed as such by their principal commentators. Though Millar's Discourse on the Origin of the Distinction of Ranks (1771) has received acclaim for its perceived sociological value, his intended masterwork, An Historical View of the English Constitution (1803) has been almost completely neglected by contemporary scholarship. The intent of this paper is threefold: first, by viewing Millar in the historiographical context of late Enlightenment Britain, Millar's texts become recognizable as they were when they were first read, that is, as works of history.
    [Show full text]
  • Of Mushrooms and Method: History and the Family in Hobbes's
    1 Of Mushrooms and Method: History and the Family in Hobbes’s Science of Politics The standard view of Thomas Hobbes’s political philosophy is that it is a form of contract theory. Commentators who disagree on much else nonetheless typically agree upon this.1 Deborah Baumgold, in particular, has recently argued that Hobbes’s political theory is an attempt to combine the absolutist commitments of Jean Bodin with the contract approach of Hugo Grotius, inaugurating a contractualist tradition in political thought that runs through Locke and Rousseau all the way to Rawls.2 There are, however, compelling reasons for rejecting the standard view of Hobbes as a contract theorist. These are revealed by undertaking a close examination of Hobbes’s account of the family and of the role of history. Doing so invites us to reconsider our assessment of how he believes that sovereignty, and thus political society, really comes into being, and what that means for the underlying status and foundation of Hobbes’s political philosophy as a whole. The following essay performs this task, aiming in particular to reverse the order of priority typically assigned to Hobbes’s views of sovereignty by institution and acquisition. In addition to casting doubt on Hobbes’s status as a contract theorist, two further consequences follow. First, we are discouraged from thinking of Hobbes as in any sense a foundationally democratic thinker. Second, the way to an alternative intellectual history of post-Hobbesian political thought is opened, one focusing upon history and the family in the context of arguments over human sociability rather than the traditional contract-orientated path with its much-trodden route through Locke and Rousseau.
    [Show full text]
  • 2. Politics and Culture in Hume's History Of
    2. POLITICS AND CULTURE IN HUME’S HISTORY OF ENGLAND Simon Kow J.G.A. Pocock has remarked that “Hume is the only major philosopher to have produced a major work of historiography, and to have expounded his philosophy through the medium of historiography without the aid of a historicist philosophy of the kind appearing in the next century”.1 Nev- ertheless, while Hume’s History of England (1754–62) may have been con- sidered “for at least a hundred years, the standard history of the English nation”,2 it was relatively neglected thereafter until recent decades and is not as commented upon by interpreters of Hume as such works as A Trea- tise of Human Nature. Indeed, the relation between Hume’s history and his philosophy is far from clear, not least because Hume makes no explicit ref- erence in his history to the Treatise, the two Enquiries, or other such works regarded as central to his philosophical thought.3 At best, Hume’s status as the first “philosophical historian”4 should be taken in a broad sense; as Pocock points out, “philosophy” in Hume’s time “very often denoted a fixed determination to have nothing to do with epistemology, metaphys- ics or what could otherwise be termed ‘minute philosophy’ ”.5 Although the degree to which Hume’s “minute philosophy” and his his- torical work can be linked poses major difficulties for the interpreter, we 1 J.G.A. Pocock, Barbarism and Religion, Volume 2: Narratives of Civil Government (Cam- bridge, Eng., 1999), p. 176. 2 David Fate Norton, “History and Philosophy in Hume’s Thought”, in David Fate Nor- ton and Richard H.
    [Show full text]
  • 10764.Ch01.Pdf
    © 2008 UC Regents Buy this book The publisher gratefully acknowledges the generous contribution to this book provided by the Ahmanson Foundation Humanities Endowment Fund of the University of California Press Foundation. The publisher also gratefully acknowledges the support of the Harvard Historical Series. Cover illustration and frontispiece from Athanasius Kircher, Arca Noë, in tres libros digesta. Reproduced courtesy of the Houghton Library, Harvard University. A Caravan Book For more information, visit www.caravanbooks. org. University of California Press, one of the most distinguished university presses in the United States, enriches lives around the world by advancing scholarship in the humanities, social sciences, and natural sciences. Its activities are supported by the UC Press Foundation and by philanthropic contributions from individuals and institutions. For more information, visit www.ucpress.edu. University of California Press Berkeley and Los Angeles, California University of California Press, Ltd. London, England © 2008 by The Regents of the University of California Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Smail, Daniel Lord. On deep history and the brain / Daniel Lord Smail. p. cm. Includes bibliographical references and index. isbn: 978-0-520-25289-9 (cloth : alk. paper) 1. History—Philosophy. I. Title. D16.9.S62 2007 901—dc22 2007011729 Manufactured in the United States of America 15 14 13 12 11 10 09 08 10987654321 The paper used in this publication meets the minimum requirements of ansi/niso z39.48–1992 (r 1997) (Permanence of Paper). CONTENTS Preface ix Introduction: Toward Reunion in History 1 1. The Grip of Sacred History 12 2. Resistance 40 3. Between Darwin and Lamarck 74 4.
    [Show full text]