Nominalism and Its Aftermath: the Philosophy of Nelson Goodman Dordrecht: Springer, IX, 170 P

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Nominalism and Its Aftermath: the Philosophy of Nelson Goodman Dordrecht: Springer, IX, 170 P Enrahonar. Quaderns de Filosofia 49, 2012 155-174 RESSENYES Shottenkirk, Dena (2009) Nominalism and Its Aftermath: The Philosophy of Nelson Goodman Dordrecht: Springer, IX, 170 p. Nominalism Unscathed ognizes, themes from all three interweave Nelson Goodman is widely considered Goodman’s work, so it would be a mis- one of the foremost philosophers of the take to end the discussion there. 20th century. He made significant con- To understand the motivation be- tributions to metaphysics, epistemology hind Goodman’s nominalism, some and the philosophy of art. Standardly his background may be helpful. According works are considered in isolation, and are to naïve set theory, any collection of not seen as resting upon each other in items constitutes a set. Unfortunately, any significant way. In Nominalism and this gives rise to the Russell paradox. The its Aftermath: the Philosophy of Nelson set of all sets that do not contain them- Goodman, Dena Shottenkirk (Lecturer at selves contains itself if and only if it does Brooklyn College in New York) attempts not contain itself. Although intuitively to unite Goodman’s philosophical enter- plausible, it is inconsistent. Further, be- prises under the nominalist framework cause arithmetic reduces to set theory, if he worked in. This is an insightful and naïve set theory is set theory, mathemat- promising line of inquiry. However, the ics as a whole rests on shaky ground. book falls short of its goal due to miscon- Thus several mathematicians including ceptions of Goodman’s philosophical Russell developed amended versions of positions. set theory. Russell’s ramified theory The work is composed of three main of types constrains set membership in a sections that focus on Goodman’s meta- manner that he describes as «perverse» physics, epistemology and philosophy of (Bertrand Russell 1908). Every other art. Each section draws heavily on the non-naïve set theory contains elements conclusions of its predecessors. Given the that are equally unintuitive. All are des- chronological order of Goodman’s major perate expedients to restore consistency. publications (The Structure of Appearance Nelson Goodman took a much bold- (1951), Fact, Fiction and Forecast (1955), er course. He denied the existence of sets, and Languages of Art (1968)), this is restricting his ontology to individuals. plausible. However, as Shottenkirk rec- The two guiding principles governing his 156 Enrahonar. Quaderns de Filosofia 49, 2012 Ressenyes nominalism are ‘entities are identical just that «philosophy is not about ‘the world’ in case their parts are identical’ and ‘there but about the language through which we is no entity without an identity’. The first see the world, and the latter is primarily principle excludes set theory, because ascertained through science» (68). This is many different sets have exactly the same wrong on multiple counts. It is at best elements. The second excludes intension- misleading to say that Goodman thinks al entities such as properties, because they that philosophy is not about the world. lack determinate identity conditions. He holds that symbols refer to items in Anything that satisfies the two conditions the world. The word ‘cat’ and a picture qualifies as an individual — so it is pos- of a cat is about a cat, not about the way sible for abstract, concrete, mental and we represent cats. The word ‘individual’ physical things to be individuals. Good- is about an individual, not about the way man devoted much of his early career to we represent individuals. Goodman does determining what could be accomplished not hold that understanding is couched with such a limited ontological frame- exclusively in language. In Languages of work. He and Henry Leonard developed Art he claims that works of art function a version of mereology — the calculus of in non-linguistic symbol-systems which individuals (Nelson Goodman and enable us to understand things in non- Henry Leonard 1940). In ‘Steps toward linguistic ways. He denies that under- a Constructive Nominalism’ (1947) standing is primarily achieved through Goodman and W. V. Quine investigated science. He insists that «the arts must be how much of mathematics could be sal- taken no less seriously than the sciences vaged in an ontology without sets. as modes of discovery, creation and en- Philosophers standardly assume that largement of knowledge in the broad so drastically restricting metaphysical re- sense of advancement of the understand- sources must yield an impoverished phi- ing» (WW, 102). losophy. However, in The Structure of One of the most glaring mistakes in Appearance, Goodman shows that es- Nominalism and its Aftermath concerns chewing sets, properties and natural the presentation of the grue paradox. kinds can be liberating. We can acknowl- Goodman is well known for demonstrat- edge that members of any extension have ing that we do not have an adequate con- something in common — i.e., the mem- ception of inductive validity. Previously, bership in that extension. Atypical kinds many thinkers accepted the principle may be interesting and informative. that if one has observed many A’s in the There is no incentive to think that there past and they have all been B’s and no is a single, basic way the world is. In The A’s that are not B’s, one has reason to Structure of Appearance Goodman devel- believe that unobserved A’s are also B’s. ops a phenomenalist system to illustrate Then Goodman introduced ‘grue’. the power of his form of nominalism. Something is grue just in case it is ob- But he does not claim that it does or served before time t and found to be should underwrite physicalism. There are green, or not observed before time t and many ways things can be organized. Phe- is blue. If time t is in the future, all ob- nomenalism is a way of structuring ap- served emeralds have the property of pearances. being grue — for all emeralds have been The Structure of Appearance is a work observed before time t and have been in formal philosophy that is heavily influ- found to be green. Given the inductive enced by Carnap’s Aufbau (1928). Ob- principle set out above, we have induc- serving parallels with logical positivism, tive evidence that all emeralds are grue. Shottenkirk says that Goodman claims But the same evidence supports the con- Ressenyes Enrahonar. Quaderns de Filosofia 49, 2012 157 clusion that all emeralds are green. So by tions and coextensive terms in projec- the above principle, our observations tions by speakers in any community. provide reason to believe that an emerald Further, entrenchment is not sufficient not observed before t is both green and for projectibility. A projectible hypoth- blue. This is preposterous. Shottenkirk esis must also have known positive in- mischaracterizes the problem. She states: stances, no known negative instances, «Since evidence statements regarding all and some undetermined instances. the emeralds before t confirm that they Whether or not a given predicate like are all grue, they unfortunately confirm, «green» was projected in the past is de- in turn, both of the competing hypoth- pendent on the ways various linguistic eses, e.g., 1) that all emeralds are green communities used words. But whether a and 2) that all emeralds are blue» (84). predicate is projectible is not a matter of This is incorrect. The observation of community consensus. green emeralds does not confirm the hy- Shottenkirk intimates that the grue pothesis that all emeralds are blue — in- paradox is problematic for Goodman be- deed, it disproves it. If all that is required cause his nominalist framework does not for confirmation is conformity to the allow natural kinds. If this were so, the evidence, the observation confirms that paradox would not have had the monu- emeralds that have not been observed mental impact on epistemology that it before time t are blue. That in itself is did. Everyone concerned with induction problematic. or counterfactual reasoning has to take it Goodman argues that not all predi- seriously, not only nominalists. Recog- cates are projectible; so not all are suita- nizing natural kinds does not solve the ble for using in induction or projecting problem. Goodman’s challenge to realists from known to unknown cases. Predi- is: even if there are natural kinds, what cates like ‘green’ are projectible and justifies you in thinking that ‘green’, predicates like ‘grue’ are not. Although rather than ‘grue’ is one of them? all emeralds observed before t are grue, A further problem with Nominalism we cannot make inductive inferences and its Aftermath is that it mischaracter- from that fact to the conclusion that all izes Goodman’s epistemological stance. emeralds are grue. The critical question Shottenkirk states that Goodman «main- is what accounts for projectibility. tains a modified coherentism» (77). Al- Shottenkirk holds that Goodman’s though she admits that he is not strict answer is a form of social constructivism. coherentist, she holds that he simply al- «Predicates are entrenched because they tered a coherence account of knowledge. are in accordance with the practice of the This is not an accurate description. His- community» (85). This is incorrect for torically, epistemologies were character- several reasons. Goodman claims that a ized as foundationalist or coherentist. predicate is entrenched if it and its cog- Foundationalism maintains that knowl- nates have been projected far more often edge is grounded on beliefs whose cer- than any rivals it has. Non-projective tainty derives from experience or reason. uses of predicates are irrelevant. Because Coherentism maintains that knowledge he includes cognates, his analysis is not is grounded in a given belief’s function- dependent on any particular community. ing within a coherent system in which That ‘green’ is entrenched depends not each belief supports and is supported by only on the use of ‘green’ in projections the others in that system.
Recommended publications
  • On the Epistemological Significance of Aesthetic Values in Architectural Theory
    On the Epistemological Significance of Aesthetic Values in Architectural Theory by Ritu Bhatt Master of Architecture (1993) Kansas State University Bachelor of Architecture (1990) University of Roorkee, India Submitted to the Department of Architecture in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Architecture: History and Theory of Architecture at the T yTT Massachusetts Institute of Technology January, 2000 @ 2000 Ritu Bhatt. All rights reserved The author hereby grants to MIT permission to reproduce and to distribute publicly paper and electronic copies of this thesis document in whole or in part. Signature of Author...................................................................... Department of Architecture January 7, 2000 C ertified b . ... .................... .. tanrord A son ark Jarzo Professor of History and Assoc. Pro essor of History and Architecture Architecture Thesis Co- Supervisor Thesis Co- Supervisor Accepted by................................. V ... - ........ Stanford Anderson Chairman, Department Committee on Graduate Students Thesis Readers Professor Stanford Anderson Professor of History and Architecture Head, Department of Architecture, MIT Professor Mark Jarzombek Associate Professor of History and Architecture, MIT Professor Sibel Bozdogan Adjunct Professor, Graduate School of Design, Harvard University Professor Diane Ghirardo Professor of Architecture, University of Southern California Professor Satya P. Mohanty Professor of English, Cornell University Professor Catherine
    [Show full text]
  • A Critique of Nelson Goodman's Aesthetics: Music As Process
    PANDION: The Osprey Journal of Research & Ideas Volume 1 Number 1 Article 6 2020 A Critique of Nelson Goodman’s Aesthetics: Music As Process William S. Gilbert University of North Florida, [email protected] Faculty Mentor: Sarah Mattice, PhD, Associate Professor Department of Philosophy and Religious Studies This paper was a co-winner of the Philosophy Program's 2019-2020 Paper Prize. Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.unf.edu/pandion_unf Part of the Comparative Philosophy Commons, and the Esthetics Commons Recommended Citation Gilbert, William S. (2020) "A Critique of Nelson Goodman’s Aesthetics: Music As Process," PANDION: The Osprey Journal of Research and Ideas: Vol. 1 : No. 1 , Article 6. Available at: https://digitalcommons.unf.edu/pandion_unf/vol1/iss1/6 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Student Scholarship at UNF Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in PANDION: The Osprey Journal of Research & Ideas by an authorized administrator of UNF Digital Commons. For more information, please contact Digital Projects. © 2020 All Rights Reserved A Critique of Nelson Goodman’s Aesthetics: Music As Process Cover Page Footnote The advice and mentorship offered by Dr. Sarah Mattice was absolutely critical in not only the essays development but also my development as a student and thinker. Her feedback and generosity with time in meetings is something I am deeply grateful for. Dr. Jean Miller of Virginia Tech is also responsible for highly valuable suggestions for a much needed revision. I am very grateful for her advice. Finally I would like to thank Jason Simpson of the UNF Writing Center.
    [Show full text]
  • Nelson Goodman's Arguments Against Perspective: a Geometrical
    Branko Mitroviü Research Department of Architecture Nelson Goodman’s Arguments Against Unitec Institute of Technology Carrington Rd., Mt Albert Perspective: A Geometrical Analysis Auckland, NEW ZEALAND Presented at Nexus 2012: Relationships Between Architecture [email protected] and Mathematics, Milan, 11-14 June 2012 Keywords: Nelson Goodman, Abstract. Nelson Goodman’s highly influential book perspective theory, geometry of Languages of Art argued that that all visual experience is perspective, Ernst Gombrich, merely a cultural construct. In presenting his thesis Goodman Erwin Panofsky relied on a series of geometrical arguments intended to show that the geometrical construction of perspective does not rely on the geometry of light rays. In this article I analyze the geometrical validity of Goodman's arguments. Introduction For the past fifty years few books by English-speaking philosophers have exercised a greater influence on art- and architectural history than Nelson Goodman’s Languages of Art [1968]. This book was an important contribution to the rise of cultural relativism that subsequently came to dominate the English-speaking humanities for decades. Goodman adopted the view (previously advocated by Ernst Gombrich in his book Art and Illusion [1960]) that “there is no innocent eye” and that the totality of an individual’s perception is predetermined by and a result of that person’s conceptual framework.1 Unlike Gombrich, however, Goodman inferred that, since our conceptual frameworks derive from the cultures we live in, all we can know and perceive is a result of our cultural background; he consequently argued that reality itself was but a cultural construct.2 According to this view, there are no facts that constitute the world independent of human cognitive apparatus.
    [Show full text]
  • How to Benacerraf a Goodman-Lewis
    How to Benacerraf a Goodman-Lewis This paper offers a limited defense of the thesis Nelson Goodman labels “nominalism,” according to which there are no distinct entities constructed from the same basic entities. Goodmanian nominalism-- “gnominalism,” for short—bears an uncertain relation to more familiar nominalist theses, but, according to Goodman, anti-gnominalism is simply “incomprehensible.” Unfortunately, as many commentators have noted, Goodman offers frustratingly little in the way of arguments for gnominalism. The present reassessment of gnominalism argues that Goodman is right to claim that theories violating gnominalism incur a distinctive theoretical vice. At the same time, the glaring lack of arguments for gnominalism indicate that something has gone badly wrong. Roughly speaking, Goodman’s support for gnominalism mistakes the symptom for the disease. This is because the vice of anti-gnominalist theories is that they are uniformly susceptible to variations on the Non-Uniqueness Problem that Paul Benacerraf presents for set- theoretic reductions. Gnominalism can therefore be motivated as a response to the Non-Uniqueness Problem. For this reason, would-be gnominalists like David Lewis are best served to argue against contested posits by showing these posits to yield Non-Uniqueness Problems given the existence of distinct entities constructed from the basic entities. To this end, after explaining gnominalism and its connection to the Non-Uniqueness Problem, I discuss how Lewis’ version of gnominalism departs from Goodman’s own. I then argue that a Non-Uniqueness Problem arises for those who posit structural universals—the leading target of Lewis’ gnominalism. (Word Count: 4284) §1. Introduction Two conceptions of nominalism are commonly distinguished when discussing debates between nominalists and platonists.1 The first kind of nominalism denies the existence of universals and holds, instead, that all entities are particulars rather than general entities like universals.
    [Show full text]
  • Nelson Goodman Remembered Curtis Carter Marquette University, [email protected]
    Marquette University e-Publications@Marquette Philosophy Faculty Research and Publications Philosophy, Department of 1-1-1999 Nelson Goodman Remembered Curtis Carter Marquette University, [email protected] Published version. Aesthetics On-Line (1999). Permalink. © 1999 Curtis Carter. Used with permission. Nelson Goodman Remembered Curtis Carter The American philosopher Nelson Goodman died on November 25, 1998, in Needham, Massachusetts, at the age of 92. He was buried in a family grave site in Everett, Massachusetts. His wife, Katharine Sturgis Goodman, preceded him in death in 1996. Born on August 7, 1906 in Sommerville, Massachusetts, Goodman became a leading proponent of analytic philosophy in the United States and his theories are now studied throughout the world. Goodman was a Professor of Philosophy at Harvard University from 1968-1977. Previously he served as Harry Austryn Wolfson Professor of Philosophy at Brandeis University from 1964-67, Professor of Philosophy from 1951-1964 and Associate Professor from 1946- 1951 at the University of Pennsylvania, and Instructor in Philosophy at Tufts College, 1944- 1945. Prior to these appointments Goodman was Director of the Walker-Goodman Art Gallery in Boston from 1929 to 1941. From 1942 to 1945 he performed military service in the United States Army. He received his B.S. in 1928 (Phi Beta Kappa, Magna cum laude) and his Ph.D. in 1941, both from Harvard University. Goodman’s interests ranged from philosophy to collecting art. Within philosophy, Goodman’s writing and teaching were
    [Show full text]
  • John Cage, Gilles Deleuze, and the Idea of Sound Iain
    John Cage, Gilles Deleuze, and the Idea of Sound Iain Campbell [draft only, final version published in parallax, 23:3, 361-378, DOI:10.1080/13534645.2017.1343785] Across John Cage’s writings there is one moment to which he would often return, posing it as a turning point, a kind of singular epiphany in his thought and work. This is his famous visit to an anechoic chamber, and the consequent ‘discovery’ of his concept of silence. Describing his visit to the chamber, an environment designed to have as little acoustic resonance as possible and as such to be as silent as possible, Cage recounts hearing two sounds, one low and one high. Asking the engineer what these sounds were, Cage was told that the former was the sound of his blood in circulation, the latter his nervous system in operation. What Cage takes from this is that there can be no genuine silence, that ‘until I die there will be sounds’.1 This in turn entails a conception of sound wherein it is not defined simply by its analytical characteristics, but also by how it necessarily exceeds intentionality, of both composer and of listener. This is the basis for Cage’s often-repeated but obscure claim that the function of art is to ‘imitate Nature in her manner of operation’,2 and by extension the other oft-repeated Cagean mantra of ‘let[ting] sounds be themselves’3 – two cornerstones of an understanding of art in which the certainty of a creative or observational standpoint cannot serve as its foundation.
    [Show full text]
  • The Ontology of Technique As Explored Through the Early Work of Peter Eisenman
    On the (im)Possibility of Reading: The Ontology of Technique as Explored through the Early Work of Peter Eisenman The significance of the final form resides in its capacity to reveal its own origins. — Peter Eisenman ‘’The Futility of Objects” CHARLES CRAWFORD INTRODUCTION NewSchool of Architecture + Design Can a form in some manner “communicate” to a viewer the “intent” of its cre- ator? In the 1970’s and 1980’s many notable figures explored this question, the question Jorge Silvetti once referred to as “the problem of communication.” Aldo Rossi proposed a language of reductivist purity; Michael Graves a return to the familiar language of classicism; Robert Venturi and Denise Scott Brown a version of Populism; and Peter Eisenman proposed an experiment in pure syntax, devoid of cultural reference. This paper explores issues of ontology and technique and, hopefully, in that pro- cess, suggests a path by which we might connect both to tectonics. With his early work, most notably the houses, the CSULB Student Center and the Wexner Center, Peter Eisenman conducted an experiment in communication, attempting to produce architecture of linguistic structuralism. This attempt to incorporate Chomsky’s theory of syntax into a language of art possessed an inter- nal codification, which it was hoped would aide the viewer in “deconstructing” the process of composition. As Jeffery Kipnis writes, however, in “An Architecture Unbound:” Rather than ‘exposing’ an essential structure of (all) architectural possibility in an unambiguously accessible announcement of purely formal intentions, the suc- cess of the work, its architectural potency, seemed, paradoxically, to depend on ambiguity, on a deflection of readable intent.
    [Show full text]
  • Print This Article
    Aesthetic Experience, Mimesis and Testimony Roger W. H. Savage University of California Los Angeles Abstract In this article, I relate the demand that Paul Ricœur suggests mimesis places on the way we think about truth to the idea that the work of art is a model for thinking about testimony. By attributing a work’s epoché of reality to the work of imagination, I resolve the impasse that arises from attributing music, literature, and art’s distance from the real to their social emancipation. Examining the conjunction, in aesthetic experience, of the communicability and the exemplarity of a work reveals how Ricœur’s definition of mimesis as refiguration relates to the “rule” that the work summons. This “rule” constitutes the solution to a problem or question for which the work is the answer. In conclusion, as a model for thinking about testimony, the claims that works make have a counterpart in the injunctions that issue from exemplary moral and political acts. Keywords: Aesthetic experience, Mimesis, Judgment, Testimony Résumé Dans cet article, j’établis un lien entre l’exigence que, selon Paul Ricœur,la mimèsis place dans notre façon de penser la vérité, et l’idée que l’œuvre d’art est un modèle pour penser le témoignage. Appliquant l’époché de la réalité à l’oeuvre d’imagination, j’évite l’impasse qui se dresse lorsqu’on attribue la musique, la littérature et la distance artistique du réel à leur émancipation sociale. L’étude de la conjonction du caractère communicable et exemplaire d’une œuvre – dans l’expérience esthétique - met en lumière la relation que la définition par Ricœur de la mimésis comme refiguration établit avec la “règle” que l’œuvre convoque.
    [Show full text]
  • On Freeing Aesthetic Emotions
    Inside-Out or Outside-In? On Freeing Aesthetic Emotions Gerald Moshammer and Barbara Ekamp Introduction In their seminal Dialectic of Enlightenment, Max Horkheimer and Theodor W. Adorno drastically portray the scientific usurpation of the human sphere: That they [the behaviorists] apply to human beings the same formulae and results which they wring without restraint from defenseless animals in their abominable physiological laboratories, proclaims the difference in an especially subtle way. The conclusion they draw from the mutilated animal bodies applies, not to animals in freedom, but to human beings today. By mistreating animals they announce that they, and only they in the whole of creation, function voluntarily in the same mechanical blind, automatic way as the twitching movements of the bound victims made use of by the expert.1 Immanuel Kant famously defined the Enlightenment as emancipation from superstition. He argued in the name of science, that is, natural laws. Yet, against the backdrop of his diagnosis, Kant equally undertook an immense dialectic effort to expose ethical reasoning and aesthetic experience as autonomous islands in the sea of blind natural forces. The Neo-Marxists Adorno and Horkheimer do not subscribe to such a sharp contrast between nature and deontic rationality or aesthetic imagination. They, however, follow Kant in not selling out to science every gram of the human soul. They note, “art, morality, and sublime love are masks of nature, in which nature reappears transformed and becomes expressive as its own antithesis. Through its masks it acquires the gift of speech; in its distortion it manifests its essence; beauty is the serpent which displays the wound where once the fang was implanted.”2 The behaviorists, on the contrary, are Gerald Moshammer is an Assistant Professor and Barbara Ekamp a Lecturer at Mahidol University International College, Thailand.
    [Show full text]
  • British Idealist Aesthetics, Collingwood, Wollheim, and the Origins of Analytic Aesthetics
    Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication Volume 4 200 YEARS OF ANALYTICAL PHILOSOPHY Article 12 2008 British Idealist Aesthetics, Collingwood, Wollheim, And The Origins Of Analytic Aesthetics Chinatsu Kobayashi Université du Québec à Montréal Follow this and additional works at: https://newprairiepress.org/biyclc This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 4.0 License. Recommended Citation Kobayashi, Chinatsu (2008) "British Idealist Aesthetics, Collingwood, Wollheim, And The Origins Of Analytic Aesthetics," Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication: Vol. 4. https://doi.org/10.4148/biyclc.v4i0.136 This Proceeding of the Symposium for Cognition, Logic and Communication is brought to you for free and open access by the Conferences at New Prairie Press. It has been accepted for inclusion in Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication by an authorized administrator of New Prairie Press. For more information, please contact [email protected]. British Idealist Aesthetics 2 The Baltic International Yearbook of two, Bernard Bosanquet and Robin Collingwood appear, therefore, to Cognition, Logic and Communication be the only idealist aestheticians of significance in the first half of the twentieth century.4 Of the two, Collingwood knew more about art5 and August 2009 Volume 4: 200 Years of Analytical Philosophy was by far more original, as he produced a philosophy of art that truly pages 1-40 DOI: 10.4148/biyclc.v4i0.136 engaged with the artistic preoccupations of his days in The Principles of Art (Collingwood 1938). Among the ‘realists’, the topic was hardly more popular: only Samuel Alexander and E.
    [Show full text]
  • Nelson Goodman's 'Theory of Symbols': an Exposition and Critique
    Nelson Goodman's 'Theory of Symbols': an Exposition and Critique Evan Wm. Cameron Professor Emeritus Senior Scholar in Screenwriting Graduate Programmes, Film & Video and Philosophy York University [Presented on 13 February 1985 to the 'Media, Mind and Society' Seminar of David R. Olson, Co-Director of the McLuhan Program in Culture and Technology, University of Toronto, Toronto, Ontario. (Original notes in outline form, amended only as needed to permit comprehension by readers.) Nelson Goodman's 'Theory of Symbols': an Exposition and Critique1 1. Opening remarks: 2. Novel status of Goodman among philosophical peers: A. Philosophers are specialists (philosophers of science, for example, or logicians, aestheticians, philosophers of language, philosophers of mathematics and so on); yet Goodman has published in journals ranging from the Journal of Symbolic Logic to the Journal of Aesthetics; has had reviews of his work in specialized journals of science, mathematics, art and critical studies; and has been invited to give the John Locke lectures at Oxford and the 1st Kant lectures at Stanford. B. Peers are specialists; proceed as if Goodman had not lived, thought or written; yet the best of them admit that their only genuine antagonist is Goodman. How so? During the early part of his career, Goodman managed to construct within many parts of philosophy contradictions and paradoxes that not only rendered all current work suspect but seemed to promise that all future work would be suspect as well. The only choice, in many of these fields, was to plow ahead as if he didn't exist, or to stop working! 3. Examples of prior (and devastating) critical work: A.
    [Show full text]
  • The Closure of Experience Kant, Goodman, and the Aesthetic Approach Hanno Birken-Bertsch
    The closure of experience Kant, Goodman, and the aesthetic approach Hanno Birken-Bertsch ant ends traditional epistemology and founds the aesthetic approach. - K One can say that epistemology is supposed to investigate how an appearance comes about. »Appearance« is one of the key words in Kant. A table, for example, is an appearance for you and me. Epistemology asks how it comes about that we see this table. The point is that one cannot explain the table by something that is not, like the table, an appearance. This insight is the end of epistemology and the beginning of aesthetics. Or, to avoid confusion, it is better to speak of »the aesthetic approach«, although I am not altogether satisfied with this phrase. For the aesthetic approach, our world consists of experience. Our task is to find out what follows from this starting point. 1. K ant’s aesthetics We are focusing on the first critique, the Critique o f Pure Reason, in the first edition, which was published in 1781. This book is - among other things - an intersection of two approaches, the epistemological and the aesthetic. Two ways of theorizing cross in the book, and their models of thought are intertwined. Kant inherits epistemology and founds the aesthetic approach. The relevant text for both is a chapter in the Critique o f Pure Reason, entitled »Transcendental Aesthetics«. Why is it called »Aesthetics«? In ancient Greek aisthesis means perception, and »Aesthetics« is thus concerned with what relates to aisthesis. Following the idea of the word Kant deals with perception and sensibility. In a footnote he even complains about those who use the word »aesthetics« to refer to a philosophy of art or the beautiful.
    [Show full text]