A THEORY of JUSTICE PLURALISM by Adam Gjesdal

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

A THEORY of JUSTICE PLURALISM by Adam Gjesdal A Theory of Justice Pluralism Item Type text; Electronic Dissertation Authors Gjesdal, Adam Publisher The University of Arizona. Rights Copyright © is held by the author. Digital access to this material is made possible by the University Libraries, University of Arizona. Further transmission, reproduction, presentation (such as public display or performance) of protected items is prohibited except with permission of the author. Download date 26/09/2021 03:50:42 Link to Item http://hdl.handle.net/10150/634403 A THEORY OF JUSTICE PLURALISM by Adam Gjesdal __________________________ Copyright © Adam Gjesdal 2019 A Dissertation Submitted to the Faculty of the DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements For the Degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY In the Graduate College THE UNIVERSITY OF ARIZONA 2019 3 Acknowledgments I wish to thank the Institute for Humane Studies, the Mercatus Center at George Mason University, and the Center for the Philosophy of Freedom at the University of Arizona for financial support that freed so much of my time for research. Shauna Garland, Debbie Jackson, Sandra Kimball, and Gayle Siegel have been kind and patient sources of support, administrative and otherwise. Each member of my committee—Tom Christano, Jerry Gaus, Dave Schmidtz, and Steve Wall—exemplifies a different style of philosophizing and provides a different inspirational model for how to grow as a scholar, and I have learned much from each of them. Communicativeness not being one of my vices, I have not discussed this dissertation with many people outside of my committee. But I wish to single out and thank Phil Smolenski, Kevin Vallier, and Chad Van Schoelandt for helpful conversation. Jerry Gaus has been overwhelmingly generous with his time mentoring me. Whatever merits this dissertation may have are all due to his influence. I expect to look back in a few years on this dissertation as less than a journeyman’s work, so it is with some embarrassment I dedicate it to anyone. With embarrassment, then, I dedicate it to Jerry. 4 Table of Contents Abstract 5 Introduction 6 Chapter 1: Justice Pluralism and Political Liberalism 12 Chapter 2: Political Liberalism without Epistemology 36 Chapter 3: Justice Pluralism and Optimal Legitimacy 65 Chapter 4: Abortion and the Limits of Optimal Legitimacy 105 Gjesdal Dissertation 5 Abstract Political liberalism aims to describe how a free, liberal political order can be justified in societies marked by deep, intractable disagreement about matters of religion, philosophy, and morality. My dissertation explores the implications for political liberalism of justice pluralism: the view that reasonable citizens can disagree over which theory of justice, of a set of eligible or “reasonable” theories, is best. I argue that the values of political liberalism that lead to acknowledging a pluralism of reasonable comprehensive doctrines also lead to seeing political liberalism as a two-level theory. There is the meta-level of political liberalism per se, and the level of specific conceptions of justice. Political liberalism per se respects reasonable disagreement about the design of an original position argument, seeing no single design as the most reasonable. Specific conceptions of justice like Rawls’ justice as fairness, in contrast, take a stand on which specific design of an original position argument is the most reasonable. As a result, at each level, political liberalism has different constraints on the claims it can make about the nature of a just society. The difficult challenge is to articulate in just what sense a reasonable citizen can embrace the meta-theory of political liberalism, which sees many reasonable conceptions as on par, while nevertheless, reasonably advocating their favored conception as the best. This dissertation attempts to meet this challenge, showing that while political liberalism per se does not take sides in disputes between reasonable conceptions of justice, it is open to citizens to embrace one conception that guides their reasoning about a range of political matters. Gjesdal Dissertation 6 Introduction Liberal institutions encourage reasonable disagreement by instilling in citizens the idea that they are politically free and equal. Reasoning under this self-conception, citizens naturally develop a pluralism of conceptions of the good life. They also develop a pluralism of conceptions of the just society. Call this the thesis of reasonable disagreement. This thesis predicts that reasonable disagreement is, in Rawls’ words, “the normal result of the exercise of human reason within the framework of the free institutions of a constitutional democratic regime.”1 The thesis implies nothing about how these institutions should work, or how citizens living under them should act. For that we must turn to what Stephen Macedo calls “the moral lodestar” of the political liberal project: the principle of public justification.2 We are concerned here with a formulation of this principle requiring that exercises of political power be justified to citizens in terms they can accept as free and equal.3 The thesis of reasonable disagreement and the principle of public justification together seem to have the troubling implication that, for political liberals, justice cannot justify political power. Together, the thesis and principle imply that exercises of political power should not be justified by 1 John Rawls, Political Liberalism. Columbia University Press, 2005, xvi 2 Stephen Macedo, Liberal Virtues: Citizenship, Virtue, and Community in Liberal Constitutionalism. Oxford University Press, 1990, 78. 3 In formulating the principle of public justification this way, I am following Rawls and his criterion of reciprocity, which in the unpublished, revised version of Political Liberalism requires that exercises of political power be acceptable to citizens “as free and equal.” See HUM 48, Box 30, folder 3, “Lecture IV: The Idea of Overlapping Consensus,” Harvard University Archives, 108. Other theorists—Gerald Gaus is the prominent example—formulate the principle quite differently, requiring instead that citizens (or idealized members of the public) have “sufficient reason to endorse” publicly justified laws, rather than that those laws be acceptable to them as free and equal. This dissertation focuses exclusively on the Rawlsian formulation. Gaus offers his alternative formulation of the principle at: The Order of Public Reason: A Theory of Freedom and Morality in a Diverse and Bounded World. Cambridge University Press, 2011, 263. For an extensive discussion of the merits and objections to the “sufficient reason to endorse” formulation, see Kevin Vallier. Public Justification. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/justification-public/. Gjesdal Dissertation 7 appeal to doctrines the truth of which are in reasonable dispute. Regarding these doctrines, some citizens reject their truth as a consequence of reasoning under the conception of themselves as free and equal. These citizens cannot accept these doctrines as free and equal, in the very specific sense that they reject their truth while reasoning as free and equal. Because these doctrines include conceptions of justice, political liberals’ own commitments seem to imply that conceptions of justice cannot justify exercises of political power to all reasonable citizens. Political liberals must show this implication does not follow, if conceptions of justice are to have a justificatory role in the theory of political liberalism. This dissertation develops a two-level theory of political liberalism to reconcile the thesis of reasonable disagreement with the principle of public justification. On the two-level view, all reasonable citizens endorse a set of political values, but they reasonably disagree about how these values are best interpreted and ordered into a political conception. The very best interpretation and ordering yields the political conception that is most reasonable. What distinguishes the two-level view from other theories of political liberalism is its commitment to viewing no single conception of justice as uniquely most reasonable. The two-level view embraces justice pluralism, holding that there is a family of most reasonable political conceptions of justice. This family of most reasonable political conceptions constitutes the second level of the two-level theory. The first level is that of a single conception of justice that a citizen justifiably regards as most reasonable. Thus the two-level theory views reasonable citizens in liberal societies as deliberating within three mutually interacting evaluative frameworks: The family of most reasonable political conceptions (2nd level of political liberalism) A single most reasonable political conception of justice (1st level of political liberalism) A reasonable comprehensive doctrine We reconcile the thesis of reasonable disagreement with the principle of public justification as Gjesdal Dissertation 8 follows. Citizens reasonably disagree at the first level about which conception of justice is most reasonable. At the second level, any member of the family of most reasonable political conceptions offers terms citizens can accept as free and equal. Both levels describe standpoints citizens adopt. The first level describes the standpoint of a citizen deliberating about which proposed law to support, and the second level, that of a citizen evaluating the legitimacy of enacted law. The two-level theory assumes all citizens honor what Rawls
Recommended publications
  • Shorter Curriculum Vitae Akihiro Kanamori
    SHORTER CURRICULUM VITAE AKIHIRO KANAMORI DESCRIPTION: Born 23 October 1948 in Tokyo, Japan; now a United States citizen. DEGREES: 1966-1970 California Institute of Technology, Bachelor of Science. 1970-1975 University of Cambridge (King's College), Doctor of Philosophy. Subject: Set Theory, Mathematics. Thesis: Ultrafilters over Uncountable Cardinals. Advisor: A.R.D. Mathias. This involved one year of research at: 1972-1973 University of Wisconsin, Madison. Advisor: K. Kunen. PROFESSIONAL EXPERIENCE: 1975-1977 Lectureship at the University of California, Berkeley. 1977-1981 Benjamin Pierce Assistant Professorship at Harvard University. 1981-1982 Assistant Professorship at Baruch College of the City University of New York. 1982-1983 Visiting Associate Professorship at Boston University. 1983-1992 Associate Professorship at Boston University. 1988-1989 Berman Visiting Professorship, Institute of Mathematics, Hebrew University of Jerusalem. 1992- Professorship at Boston University. 1995 Visiting Professorship, Institute of Mathematics, Hebrew Universiy of Jerusalem. 2002-2003 Senior Fellow of the Dibner Institute for the History of Science and Technology. Visiting Scholar at the Department of the History of Science at Harvard University. 1 2009-2010 Senior Fellow of the Lichtenberg-Kolleg, Institute for Advanced Study, G¨ottingen,Germany. Lecture Course on Set Theory, Mathematische Institut, G¨ottingen,Germany, June-July 2010. FELLOWSHIPS AND AWARDS: Marshall Scholarship (British Government), 1970-1972. Danforth Foundation Fellowship, 1970-1975. Woodrow Wilson Foundation Fellowship, 1970. 1984 New England Open Co-Champion of Chess. Equal First 1986 Greater Boston Chess Open. Equal Second, 1987 Massachusetts Chess Open Championship. Equal Sixth, 1989 Israel Open. Class Prize, 1992 New England Open Championship. 2002-2003 Senior Fellowship, Dibner Institute for the History of Science and Technology.
    [Show full text]
  • Future Pasts
    FUTURE PASTS The Analytic Tradition in Twentieth-Century Philosophy Edited by JULIET FLOYD SANFORD SHIEH OXFORD VNWERSITY I'RSSS 2001 1879 Publication ofFr:ege's Begriffsschrift 1 Frege's Conception of Logic WARREN GOLDFARB Frege is of course an important progenitor of modern logic. The technical ad­ vances he made were compreheusive. He clearly depicted polyadic predication, negation. the conditional, and the quantifier as the bases of logic; and he gave an analysis of and a notation for t.he quantifier that enabled him to deal fully and perspicuously with multiple generality. Moreover. be argued that mathematical demonstrations, to be ti.illy rigorous, must be carried out using only explicitly for­ mulated rules, that is, syntactically specified axioms and rules of inference. Less clear, however. is the philosophical and interpretive question ofhow Frege understands his formalism and its purposes. Upon examination, it appears that Frege had a rather different view of the subject he was creating than we do nowa­ days. ln lectures and seminars as far back as the early 1960s, Burton Dreben called attention to differences between how Frege viewed i.he subject mauer of logic and how we do. The point has been taken up by several commentators, beginning with Jean van Heijenoort. 1 The technical development historically required to get from a Fregeau conception to our own was discussed in my "Logic in the Twenties: The Nature of the Quantifier."2 Yet there is currently litlle ap­ preciation of the philosophical import of these differences, that is, the role in Prege' s philosophy that his conception oflogic, as opposed to ours.
    [Show full text]
  • 6 X 10.Long New.P65
    Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-11514-8 - Kurt Godel: Essays for his Centennial Edited by Solomon Feferman, Charles Parsons and Stephen G. Simpson Excerpt More information GENERAL © in this web service Cambridge University Press www.cambridge.org Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-11514-8 - Kurt Godel: Essays for his Centennial Edited by Solomon Feferman, Charles Parsons and Stephen G. Simpson Excerpt More information THE GODEL¨ EDITORIAL PROJECT: A SYNOPSIS SOLOMON FEFERMAN The final two volumes, numbers IV and V, of the Oxford University Press edition of the Collected Works of Kurt Godel¨ [3]–[7] appeared in 2003, thus completing a project that started over twenty years earlier. What I mainly want to do here is trace, from the vantage point of my personal involvement, the at some times halting and at other times intense development of the Godel¨ editorial project from the first initiatives following Godel’s¨ death in 1978 to its completion last year. It may be useful to scholars mounting similar editorial projects for other significant figures in our field to learn how and why various decisions were made and how the work was carried out, though of course much is particular to who and what we were dealing with. My hope here is also to give the reader who is not already familiar with the Godel¨ Works a sense of what has been gained in the process, and to encourage dipping in according to interest. Given the absolute importance of Godel¨ for mathematical logic, students should also be pointed to these important source materials to experience first hand the exercise of his genius and the varied ways of his thought and to see how scholarly and critical studies help to expand their significance.
    [Show full text]
  • Applicability of Mathematics As a Philosophical Problem
    The Applicability of Mathematics as a Philosophical Problem The Appl icabiIity of Mathematics as a Philosophical Problem Mark Steiner Harvard University Press Cambridge, Massachusetts London, England 1998 To the memory ofmyfather and my mother Copyright © 1998 by the President and Fellows of Harvard College All rights reserved Printed in the United States of America Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Steiner, Mark. The applicability of mathematics as a philosophical problem / Mark Steiner. p. cm. Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 0-674-04097-X (cloth) ISBN 0-674-00970-3 (paper) 1. Mathematical physics. 2. Mathelnatics-Philosophy. QC20.S743 1998 530. I5-dc2l 98-3468 This book has been digitally reprinted. The content remains identical to that ofprevious printings. Contents Acknowledgments vii Introduction 1. The Semantic Applicability of Mathematics: Frege's Achievements 13 2. The Descriptive Applicability of Mathematics 24 3. Mathematics, Analogies, and Discovery in Physics 48 4. Pythagorean Analogies in Physics 76 5. Formalisms and Formalist Reasoning in Quantum Mechanics 116 6. Formalist Reasoning: The Mystery of Quantization 136 Appendix A. A "Nonphysical" Derivation of Quantum Mechanics 177 Appendix B. Nucleon-Pion Scattering 197 Appendix C. Nonrelativistic Schroedinger Equation with Spin 200 References 203 Index 211 Acknowledgments I am grateful to Daniel Amit, Paul Benacerraf, Bernard Berofsky, Jed Buchwald, Sylvain Cappell, Alan Chalmers, Percy Deift, Burton Dreben, Shmuel Elitzur, Juliet Floyd, Harry Furstenberg, Joel Gersten, Shelly Goldstein, Shaughan Lavine, Jesper Liitzen, David Malament, Nathan Malkin, Benoit Mandelbrot, Sidney Morgenbesser, Yuval Ne'eman, Robert Nozick, Itamar Pitowsky, Carl Posy, Hilary Putnam, Sam Schweber, Stewart Shapiro, Barry Simon, Shlomo Sternberg, and Larry Zalcman for their much appre­ ciated advice and criticism.
    [Show full text]
  • Rawls's Political Liberalism and Its Foundation
    Copyright by Carla Saenz 2007 The Dissertation Committee for Carla Saenz certifies that this is the approved ver­ sion of the following dissertation: POLITICAL LIBERALISM AND ITS INTERNAL CRITIQUES: FEMINIST THEORY, COMMUNITARIANISM, AND REPUBLI­ CANISM Committee: A.P. Martinich, Supervisor Kathleen M. Higgins Cory Juhl S.A. Lloyd Tara Smith POLITICAL LIBERALISM AND ITS INTERNAL CRITIQUES: FEMINIST THEORY, COMMUNITARIANISM, AND REPUBLI­ CANISM by Carla Saenz, B.A.; M.A. Dissertation Presented to the Faculty of the Graduate School of The University of Texas at Austin in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy The University of Texas at Austin May, 2007 To my girlfriends, including my mother, my sisters, and my aunt Marilú, for their unconditional love and support. Acknowledgements This project would not have been realized without the support of many people whom I owe my gratitude. Many thanks to the members of my dissertation committee ±Al Martinich, Kathleen Higgins, Tara Smith, Sharon Lloyd, and Cory JuhlÐ for their generous comments and enormous support. No words can properly express my gratitude to my supervisor, Al Martinich, for his guidance. The countless hours I have spent discussing my project with him are invaluable. As an academic, Al is an insightful philosopher, an acute reader, and a brilliant teacher. I cannot list the sections of my dissertation that have benefited from his sharp comments and suggestions. I have learned from him the kind of professional I want to be. As a person, he is generous, sincere, wise, and incredibly humble. He is the phronimos. I could not have had a better role model.
    [Show full text]
  • WORKING from WITHIN the Nature and Development of Quine's
    [Final manuscript. Forthcoming, Oxford University Press] WORKING FROM WITHIN The Nature and Development of Quine’s Naturalism Sander Verhaegh ii It is understandable […] that the philosopher should seek a transcendental vantage point, outside the world that imprisons [the] natural scientist and mathematician. He would make himself independent of the conceptual scheme which it is his task to study and revise. “Give me πoυ στω [a place to stand]”, Archimedes said, “and I will move the world.” However, there is no such cosmic exile. […] The philosopher is in the position rather, as Neurath says, “of a mariner who must rebuild his ship on the open sea”. W. V. Quine (notes for Sign and Object, November 5, 1944) iii Table of Contents Preface xi List of Abbreviations xv 1. Introduction 1 PART I: NATURE 2. Naturalizing Epistemology 25 3. Naturalizing Metaphysics 59 4. In Mediis Rebus 89 PART II: DEVELOPMENT 5. Sign and Object 127 6. Analytic and Synthetic 169 7. Science and Philosophy 231 8. Conclusion 265 Appendices 269 Bibliography 311 Index 353 iv Extended Table of Contents Preface xi List of Abbreviations xv 1. Introduction 1 1.0. Summary 1 1.1. Historical background 1 1.2. Naturalism and analytic philosophy 5 1.3. Working from within 7 1.4. Reading Quine in historical context 9 1.5. Plan 11 PART I: NATURE 2. Naturalizing Epistemology 25 2.0. Summary 25 2.1. Introduction 25 2.2. From certainty to straight psychology 29 2.3. Two strategies 35 2.4. Self-sufficient sensory languages 37 2.5. Quine’s response to the sceptic 41 2.6.
    [Show full text]
  • Bibliography of the Writings of Hilary Putnam
    PART THREE BIBLIOGRAPHY OF THE WRITINGS OF HILARY PUTNAM Compiled and Edited by John R. ShooK with the assistance of Hilary Putnam anD Joseph PalenCIK Putnam Bibliography.indd 891 1/24/2015 4:09:12 PM Putnam Bibliography.indd 892 1/24/2015 4:09:12 PM BIBLIOGRAPHY OF THE WRITINGS OF Hilary Putnam This bibliography lists books and then shorter writings, in chronological order of their first publication. Chapters of books are accompanied by a year of first publication; those chapters lacking a year were first published in that book. Only selected reprintings of shorter writings are mentioned, to clarify multiple versions. A translation of a shorter item is included if that was its first publication; any later publication in English is mentioned. BOOKS The Meaning of the Concept of Probability in Application to Finite Sequences. Ph.D. dis- sertation, University of California, Los Angeles, 1951. New York: Garland, 1990. The 1990 reprinting includes “Introduction Some Years Later,” 1–12. Philosophy of Mathematics: Selected Readings. Edited with Paul Benacerraf. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall, 1964. Includes an “Introduction” with Paul Benacerraf, 1–27. The 2nd edition (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1983) adds two chapters by Putnam: “Mathematics without Foundations” (1967), 295–313; and “Models and Reality” (1980), 421–45. Philosophy of Logic. New York: Harper and Row, 1971. London: George Allen and Unwin, 1972. Translated into Italian (1975), Japanese (1975), Chinese (1984). Repr. in Math- ematics, Matter and Method, 2nd ed. (1985), 323–57. Repr., London: Routledge, 2010. CONTENTS Preface, vii 1. What Logic Is, 3–7 2.
    [Show full text]
  • Wittgenstein's Investigations 1-133
    Wittgenstein’s Investigations 1–133 ‘It is a genuinely important book…there is nothing I know of in print which goes into such sophisticated detail as Lugg in getting Wittgenstein right.’ Burton Dreben, Harvard and Boston Universities One of the greatest works of twentieth-century philosophy, Ludwig Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations is also one of the most controversial. Wittgenstein’s Investigations 1–133 provides a clear and concise introduction to the crucial early sections of this classic work. Andrew Lugg discusses in detail what Wittgenstein says about meaning, metaphysics and philosophy in sections 1–133 of the Philosophical Investigations. Besides making Wittgenstein’s thought accessible to a general audience and explaining its philosophical significance, the book develops a radical interpretation of his remarks. It takes Wittgenstein’s text to epitomize his philosophical outlook and applies Wittgenstein’s philosophical strategy to his own words. Wittgenstein’s Investigations 1–133 will be a valuable resource for anyone interested in Wittgenstein, language and the history of twentieth- century philosophy. Andrew Lugg is Professor of Philosophy at the University of Ottawa. For Lynne Cohen, fellow traveller and partner for the best part of a lifetime. Wittgenstein’s Investigations 1–133 A guide and interpretation Andrew Lugg London and New York First published 2000 by Routledge 11 New Fetter Lane, London EC4P 4EE Simultaneously published in the USA and Canada by Routledge 29 West 35th Street, New York, NY 10001 Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group This edition published in the Taylor & Francis e-Library, 2003. ©2000 Andrew Lugg All rights reserved.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction to the Philosophy of J. L. Austin
    The Philosophy of J. L. Austin EDITED BY Martin Gustafsson and Richard Sørli 1 3 Great Clarendon Street, Oxford ox2 6dp Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers the University’s objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education by publishing worldwide in Oxford New York Auckland Cape Town Dar es Salaam Hong Kong Karachi Kuala Lumpur Madrid Melbourne Mexico City Nairobi New Delhi Shanghai Taipei Toronto With offices in Argentina Austria Brazil Chile Czech Republic France Greece Guatemala Hungary Italy Japan Poland Portugal Singapore South Korea Switzerland Thailand Turkey Ukraine Vietnam Oxford is a registered trade mark of Oxford University Press in the UK and in certain other countries Published in the United States by Oxford University Press Inc., New York # The several contributors 2011 The moral rights of the authors have been asserted Database right Oxford University Press (maker) First published 2011 All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, without the prior permission in writing of Oxford University Press, or as expressly permitted by law, or under terms agreed with the appropriate reprographics rights organization. Enquiries concerning reproduction outside the scope of the above should be sent to the Rights Department, Oxford University Press, at the address above You must not circulate this book in any other binding or cover and you must impose the same condition on any acquirer British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data Data available Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data Data available Typeset by SPI Publisher Services, Pondicherry, India Printed in Great Britain on acid-free paper by MPG Books Group, Bodmin and King’s Lynn ISBN 978–0–19–921975–9 1 3 5 7 9 10 8 6 4 2 Contents Contributors vi 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Hannah Ginsborg Department of Philosophy University of California, Berkeley Berkeley, CA 94720-2390 Email: [email protected] Office Phone: 510 664 9077
    Hannah Ginsborg Department of Philosophy University of California, Berkeley Berkeley, CA 94720-2390 Email: [email protected] Office phone: 510 664 9077 EMPLOYMENT Willis S and Marion Slusser Professor of Philosophy, U.C. Berkeley, 2018-present Chair, Department of Philosophy, U.C. Berkeley, 2016- 2019 Professor of Philosophy, U.C. Berkeley, 2006- present Associate Professor of Philosophy, U.C. Berkeley, 1990-2006 Assistant Professor of Philosophy, U.C. Berkeley, 1988-1990 Teaching Fellow, Harvard University, 1982-1984 and 1986-1987 EDUCATION Harvard University, 1980-1988 Ph.D. in Philosophy awarded 1989. Dissertation: “The Role of Taste in Kant’s Theory of Cognition,” supervised by Burton Dreben and John Rawls University of Oxford, 1976-1980 Major Scholar at Wadham College, reading Philosophy and Modern Languages (French). B.A. (First Class Honours) awarded 1980 Freie Universität, Berlin, Germany, 1985-1986 Study in philosophy Université de Paris-1, France , 1978-1979. Study in logic and philosophy ACADEMIC PRIZES, AWARDS AND FELLOWSHIPS Reimar Lüst Prize (awarded by the Humboldt Foundation and the Fritz Thyssen Foundation), 2019 Visiting Scholar, Humboldt University, Berlin, 2019-2020 U. C. Berkeley Humanities Research Fellowship, 2019-2020 Taylor Fellowship (University of Otago, New Zealand), July 2019 Visiting Research Professor, Ludwig-Maximilian University of Munich, Fall 2014 Fellow, Wissenschaftskolleg zu Berlin (Institute of Advanced Study, Berlin), 2010-2011 Senior Fellow, Townsend Center for the Humanities, U.C. Berkeley, 2008-2009 Visiting Scholar, Max Planck Institute for the History of Science, Berlin, summers 2006, 2007 and 2008 Visting Scholar, Max Planck Institute for the History of Science, Berlin, 2004-2005 American Council of Learned Societies Fellowship, 2004-2005 U.C.
    [Show full text]
  • Replace This with the Actual Title Using All Caps
    POLITICAL LIBERALISM AND THE POSSIBILITY OF EGALITARIANISM A Dissertation Presented to the Faculty of the Graduate School of Cornell University In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy by James Kelleher III January 2008 © 2008 James Kelleher III POLITICAL LIBERALISM AND THE POSSIBILITY OF EGALITARIANISM James Kelleher III, Ph. D. Cornell University 2008 This dissertation is a study of political liberalism, both as that doctrine was developed by John Rawls and as it has come to be understood and modified by others. It is agreed that the search for moral common ground was at the heart of Rawls’s project, but the details of his preferred response to the “fact of reasonable pluralism” are widely disputed. I argue that the currently dominant views of these details are mistaken, and I offer new interpretations of Rawls’s political liberalism and of his reasons for developing it. I claim that Rawls’s theory is, contrary to most accounts, more concerned with justice than with legitimacy and less concerned with securing agreement between actually existing citizens than his most well-known formulations might suggest. But this resulting theory incorporates two fundamental yet conflicting strands, and the only way to render it consistent and plausible is to formulate an “orthodox political liberalism” that ends up looking much like the view painted by the (still) mistaken rival interpretations. This orthodox political liberalism derives its plausibility from the resemblance of its moral rationale to the rationale for the traditional liberal stance in favor of state neutrality on religion. It is next argued that orthodox political liberalism has difficultly sustaining the arguments needed to defend a sufficiently determinate egalitarian criterion of distributive justice.
    [Show full text]
  • Conversations 7
    Conversations 7 THE JOURNAL OF CAVELLIAN STUDIES CONVERSATIONS 7 Conversations: The Journal of Cavellian Studies 7 Date June 2019 - September 2020 Editor David LaRocca (Cornell University) Contributors Steven G. Affeldt (Le Moyne College) Isabel Andrade (Yachay Wasi) Stephanie Brown (Williams College) Alice Crary (University of Oxford/The New School) Byron Davies (National Autonomous University of Mexico) Thomas Dumm (Amherst College) Richard Eldridge (Swarthmore College) Yves Erard (University of Lausanne) Eli Friedlander (Tel Aviv University) Alonso Gamarra (McGill University) Paul Grimstad (Columbia University) Arata Hamawaki (Auburn University) Louisa Kania (Williams College) Nelly Lin-Schweitzer (Williams College) Richard Moran (Harvard University) Sianne Ngai (Stanford University) Bernie Rhie (Williams College) Lawrence Rhu (University of South Carolina) Eric Ritter (Vanderbilt University) William Rothman (University of Miami) Naoko Saito (Kyoto University) Don Selby (College of Staten Island, The City University of New York) P. Adams Sitney (Princeton University) Abraham D. Stone (University of California, Santa Cruz) Nicholas F. Stang (University of Toronto) Lindsay Waters (Harvard University Press) Kay Young (University of California, Santa Barbara) CONVERSATIONS 7 Managing Editors Sérgio Dias Branco (University of Coimbra): [email protected] Amir Khan (Dalian Maritime University): [email protected] Advisory Board Sarah Beckwith (Duke University) Peter Dula (Eastern Mennonite University) Richard Eldridge (Swarthmore
    [Show full text]