Paradoxes (Trends in Logic

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Paradoxes (Trends in Logic Trends in Logic Volume 31 For further volumes: http://www.springer.com/series/6645 TRENDS IN LOGIC Studia Logica Library VOLUME 31 Managing Editor Ryszard Wójcicki, Institute of Philosophy and Sociology, Polish Academy of Sciences, Warsaw, Poland Editors Wieslaw Dziobiak, University of Puerto Rico at Mayagüez, USA Melvin Fitting, City University of New York, USA Vincent F. Hendricks, Department of Philosophy and Science Studies, Roskilde University, Denmark Daniele Mundici, Department of Mathematics ‘‘Ulisse Dini’’, University of Florence, Italy Ewa Orłowska, National Institute of Telecommunications, Warsaw, Poland Krister Segerberg, Department of Philosophy, Uppsala University, Sweden Heinrich Wansing, Institute of Philosophy, Dresden University of Technology, Germany SCOPE OF THE SERIES Trends in Logic is a bookseries covering essentially the same area as the journal Studia Logica – that is, contemporary formal logic and its applications and relations to other disciplines. These include artificial intelligence, informatics, cognitive science, philosophy of science, and the philosophy of language. However, this list is not exhaustive, moreover, the range of applications, comparisons and sources of inspiration is open and evolves over time. Volume Editor Heinrich Wansing Piotr Łukowski Paradoxes 123 Piotr Łukowski Department of Cognitive Science University of Łódz´ Smugowa 10/12 91-433 Łódz´ Poland e-mail: [email protected] Translated by Marek Gensler ISBN 978-94-007-1475-5 e-ISBN 978-94-007-1476-2 DOI 10.1007/978-94-007-1476-2 Springer Dordrecht Heidelberg London New York Ó Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2011 No part of this work may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, microfilming, recording or otherwise, without written permission from the Publisher, with the exception of any material supplied specifically for the purpose of being entered and executed on a computer system, for exclusive use by the purchaser of the work. Cover design: eStudio Calamar, Berlin/Figueres Printed on acid-free paper Springer is part of Springer Science+Business Media (www.springer.com) To my Parents, Maria and Zdzisław Contents 1 Introduction ........................................ 1 References . 3 2 Paradoxes of Wrong Intuition ........................... 5 2.1 Bottle Imp Paradox (Stevenson’s Bottle), or the Unintuitive Character of a Conclusion Following a Sufficient Multiplication of a Simple Reasoning . 5 2.2 Newcomb’s Paradox, or the Unintuitive Character of a Conclusion Drawn from Premises with Non-intuitive Assumption . 7 2.3 Paradox of Common Birthday, or the Unintuitive Character of Some Results in Probability Calculus. 11 2.4 Paradox of Approximation and Paradox of the Equator, or the Unintuitive Character of Some Results in Euclidean Geometry. 13 2.5 Horses’ Paradox, or the Intuitive Character of an Erroneous Application of Mathematical Induction. 15 2.6 Hempel’s Paradox (Raven, Confirmation), or the Unintuitive Character of Some Inductive Reasoning Results . 16 2.7 Paradoxes of Infinity, or Unintuitive Character of Some Results Obtained in Set Theory . 19 2.7.1 Aristotelian Circles Paradox, or the Definition of an Infinite Set. 19 2.7.2 Holy Trinity Paradox, or Application of the Definition of Infinite Set in Theology. 27 2.8 Fitch’s Paradox, or the Conflict of Two Intuitions. 32 References . 35 3 Paradoxes of Ambiguity ................................ 37 3.1 Protagoras’ (Law Teacher’s) Paradox. 37 3.2 Electra’s (the Veiled One’s) Paradox and Other Equivocations. 48 vii viii Contents 3.3 The Horny One’s Paradox . 51 3.4 Nameless Club Paradox . 52 3.5 Paradox of a Stone, or an Attempt at Disproving God’s Omnipotence . 54 References . 73 4 Paradoxes of Self-Reference ............................. 75 4.1 Möbius Ribbon and Klein Bottle, or Self-Reference in Mathematics . 75 4.2 Great Semantical Paradoxes . 80 4.2.1 Liar Antinomy . 80 4.2.2 Buridan’s Paradox. 106 4.2.3 Generalized Form of Liar Antinomy . 108 4.2.4 Curry’s Paradox . 109 4.3 Other Semantic Paradoxes . 110 4.3.1 Barber’s Antinomy . 111 4.3.2 Richard’s and Berry’s Antinomies. 113 4.3.3 Grelling’s Antinomy (Vox Non Appellans Se) . 118 4.4 Unexpected Examination (Hangman’s) Paradox, or Self-Reflexive Reasoning . 119 4.5 Crocodile’s Paradox, or Baron Münchhausen Fallacy. 124 References . 128 5 Ontological Paradoxes ................................. 131 5.1 Paradoxes of Difference - Paradox of a Heap . 131 5.1.1 What is Vagueness? . 141 5.1.2 Proposals Substituting Preciseness for Vagueness . 151 5.1.3 Vagueness Respecting Proposals. 166 5.2 Paradoxes of Change . 171 5.2.1 Paradox of the Moment of Death (Change of State Paradox) . 171 5.2.2 Paradoxes of Identity. 172 5.2.3 The Paradoxes of Motion. 175 5.3 Diagnosis of Paradoxes of Vagueness and Change . 181 References . 185 Names Index ........................................... 189 Subject Index .......................................... 193 Chapter 1 Introduction Because of their attractive intellectual form, it is tempting to treat paradoxes lightly, as if they were only an intellectual entertainment. Admittedly, when presented in interesting and non-trivial way, they can offer an attractive diversion at a party. Reducing them to entertainment only, however, is disrespectful not only to their authors but also to ourselves, since paradoxes should be treated as alarm signals informing of danger resulting from some errors in our thinking. This absolutely serious function which they play ought to be recognized especially by people who are interested in logic and philosophy. It is for this reason that para- doxes deserve not only attention but also serious consideration of the conclusions following from them. Regrettably, it is not so. One can still encounter logical and, especially, philosophical ideas, which seem to ignore the existence of paradoxical arguments, or at best question the sense of dealing with them. Many philosophical ideas can survive only because they disregard completely such paradoxes as sorites, paradoxes of change, motion or identity. If treated seriously, the conclu- sions following from those paradoxes could be death blows to a number of metaphysical or ontological ideas. Paradox is a thought construction, which leads to an unexpected contradiction.1 The essence of this definition lies in the word ‘‘unexpected’’. We often reach contradictions, but not every such situation is seen as paradoxical. True, a contra- diction understood as a conjunction of two propositions/sentences/statements/ claims, of which one is the negation of the other, is something that we should reject. But every such conjunction is paradoxical for us: if I consciously accept some P together with non-P, I should not be surprised that I have to accept a contradiction P and non-P. A paradox appears only when we get a contradiction in spite of: • Using logically correct rules of inference • Being convinced that we formulated our thoughts precisely • Certitude that the opinions we have so far are rational. 1 For stylistic reasons, the word ‘‘paradox’’ will be sometimes replaced by the word ‘‘dilemma’’ in order to avoid repetitions. P. Łukowski, Paradoxes, Trends in Logic, 31, 1 DOI: 10.1007/978-94-007-1476-2_1, Ó Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2011 2 1 Introduction Then, indeed, the contradiction which appears is unexpected, since the procedure applied in our reasoning was devised specially to prevent it. Logical checks were functioning and yet we obtained a contradiction, a very serious error. By tradition, a paradox (gr. paqadonof, paradoxos) is an opinion, conclusion etc., which is contrary to common belief. According to Aristotle (384–322 BC), a statement paradoxical when it is contrary to the belief of a group of people. One and the same opinion can be a paradox for one group of people but not for another. The word ‘‘infinity’’ is often used in its every day sense of something without an end, something inexhaustible. For a common man, the mathematical understanding of infinity and its properties would be a surprise or even something unbelievable. Yet that knowledge is nothing strange for a person with mathematical education. In a narrower sense, a paradox is an antinomy (Greek amsimolia, antinomia; anti— against, molof, nomos—law). We shall call a reasoning antinomic when, despite its logically correct form, it leads to a contradiction: P and non-P. In a still narrower sense, an antinomy is a logically correct reasoning, which justifies an equivalence: P if and only if non-P. It is in this sense that antinomy is understood most often. A special kind of paradoxes are sophisms (Greek: rouirla, sophisma—false conclusion). Aristotle uses his name for every argument, which seems to be correct but is not. Usually, the word ‘‘sophism’’ is understood to include an intention to deceive the listener. For this reason, one distinguishes a paralogism (Greek: paqakocirlof, paralogismos—false conclusion), which is an incorrect reasoning without an intention to deceive. A person, who presents such a reasonings, is either unaware that it is erroneous or knows that it is wrong but treats the presentation as a joke or a didactic trick to be explained soon. Classification of paradoxes is rather difficult, since it is not clear according to which criteria it should be done. In this book, we have accepted the essence of a paradox as the fundament of classification. If the essence of a paradox is an error of ambiguity, it is classified as a paradox ambiguity, regardless of the character of its narration. This can be manifestly seen in the case of such paradoxes as Newcomb’s and Protagoras’s. Accordingly, the book has four chapters. The first one analyzes those paradoxes, which result from a clash between a logically correct reasoning and our previously accepted opinions. Here we can place e.g., Georg Cantor’s set theory paradoxes, but because of their strictly mathematical character they will not be discussed in this book.
Recommended publications
  • The P–T Probability Framework for Semantic Communication, Falsification, Confirmation, and Bayesian Reasoning
    philosophies Article The P–T Probability Framework for Semantic Communication, Falsification, Confirmation, and Bayesian Reasoning Chenguang Lu School of Computer Engineering and Applied Mathematics, Changsha University, Changsha 410003, China; [email protected] Received: 8 July 2020; Accepted: 16 September 2020; Published: 2 October 2020 Abstract: Many researchers want to unify probability and logic by defining logical probability or probabilistic logic reasonably. This paper tries to unify statistics and logic so that we can use both statistical probability and logical probability at the same time. For this purpose, this paper proposes the P–T probability framework, which is assembled with Shannon’s statistical probability framework for communication, Kolmogorov’s probability axioms for logical probability, and Zadeh’s membership functions used as truth functions. Two kinds of probabilities are connected by an extended Bayes’ theorem, with which we can convert a likelihood function and a truth function from one to another. Hence, we can train truth functions (in logic) by sampling distributions (in statistics). This probability framework was developed in the author’s long-term studies on semantic information, statistical learning, and color vision. This paper first proposes the P–T probability framework and explains different probabilities in it by its applications to semantic information theory. Then, this framework and the semantic information methods are applied to statistical learning, statistical mechanics, hypothesis evaluation (including falsification), confirmation, and Bayesian reasoning. Theoretical applications illustrate the reasonability and practicability of this framework. This framework is helpful for interpretable AI. To interpret neural networks, we need further study. Keywords: statistical probability; logical probability; semantic information; rate-distortion; Boltzmann distribution; falsification; verisimilitude; confirmation measure; Raven Paradox; Bayesian reasoning 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Paradoxes Situations That Seems to Defy Intuition
    Paradoxes Situations that seems to defy intuition PDF generated using the open source mwlib toolkit. See http://code.pediapress.com/ for more information. PDF generated at: Tue, 08 Jul 2014 07:26:17 UTC Contents Articles Introduction 1 Paradox 1 List of paradoxes 4 Paradoxical laughter 16 Decision theory 17 Abilene paradox 17 Chainstore paradox 19 Exchange paradox 22 Kavka's toxin puzzle 34 Necktie paradox 36 Economy 38 Allais paradox 38 Arrow's impossibility theorem 41 Bertrand paradox 52 Demographic-economic paradox 53 Dollar auction 56 Downs–Thomson paradox 57 Easterlin paradox 58 Ellsberg paradox 59 Green paradox 62 Icarus paradox 65 Jevons paradox 65 Leontief paradox 70 Lucas paradox 71 Metzler paradox 72 Paradox of thrift 73 Paradox of value 77 Productivity paradox 80 St. Petersburg paradox 85 Logic 92 All horses are the same color 92 Barbershop paradox 93 Carroll's paradox 96 Crocodile Dilemma 97 Drinker paradox 98 Infinite regress 101 Lottery paradox 102 Paradoxes of material implication 104 Raven paradox 107 Unexpected hanging paradox 119 What the Tortoise Said to Achilles 123 Mathematics 127 Accuracy paradox 127 Apportionment paradox 129 Banach–Tarski paradox 131 Berkson's paradox 139 Bertrand's box paradox 141 Bertrand paradox 146 Birthday problem 149 Borel–Kolmogorov paradox 163 Boy or Girl paradox 166 Burali-Forti paradox 172 Cantor's paradox 173 Coastline paradox 174 Cramer's paradox 178 Elevator paradox 179 False positive paradox 181 Gabriel's Horn 184 Galileo's paradox 187 Gambler's fallacy 188 Gödel's incompleteness theorems
    [Show full text]
  • A Philosophical Treatise of Universal Induction
    Entropy 2011, 13, 1076-1136; doi:10.3390/e13061076 OPEN ACCESS entropy ISSN 1099-4300 www.mdpi.com/journal/entropy Article A Philosophical Treatise of Universal Induction Samuel Rathmanner and Marcus Hutter ? Research School of Computer Science, Australian National University, Corner of North and Daley Road, Canberra ACT 0200, Australia ? Author to whom correspondence should be addressed; E-Mail: [email protected]. Received: 20 April 2011; in revised form: 24 May 2011 / Accepted: 27 May 2011 / Published: 3 June 2011 Abstract: Understanding inductive reasoning is a problem that has engaged mankind for thousands of years. This problem is relevant to a wide range of fields and is integral to the philosophy of science. It has been tackled by many great minds ranging from philosophers to scientists to mathematicians, and more recently computer scientists. In this article we argue the case for Solomonoff Induction, a formal inductive framework which combines algorithmic information theory with the Bayesian framework. Although it achieves excellent theoretical results and is based on solid philosophical foundations, the requisite technical knowledge necessary for understanding this framework has caused it to remain largely unknown and unappreciated in the wider scientific community. The main contribution of this article is to convey Solomonoff induction and its related concepts in a generally accessible form with the aim of bridging this current technical gap. In the process we examine the major historical contributions that have led to the formulation of Solomonoff Induction as well as criticisms of Solomonoff and induction in general. In particular we examine how Solomonoff induction addresses many issues that have plagued other inductive systems, such as the black ravens paradox and the confirmation problem, and compare this approach with other recent approaches.
    [Show full text]
  • Hempel and the Paradoxes of Confirmation
    HEMPEL AND THE PARADOXES OF CONFIRMATION Jan Sprenger 1 TOWARDS A LOGIC OF CONFIRMATION The beginning of modern philosophy of science is generally associated with the label of logical empiricism , in particular with the members of the Vienna Circle. Some of them, as Frank, Hahn and Neurath, were themselves scientists, others, as Carnap and Schlick, were philosophers, but deeply impressed by the scientific revolutions at the beginning of the 20th century. All of them were unified in ad- miration for the systematicity and enduring success of science. This affected their philosophical views and led to a sharp break with the “metaphysical” philosophical tradition and to a re-invention of empiricist epistemology with a strong empha- sis on science, our best source of high-level knowledge. Indeed, the members of the Vienna Circle were scientifically trained and used to the scientific method of test and observation. For them, metaphysical claims were neither verifiable nor falsifiable through empirical methods, and therefore neither true nor false, but meaningless. Proper philosophical analysis had to separate senseless (metaphysi- cal) from meaningful (empirical) claims and to investigate our most reliable source of knowledge: science. 1 The latter task included the development of formal frameworks for discovering the logic of scientific method and progress. Rudolf Carnap, who devoted much of his work to this task, was in fact one of the most influential figures of the Vienna Circle. In 1930, Carnap and the Berlin philosopher Hans Reichenbach took over the journal ‘Annalen der Philosophie’ and renamed it ‘Erkenntnis’. Under that name, it became a major publication organ for the works of the logical empiri- cists.
    [Show full text]
  • List of Paradoxes 1 List of Paradoxes
    List of paradoxes 1 List of paradoxes This is a list of paradoxes, grouped thematically. The grouping is approximate: Paradoxes may fit into more than one category. Because of varying definitions of the term paradox, some of the following are not considered to be paradoxes by everyone. This list collects only those instances that have been termed paradox by at least one source and which have their own article. Although considered paradoxes, some of these are based on fallacious reasoning, or incomplete/faulty analysis. Logic • Barbershop paradox: The supposition that if one of two simultaneous assumptions leads to a contradiction, the other assumption is also disproved leads to paradoxical consequences. • What the Tortoise Said to Achilles "Whatever Logic is good enough to tell me is worth writing down...," also known as Carroll's paradox, not to be confused with the physical paradox of the same name. • Crocodile Dilemma: If a crocodile steals a child and promises its return if the father can correctly guess what the crocodile will do, how should the crocodile respond in the case that the father guesses that the child will not be returned? • Catch-22 (logic): In need of something which can only be had by not being in need of it. • Drinker paradox: In any pub there is a customer such that, if he or she drinks, everybody in the pub drinks. • Paradox of entailment: Inconsistent premises always make an argument valid. • Horse paradox: All horses are the same color. • Lottery paradox: There is one winning ticket in a large lottery. It is reasonable to believe of a particular lottery ticket that it is not the winning ticket, since the probability that it is the winner is so very small, but it is not reasonable to believe that no lottery ticket will win.
    [Show full text]
  • SOCIALLY SITUATING MORAL KNOWLEDGE by ANNALEIGH ELIZABETH CURTIS B.A., Washburn University, 2008 M.A., University of Colorado at Boulder, 2012
    SOCIALLY SITUATING MORAL KNOWLEDGE by ANNALEIGH ELIZABETH CURTIS B.A., Washburn University, 2008 M.A., University of Colorado at Boulder, 2012 A thesis submitted to the Faculty of the Graduate School of the University of Colorado in partial fulfillment of the requirement for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy 2013 This thesis entitled: Socially Situating Moral Knowledge written by Annaleigh Elizabeth Curtis has been approved for the Department of Philosophy (Alison Jaggar) (Adam Hosein) (Graham Oddie) (Alastair Norcross) (Celeste Montoya) Date The final copy of this thesis has been examined by the signatories, and we find that both the content and the form meet acceptable presentation standards of scholarly work in the above mentioned discipline. iii Curtis, Annaleigh Elizabeth (Ph.D. Philosophy) Socially Situating Moral Knowledge Thesis directed by Professor Alison M. Jaggar I seek to provide a partial answer to this question: what is epistemically required of us as socially situated moral agents? We are familiar with the idea that each of us, as moral agents, has a set of moral obligations—to be kind, to be fair, to do good, or whatever. We are also familiar with the idea that each of us, as epistemic agents, has a set of epistemic obligations—to believe truly, to follow our evidence, to engage in inquiry, or whatever. But moral agents also have epistemic obligations that arise specifically out of the challenge of figuring out what is morally required. I argue that several commonly held accounts of our epistemic obligations as moral agents are seriously flawed; they get the methodological question wrong, perhaps at the expense of the practical question.
    [Show full text]
  • Hempel's Raven Paradox, Hume's Problem of Induction, Goodman's
    Research Report KSTS/RR-19/002 September 12, 2019 (Revised November 1, 2019) Hempel’s raven paradox, Hume’s problem of induction, Goodman’s grue paradox, Peirce’s abduction, Flagpole problem are clarified in quantum language by Shiro Ishikawa Shiro Ishikawa Department of Mathematics Keio University Department of Mathematics Faculty of Science and Technology Keio University c 2019 KSTS 3-14-1 Hiyoshi, Kohoku-ku, Yokohama, 223-8522 Japan KSTS/RR-19/002 September 12, 2019 (Revised November 1, 2019) Hempel's raven paradox, Hume's problem of induction, Goodman's grue paradox, Peirce's abduction, Flagpole problem are clarified in quantum language Shiro Ishikawa *1 Abstract Recently we proposed \quantum language" (or, \the linguistic Copenhagen interpretation of quantum me- chanics", \measurement theory") as the language of science. This theory asserts the probabilistic inter- pretation of science (= the linguistic quantum mechanical worldview), which is a kind of mathematical generalization of Born's probabilistic interpretation of quantum mechanics. In this preprint, we consider the most fundamental problems in philosophy of science such as Hempel's raven paradox, Hume's problem of induction, Goodman's grue paradox, Peirce's abduction, flagpole problem, which are closely related to measurement. We believe that these problems can never be solved without the basic theory of science with axioms. Since our worldview has the axiom concerning measurement, these problems can be solved easily. Hence there is a reason to assert that quantum language gives the mathematical foundations to science.*2 Contents 1 Introduction 1 2 Review: Quantum language (= Measurement theory (=MT) ) 2 3 Hempel's raven paradox in the linguistic quantum mechanical worldview 12 4 Hume's problem of induction 19 5 The measurement theoretical representation of abduction 23 6 Flagpole problem 25 7 Conclusion; To do science is to describe phenomena by quantum language 27 1 Introduction This preprint is prepared in order to reconsider ref.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy of Science for Scientists: the Probabilistic Interpretation of Science
    Journal of Quantum Information Science, 2019, 9, 123-154 https://www.scirp.org/journal/jqis ISSN Online: 2162-576X ISSN Print: 2162-5751 Philosophy of Science for Scientists: The Probabilistic Interpretation of Science Shiro Ishikawa Department of Mathematics, Faculty of Science and Technology, Keio University, Yokohama, Japan How to cite this paper: Ishikawa, S. (2019) Abstract Philosophy of Science for Scientists: The Probabilistic Interpretation of Science. Recently we proposed “quantum language” (or, “the linguistic Copenhagen Journal of Quantum Information Science, interpretation of quantum mechanics”, “measurement theory”) as the lan- 9, 123-154. guage of science. This theory asserts the probabilistic interpretation of science https://doi.org/10.4236/jqis.2019.93007 (=the linguistic quantum mechanical worldview), which is a kind of mathe- Received: August 27, 2019 matical generalization of Born’s probabilistic interpretation of quantum me- Accepted: September 24, 2019 chanics. In this paper, we consider the most fundamental problems in phi- Published: September 27, 2019 losophy of science such as Hempel’s raven paradox, Hume’s problem of in- Copyright © 2019 by author(s) and duction, Goodman’s grue paradox, Peirce’s abduction, flagpole problem, Scientific Research Publishing Inc. which are closely related to measurement. We believe that these problems can This work is licensed under the Creative never be solved without the basic theory of science with axioms. Since our Commons Attribution International worldview (=quantum language) has the axiom concerning measurement, License (CC BY 4.0). http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/ these problems can be solved easily. Thus we believe that quantum language Open Access is the central theory in philosophy of science.
    [Show full text]
  • The Raven Is Grue: on the Equivalence of Goodman's And
    On the Equivalence of Goodman’s and Hempel’s Paradoxes by Kenneth Boyce DRAFT Nevertheless, the difficulty is often slighted because on the surface there seem to be easy ways of dealing with it. Sometimes, for example, the problem is thought to be much like the paradox of the ravens (Nelson Goodman, Fact, Fiction and Forecast, p. 75) Abstract: Historically, Nelson Goodman’s paradox involving the predicates ‘grue’ and ‘bleen’ has been taken to furnish a serious blow to Carl Hempel’s theory of confirmation in particular and to purely formal theories of confirmation in general. In this paper, I argue that Goodman’s paradox is no more serious of a threat to Hempel’s theory of confirmation than is Hempel’s own paradox of the ravens. I proceed by developing a suggestion from R.D. Rosenkrantz into an argument for the conclusion that these paradoxes are, in fact, equivalent. My argument, if successful, is of both historical and philosophical interest. Goodman himself maintained that Hempel’s theory of confirmation was capable of handling the paradox of the ravens. And Hempel eventually conceded that Goodman’s paradox showed that there could be no adequate, purely syntactical theory of confirmation. The conclusion of my argument entails, by contrast, that Hempel’s theory of confirmation is incapable of handling Goodman’s paradox if and only if it is incapable of handling the paradox of the ravens. It also entails that for any adequate solution to one of these paradoxes, there is a corresponding and equally adequate solution to the other. Historically, Nelson Goodman’s paradox involving the predicates ‘grue’ and ‘bleen’ has been taken to furnish a serious blow to Carl Hempel’s theory of confirmation in particular and to purely formal theories of confirmation in general.
    [Show full text]
  • Clear Thinking, Vague Thinking and Paradoxes
    Clear thinking, vague thinking and paradoxes Arieh Lev and Gil Kaplan Abstract Many undergraduate students of engineering and the exact sciences have difficulty with their mathematics courses due to insufficient proficiency in what we in this paper have termed clear thinking. We believe that this lack of proficiency is one of the primary causes underlying the common difficulties students face, leading to mistakes like the improper use of definitions and the improper phrasing of definitions, claims and proofs. We further argue that clear thinking is not a skill that is acquired easily and naturally – it must be consciously learned and developed. The paper describes, using concrete examples, how the examination and analysis of classical paradoxes can be a fine tool for developing students’ clear thinking. It also looks closely at the paradoxes themselves, and at the various solutions that have been proposed for them. We believe that the extensive literature on paradoxes has not always given clear thinking its due emphasis as an analytical tool. We therefore suggest that other disciplines could also benefit from drawing upon the strategies employed by mathematicians to describe and examine the foundations of the problems they encounter. Introduction Students working towards a B.A. in the exact sciences and in engineering encounter significant difficulties in their mathematics courses from day one. These students must be able to read, understand and accurately repeat definitions, and to skillfully and rigorously read and write mathematical claims and laws. In other words, they must be skilled in what this paper will refer to as "clear thinking": thinking that requires one to fully understand what concepts mean, to be able to use those concepts accurately, and to understand and express definitions and claims fully and accurately.
    [Show full text]
  • 17.09 Questions, Answers, and Evidence
    Scientific Method and Research Ethics 17.09 Questions, Answers, and Evidence Dr. C. D. McCoy Plan for Part 1: Deduction 1. Logic, Arguments, and Inference 1. Questions and Answers 2. Truth, Validity, and Soundness 3. Inference Rules and Formal Fallacies 4. Hypothetico-Deductivism What is Logic? • “What is logic?” is a question that philosophers and logicians have debated for millennia. We won’t attempt to give a complete answer to it here… Historical Perspectives on Logic • Aristotle held that logic is the instrument by which we come to know: important to coming to know is understanding the nature of things, especially the necessity of things. • Immanuel Kant held that logic is a “canon of reasoning”: a catalog of the correct forms of judgment. Logic is formal; it abstracts completely from semantic content. • Gottlob Frege held that logic is a “body of truths”: it has its own unique subject matter, which includes concepts and objects (like numbers!). • Many authors also hold that “generality” and “truth” are central notions in logic. Reasoning and Argument • Reasoning is a cognitive process that • Begins from facts, assumptions, principles, examples, instances, etc. • And ends with a solution, a conclusion, a judgment, a decision, etc. • In logic we call an item of reasoning an argument. • An argument consists in a series of statements, called the premisses, and a single statement, called the conclusion. Assessing Arguments • One reason to study logic is to understand why some instances of reasoning are good and why some are bad. • Logic neatly separates the ways arguments can be good or bad into two kinds: • The truth of the premisses.
    [Show full text]
  • Hempel's Raven Paradox
    HEMPEL’S RAVEN PARADOX: A LACUNA IN THE STANDARD BAYESIAN SOLUTION Peter B. M. Vranas [email protected] Iowa State University 7 July 2003 Abstract. According to Hempel’s paradox, evidence (E) that an object is a nonblack nonraven confirms the hypothesis (H) that every raven is black. According to the standard Bayesian solution, E does confirm H but only to a minute degree. This solution relies on the almost never explicitly defended assumption that the probability of H should not be affected by evidence that an object is nonblack. I argue that this assumption is implausible, and I propose a way out for Bayesians. 1. Introduction.1 “What do you like best about philosophy?” my grandmother asks. “Every philosopher is brilliant!” I unhesitatingly reply. “That’s hardly believable” my grandmother responds. To convince her I perform an experiment. I choose randomly a person, Rex, from the telephone directory. Predictably enough, Rex is neither brilliant nor a philosopher. “You see,” I crow, “this confirms my claim that every philosopher is brilliant!” My grandmother is unimpressed. I repeat the experiment: I choose randomly another person, Kurt. Surprisingly, Kurt is both a philosopher and brilliant. Now my grandmother is really impressed. “Look, grandma,” I patiently explain, “you are being irrational. The fact that Kurt is both a philosopher and brilliant confirms the hypothesis that every philosopher is brilliant—or so you accept. But then the fact that Rex is both nonbrilliant and a nonphilosopher confirms the hypothesis that everything nonbrilliant is a nonphilosopher, and thus also confirms the logically equivalent hypothesis that every philosopher is brilliant—or so you should accept.” “Young man, you are being impertinent” my grandmother retorts.
    [Show full text]