Dramatic Dialogues

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Dramatic Dialogues Chapter 3 The Implicit Narrator: Dramatic Dialogues 1 Introducing the Dramatic Dialogues Of the three groups of Plato’s dialogues, the dramatic dialogues form the larg- est and the most heterogeneous one. It comprises the earliest and the latest dialogues, the shortest and the longest pieces in the corpus, the most elaborate and the least elaborate, and not a few dramatic dialogues are spurious. Small wonder, then, that Plato’s dramatic dialogues exhibit a great variety of forms. This becomes immediately obvious from their openings. The short and simply structured “Socratic” dialogues normally open with a concise and efficient “zooming-in” in the course of which Socrates or another character establishes for the reader’s benefit his interlocutor’s identity and social and professional standing, as well as the immediate circumstances of the encounter: − In the Euthyphro, Euthyphro questions Socrates as to the reasons for his ar- rival at the Porch of the King Archon. − In the Crito, Socrates questions Crito as to the reasons for his arrival in the prison early in the morning. − In the Ion and Hippias Maior, Socrates questions the foreigners Ion and Hip- pias, respectively, as to the reasons for their arrival in Athens. − In the Hippias Minor, Eudicus questions Socrates as to the reasons for his silence after Hippias’ display of his art. − In the Menexenus, Socrates questions Menexenus as to the outcome of the proceedings at the meeting of the Athenian Council. Of the dialogues whose authenticity has been questioned, only the Hippias Maior functions as a regular Platonic dialogue in this respect. Alcibiades ii opens with a single question (quoted above, p. 10) rather than a series of ques- tions necessary for producing the zooming-in effect; in the Theages, the ques- tioning is preceded by a long speech by the as yet unidentified Demodocus (121b-122b), which is sharply at variance with the usual procedure. There is no zooming-in in the spurious Cleitophon, Hipparchus and Minos nor, significantly, in Alcibiades i.1 1 Cf. Friedländer 1964: 232: “While the dialogue corresponds, in this general situation, to others like the Charmides and the Lysis, there are no secondary figures in the Alcibiades nor is there any setting full of charm or symbolic meaning.” © koninklijke brill nv, leiden, ���9 | doi:�0.��63/97890043900�7_004 <UN> 48 Chapter 3 In the longer and more complex dialogues the introductory zooming-in is enhanced into an elaborate two-stage opening closely resembling the open- ings of the narrated dialogues. As in the latter, the transition from one stage to another involves a spatial change and/or modification in the cast of characters. − In the Laches, (i) the opening conversation between Lysimachus and Me- lesias on the one hand and Nicias and Laches on the other does not include Socrates, (ii) who joins the initial interlocutors only at a later stage (below, pp. 64–65). − In the Gorgias, (i) Callicles, Socrates, and Chaerephon meet in the street, apparently before Callicles’ house, (ii) and only at a later stage do they enter the house, where they meet Gorgias and Polus.2 − In the Phaedrus, (i) Socrates meets Phaedrus in the city, (ii) and they walk together to a shady spot on the banks of the Ilissus, where the conversation takes place; no change in the cast of characters is involved. − In the Laws, (i) the interlocutors meet in Cnosus, and, (ii) on their way to the cave and temple of Cretan Zeus, they arrive at a grove of cypresses, where most of their conversation apparently takes place; no change in the cast of characters is involved (625b8–c2, cf, 229a9–b2). It is hard to avoid the impression that the transition from one stage to another, as well as the changes in the setting and/or the cast of characters that accom- pany the transition, are modeled on the narrated dialogues, where they form a standard and well-developed pattern (above, pp. 27–28). This can be taken as an additional indication of Plato treating the dramatic dialogues as a form of narrative.3 The same pattern, albeit in reduced form, is present in the Sophist-Statesman and Timaeus-Critias: in these dialogues, Plato economizes on the first stage of the exposition by creating the impression that it had taken place just be- fore the dialogue began. This is obviously because all the dialogues of this group are set as sequels (above, p. 7). A similar strategy is applied in the 2 Cf. Dodds 1959: 188: “A similar change of scene from outdoors to indoors is explicitly indi- cated at Lysis 206de and in the prelude to the Theaetetus, 143b”; in Dodds’ opinion, however, the action takes place at the entrance to a public building. On the two-stage opening of the Gorgias and its similarity to the settings of narrated dialogues see also Thesleff 2003: 552–53. 3 Cf. de Jong 2004: 7–8: “In the case of the dramatic dialogues of Plato and Lucian, that is to say, those dialogues which lack a narrative frame and consist solely of speeches, it seems most sensible – in view of their close similarity to the dialogues with a narrative frame – to see them as narratives with a suppressed primary narrator and suppressed primary narratees” (original emphasis); cf. also de Jong 2014a: 17 and above, Chapter 1 with nn. 16 and 20. On Lu- cian see Whitmarsh 2004: 468; on parallels between the narrated and the dramatic dialogues see also Tarrant 1996: 143–46. <UN>.
Recommended publications
  • The Roles of Solon in Plato's Dialogues
    The Roles of Solon in Plato’s Dialogues Dissertation Presented in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Degree Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of The Ohio State University By Samuel Ortencio Flores, M.A. Graduate Program in Greek and Latin The Ohio State University 2013 Dissertation Committee: Bruce Heiden, Advisor Anthony Kaldellis Richard Fletcher Greg Anderson Copyrighy by Samuel Ortencio Flores 2013 Abstract This dissertation is a study of Plato’s use and adaptation of an earlier model and tradition of wisdom based on the thought and legacy of the sixth-century archon, legislator, and poet Solon. Solon is cited and/or quoted thirty-four times in Plato’s dialogues, and alluded to many more times. My study shows that these references and allusions have deeper meaning when contextualized within the reception of Solon in the classical period. For Plato, Solon is a rhetorically powerful figure in advancing the relatively new practice of philosophy in Athens. While Solon himself did not adequately establish justice in the city, his legacy provided a model upon which Platonic philosophy could improve. Chapter One surveys the passing references to Solon in the dialogues as an introduction to my chapters on the dialogues in which Solon is a very prominent figure, Timaeus- Critias, Republic, and Laws. Chapter Two examines Critias’ use of his ancestor Solon to establish his own philosophic credentials. Chapter Three suggests that Socrates re- appropriates the aims and themes of Solon’s political poetry for Socratic philosophy. Chapter Four suggests that Solon provides a legislative model which Plato reconstructs in the Laws for the philosopher to supplant the role of legislator in Greek thought.
    [Show full text]
  • Gorgias, Menexenus, Protagoras Edited by Malcolm Schofield Frontmatter More Information
    Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-54600-3 - Plato: Gorgias, Menexenus, Protagoras Edited by Malcolm Schofield Frontmatter More information CAMBRIDGE TEXTS IN THE HISTORY OF POLITICAL THOUGHT PLATO Gorgias, Menexenus, Protagoras © in this web service Cambridge University Press www.cambridge.org Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-54600-3 - Plato: Gorgias, Menexenus, Protagoras Edited by Malcolm Schofield Frontmatter More information CAMBRIDGE TEXTS IN THE HISTORY OF POLITICAL THOUGHT Series editors R AYMOND GEUSS Professor in Philosophy, University of Cambridge Q UENTIN SKINNER Professor of the Humanities, Queen Mary, University of London Cambridge Texts in the History of Political Thought is now firmly estab- lished as the major student textbook series in political theory. It aims to make available to students all the most important texts in the history of western political thought, from ancient Greece to the early twentieth century. All the familiar classic texts will be included, but the series seeks at the same time to enlarge the conventional canon by incorporating an extensive range of less well-known works, many of them never before available in a modern English edition. Wherever possible, texts are published in complete and unabridged form, and translations are specially commissioned for the series. Each vol- ume contains a critical introduction together with chronologies, biographical sketches, a guide to further reading and any necessary glossaries and text- ual apparatus. When completed the series will aim to offer an outline
    [Show full text]
  • The Phaedo by Plato
    Selections from The Phaedo by Plato The Death of Scorates, David, 1787. [The Phaedo tells the story of Socrates’ final moments spent, as one would expect, in philosophical dialogue with his friends. The main subject of the dialogue is the immortality of the soul. The Phaedo is one of Plato’s middle period dialogues and, as such, reveals much of Plato’s own philosophy. In the arguments Socrates puts forth for the immortality of the soul we find a clear exposition of both Plato’s metaphysics as well as his epistemology. In the first section we find Socrates explaining to his friends why a true philosopher does not fear death. Philosophy is here described as a preparation for death.] ECHECRATES: Were you there with Socrates yourself, Phaedo, when he was executed, or 57 did you hear about it from somebody else? PHAEDO: No, I was there myself, Echecrates. ECHECRATES: Then what did the master say before he died, and how did he meet his end? I should very much like to know. None of the people in Phlius go to Athens much in these days, and it is a long time since we had any visitor from there who could give us any definite b information, except that he was executed by drinking hemlock. Nobody could tell us anything more than that. PHAEDO: Then haven't you even heard how his trial went? 58 ECHECRATES: Yes, someone told us about that, and we were surprised because there was obviously a long interval between it and the execution. How was that, Phaedo? PHAEDO: A fortunate coincidence, Echecrates.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Arrangement of the Platonic Dialogues
    Ryan C. Fowler 25th Hour On the Arrangement of the Platonic Dialogues I. Thrasyllus a. Diogenes Laertius (D.L.), Lives and Opinions of Eminent Philosophers 3.56: “But, just as long ago in tragedy the chorus was the only actor, and afterwards, in order to give the chorus breathing space, Thespis devised a single actor, Aeschylus a second, Sophocles a third, and thus tragedy was completed, so too with philosophy: in early times it discoursed on one subject only, namely physics, then Socrates added the second subject, ethics, and Plato the third, dialectics, and so brought philosophy to perfection. Thrasyllus says that he [Plato] published his dialogues in tetralogies, like those of the tragic poets. Thus they contended with four plays at the Dionysia, the Lenaea, the Panathenaea and the festival of Chytri. Of the four plays the last was a satiric drama; and the four together were called a tetralogy.” b. Characters or types of dialogues (D.L. 3.49): 1. instructive (ὑφηγητικός) A. theoretical (θεωρηµατικόν) a. physical (φυσικόν) b. logical (λογικόν) B. practical (πρακτικόν) a. ethical (ἠθικόν) b. political (πολιτικόν) 2. investigative (ζητητικός) A. training the mind (γυµναστικός) a. obstetrical (µαιευτικός) b. tentative (πειραστικός) B. victory in controversy (ἀγωνιστικός) a. critical (ἐνδεικτικός) b. subversive (ἀνατρεπτικός) c. Thrasyllan categories of the dialogues (D.L. 3.50-1): Physics: Timaeus Logic: Statesman, Cratylus, Parmenides, and Sophist Ethics: Apology, Crito, Phaedo, Phaedrus, Symposium, Menexenus, Clitophon, the Letters, Philebus, Hipparchus, Rivals Politics: Republic, the Laws, Minos, Epinomis, Atlantis Obstetrics: Alcibiades 1 and 2, Theages, Lysis, Laches Tentative: Euthyphro, Meno, Io, Charmides and Theaetetus Critical: Protagoras Subversive: Euthydemus, Gorgias, and Hippias 1 and 2 :1 d.
    [Show full text]
  • Plato's Phaedo As a Pedagogical Drama
    Ancient Philosophy 33 (2013) ©Mathesis Publications 333 Plato’s Phaedo as a Pedagogical Drama Sarah Jansen The Phaedo has long been recognized as dramatic in nature (see, e.g., Jowett 1892, 193). Indeed, the dialogue’s dramatic portrayal of a Herculean Socrates attacking the heads of a hydra naturally invites this assessment (89c). At the out- set of the dialogue Socrates and the fourteen named companions are juxtaposed with Theseus and the fourteen Athenian youth, on their way to defeat the Mino- taur (58a-c).1 Also, Socrates’ death scene is particularly dramatic. Fifteen com- panions, the exact number of a tragic chorus, surround the dying Socrates and lament (117c-d).2 Reflection on this scene has prompted scholars to speculate that it is intended to ‘lend moving force’ to the tragic perspective and to ‘rouse’ readers’ emotions (see Halliwell 1984, 57-58 and Crotty 2009, 87, respectively). Despite these scholarly observations and compelling evidence that the dia- logues were treated as dramatic performance literature in antiquity (see Charal- abopoulos 2012), a number of key questions have yet to be satisfactorily and systematically answered: What is drama?; What is the Phaedo a drama about?; What is the function, if any, of the dramatic elements of the Phaedo? I undertake to answer these questions. I conclude with some thoughts about Plato’s purpose in writing dramatic dialogues and Plato’s attitude toward poetry. One of my aims throughout will be to demonstrate how a proper understanding of the literary dimension of the Phaedo sheds light on the philosophical content of the dialogue.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Foreigners As Liberators: Education and Cultural Diversity in Plato's
    1 Foreigners as Liberators: Education and Cultural Diversity in Plato’s Menexenus Rebecca LeMoine Assistant Professor of Political Science Florida Atlantic University NOTE: Use of this document is for private research and study only; the document may not be distributed further. The final manuscript has been accepted for publication and will appear in a revised form in The American Political Science Review 111.3 (August 2017). It is available for a FirstView online here: https://doi.org/10.1017/S0003055417000016 Abstract: Though recent scholarship challenges the traditional interpretation of Plato as anti- democratic, his antipathy to cultural diversity is still generally assumed. The Menexenus appears to offer some of the most striking evidence of Platonic xenophobia, as it features Socrates delivering a mock funeral oration that glorifies Athens’ exclusion of foreigners. Yet when readers play along with Socrates’ exhortation to imagine the oration through the voice of its alleged author Aspasia, Pericles’ foreign mistress, the oration becomes ironic or dissonant. Through this, Plato shows that foreigners can act as gadflies, liberating citizens from the intellectual hubris that occasions democracy’s fall into tyranny. In reminding readers of Socrates’ death, the dialogue warns, however, that fear of education may prevent democratic citizens from appreciating the role of cultural diversity in cultivating the virtue of Socratic wisdom. Keywords: Menexenus; Aspasia; cultural diversity; Socratic wisdom; Platonic irony Acknowledgments: An earlier version of this paper was presented at the 2012 annual meeting of the Association for Political Theory, where it benefitted greatly from Susan Bickford’s insightful commentary. Thanks to Ethan Alexander-Davey, Andreas Avgousti, Richard Avramenko, Brendan Irons, Daniel Kapust, Michelle Schwarze, the APSR editorial team (both present and former), and four anonymous referees for their invaluable feedback on earlier drafts.
    [Show full text]
  • The Role of Socrates, Lysis, and Menexenus in Plato's
    FILOZOFIA Roč. 75, 2020, č. 3 DOI: https://doi.org/10.31577/filozofia.2020.75.3. 3 THE ROLE OF SOCRATES, LYSIS, AND MENEXENUS IN PLATO’S LYSIS GABRIEL EVANGELOU, University of Cyprus, Department of Classics and Philosophy, Nicosia, Cyprus EVANGELOU, G.: The Role of Socrates, Lysis, and Menexenus in Plato’s Lysis FILOZOFIA, 75, 2020, No 3, pp. 195 – 211 The aim of this study is to demonstrate that the value of the Lysis does not lie in Socrates’ puzzling treatment of φίλος and φιλία, but rather in the unique role that both Socrates and the other two main interlocutors, Lysis and Menexenus, assume in this Platonic dialogue. In the Lysis, Socrates plays the role of the so- phist who uses errant logic, but with whom the young men are so infatuated that they simply agree with his every statement. Their inability to display critical thinking by challenging his flawed arguments constantly forces Socrates to re- vert to the role of the philosopher who refutes the points that he, himself, had just raised. The dialogue thus functions as a warning against blindly trusting the education of youths to sophists and potentially as an exercise for Plato’s students to detect problematic argumentation and to practise arguing against it. Keywords: Plato – Socrates – Lysis – Philia – Sophists – Aporia – Deception The perplexity of the Lysis has been a topic of considerable debate. Throughout the dialogue, the reader is given the impression that Socrates is attempting to provide a definition of ‘φίλος’1 by asking the two teenagers, Lysis and Menexenus, a series of questions.2 Nevertheless, before reaching a conclusion, their philosophical discussion 1 The scope of the Lysis has been heavily contested.
    [Show full text]
  • Reading Plato Through the Menexenus I Begin with the Current Critical Agreement That Plato Did Indeed Write the Menexenus
    Reading Plato Through the Menexenus I begin with the current critical agreement that Plato did indeed write the Menexenus. There was not always such agreement; but it was not the style of the dialogue that called it into question, nor ancient aspersions on its authenticity. This dialogue just did not seem (to many) the sort of thing Plato, our Plato, would write. It is so wildly anachronistic, so full of obvious historical distortion, and so lacking in philosophical meat. Never mind that Aristotle twice refers to it as one of Plato’s works. We are largely past those doubtful days, and there has even arisen something of a communis opinio about a general interpretation of the dialogue (while important details remain critically unsettled): Plato gives us in the Menexenus a parody of contemporary rhetoric, revealing it as facile, shallow, and destructive of the sort of political excellence it aims to celebrate, and even create in its listeners. That parody points, by contrast, the superiority of what Plato/Socrates has to offer over rhetoric: philosophy, dialectic, the truth, etc. – even though this dialogue does not give us much of that superior mode. From that consensus this paper moves forward. Does recognition of the Menexenus as a legitimate entry in Plato’s oeuvre require that we somehow change our view of what Plato does? If we agree that Plato can write a dialogue like this, do we have to reassess what Plato does elsewhere? That question is too large for full treatment in this paper, but I will approach it by refashioning it into a slightly more manageable one: are there aspects of the Platonic corpus that become clear(er) to us when we see them writ large in the Menexenus? I answer in the affirmative, and proceed to examples, hoping to set us on a path toward new ways we might read Plato through the Menexenus.
    [Show full text]
  • [The Bloomsbury Companion to Socrates, J. Bussanich and N. D. Smith, Eds., Bloomsbury, 2013, 210-32; Penultimate Draft]
    [The Bloomsbury Companion to Socrates, J. Bussanich and N. D. Smith, eds., Bloomsbury, 2013, 210-32; penultimate draft] Chapter 10 Socrates on Love Suzanne Obdrzalek Introduction: Socrates as Lover In the famous Catalogue Aria of Don Giovanni, Leporello recounts how his master seduced 2,065 ladies in France, Germany, Italy, Turkey, and Spain; reading Plato’s Socratic dialogues, one gets the sense that, while he may have had few actual conquests, at least in terms of overall susceptibility to beauty, Socrates was not far behind.1 In the Charmides, Socrates describes himself as a poor judge of youthful beauty because, like a broken yardstick, he finds almost all young men appealing (154b). In the Symposium, Alcibiades accuses Socrates of being ‘crazy about beautiful boys; he constantly follows them around in a perpetual daze’ (216d).2 Though Socrates is famous for professing ignorance, there is one area where he trumpets his expertise: in the Symposium, he declares that the only thing he understands is ta erōtika (matters of love, 177d); in the Lysis, he describes himself as mean and useless in all else, but possessed of the god-given skill to recognize lovers and beloveds (204b-c). Perhaps the most noteworthy of Socrates’ infatuations was with Alcibiades: in the Gorgias, Socrates calls himself the dual lover of philosophy and of Alcibiades (481d). In the Protagoras, teased for hunting after the ripe Alcibiades, Socrates defends himself, alluding to Homer’s observation that young men are at their most seductive when their beards are in first bloom (309a- b). However, Alcibiades was not the only youth to catch Socrates’ eye: in the opening of the Charmides, Socrates famously describes himself as aflame with passion when he catches a glimpse beneath the boy’s cloak.4 This description is paralleled in Xenophon’s Symposium, where Socrates describes the effect of rubbing his naked shoulder against Critobulos’ as the bite of a wild beast, which leaves a sting in his heart (4.27-8).
    [Show full text]
  • Plato's Introduction of Forms
    This page intentionally left blank PLATO’S INTRODUCTION OF FORMS Scholars of Plato are divided between those who emphasize the liter- ature of the dialogues and those who emphasize the argument of the dialogues, and between those who see a development in the thought of the dialogues and those who do not. In this important book, Russell Dancy focuses on the arguments and defends a developmental pic- ture. He explains the Theory of Forms of the Phaedo and Symposium as an outgrowth of the quest for definitions canvased in the Socratic dialogues, by constructing a Theory of Definition for the Socratic dialogues based on the refutations of definitions in those dialogues, and showing how that theory is mirrored in the Theory of Forms. His discussion, notable for both its clarity and its meticulous schol- arship, ranges in detail over a number of Plato’s early and middle dialogues, and will be of interest to readers in Plato studies and in ancient philosophy more generally. r. m. dancy is Professor of Philosophy at Florida State University. He is the author of Sense and Contradiction: A Study in Aristotle (1975) and TwoStudies in the Early Academy (1991), and editor of Kant and Critique (1993). PLATO’S INTRODUCTION OF FORMS R. M. DANCY Florida State University, Tallahassee Cambridge, New York, Melbourne, Madrid, Cape Town, Singapore, São Paulo Cambridge University Press The Edinburgh Building, Cambridge , UK Published in the United States of America by Cambridge University Press, New York www.cambridge.org Information on this title: www.cambridge.org/9780521838016 © R. M. Dancy 2004 This publication is in copyright.
    [Show full text]
  • Socrates' Aspasian Oration: the Play of Philosophy and Politics in Plato's
    Bryn Mawr College Scholarship, Research, and Creative Work at Bryn Mawr College Political Science Faculty Research and Scholarship Political Science 1993 Socrates' Aspasian Oration: The lP ay of Philosophy and Politics in Plato's Menexenus Stephen G. Salkever Bryn Mawr College, [email protected] Let us know how access to this document benefits ouy . Follow this and additional works at: http://repository.brynmawr.edu/polisci_pubs Part of the Ancient Philosophy Commons, and the Political Science Commons Custom Citation Salkever, Stephen G. "Socrates' Aspasian Oration: The lP ay of Philosophy and Politics in Plato's Menexenus." American Political Science Review 87 (1993): 133-143. This paper is posted at Scholarship, Research, and Creative Work at Bryn Mawr College. http://repository.brynmawr.edu/polisci_pubs/12 For more information, please contact [email protected]. American Political Science Review Vol. 87, No. 1 March 1993 SOCRATES'ASPASIAN ORATION: THE PLAY OF PHILOSOPHY AND POLITICSIN PLATO'S MENEXENUS STEPHEN G. SALKEVER Bryn Mawr College P lato'sMenexenus is overlooked,perhaps because of thedifficulty of gauging its irony.In it, Socratesrecites a funeral orationhe says he learnedfrom Aspasia, describingevents that occurredafter the deathsof both Socratesand Pericles'mistress. But the dialogue'sironic complexityis one reasonit is a centralpart of Plato'spolitical philosophy. In bothstyle and substance, Menexenus rejectsthe heroicaccount of Atheniandemocracy proposed by Thucydides'Pericles, separatingAthenian citizenship from the questfor immortalglory; its pictureof the relationshipof philosopherto polis illustratesPlato's conception of the true politikos in the Statesman. In both dialogues,philosophic response to politicsis neitherdirect rule nor apoliticalwithdrawal. Menexe- nus presentsa Socrateswho influencespolitics indirectly, by recastingAthenian history and thus transformingthe termsin whichits politicalalternatives are conceived.
    [Show full text]
  • The Un-Platonic Menexenus: a Stylometric Analysis with More Data Thomas Koentges
    The Un-Platonic Menexenus: A Stylometric Analysis with More Data Thomas Koentges HE CORPUS PLATONICUM is one of the most well-known and influential works of ancient literature, and yet it still T presents unresolved challenges regarding the authorship of some works. Since the middle of the nineteenth century, stylometry, the counting and statistical analysis of features in the language of an author, has been applied to the Corpus Platonicum in order to date works by Plato, to prove or disprove the authen- ticity of his work, or to analyze how he used different styles (for instance, to characterize different individuals in his dialogues).1 This article revisits the second of these applications with a special focus on the question of the authorship of the Menexenus. The results of previous stylometric analyses of the Corpus Platonicum were inconclusive on the question of authorship.2 One reason for this probably lies in the selection of features, which covers the frequency of certain words, the number of words in a sentence, the quantities of clausulae, or any other element of the text that can be observed and counted and that is thought to be part of the stylistic fingerprints of the author. Previously, analyses employed a limited number of features, but as Burrows has observed, “in this sort of work on language … a wealth of variables, many of which may be weak discriminators, almost 1 A good example of the latter has been published in this journal: D. San- sone, “Stylistic Characterization in Plato: Nicias, Alcibiades, and Laches,” GRBS 58 (2018) 156–176.
    [Show full text]