The Persistence of Subjectivity: on the Kantian Aftermath

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Persistence of Subjectivity: on the Kantian Aftermath P1: JZP 052184858Xagg.xml CY536B/Pippin 0521 84858 X February 25, 2005 11:11 This page intentionally left blank ii P1: JZP 052184858Xagg.xml CY536B/Pippin 0521 84858 X February 25, 2005 11:11 The Persistence of Subjectivity On the Kantian Aftermath The Persistence of Subjectivity examines several approaches to and criti- cisms of the idea at the heart of the self-understanding of the modern Western, or “bourgeois,” form of historical life: the free, reflective, self-determining subject. Since it is a relatively recent historical de- velopment that human beings have come to think of themselves as individual centers of agency and to believe that entitlement to such a self-determining life is absolutely valuable, raising such a question also raises the question of the historical location of philosophical re- flection itself. What might it mean, that is, to take seriously Hegel’s claim that philosophical reflection must always be reflection on the historical actuality of its own age? In discussions of Kant, Hegel, Heidegger, Gadamer, Adorno, Leo Strauss, Arendt, Manfred Frank, and John McDowell and in examinations of modern institutional practices and modernist art and literature, Robert Pippin challenges a number of prevalent views about both the nature and the value of “leading one’s own life.” Robert B. Pippin is the Raymond W. and Martha Hilpert Gruner Dis- tinguished Service Professor in the Committee on Social Thought, the Department of Philosophy, and the College at the University of Chicago. He is the author of several books on German idealism, in- cluding Kant’s Theory of Form, Hegel’s Idealism: The Satisfactions of Self- Consciousness, Modernism as a Philosophical Problem, and, most recently, Henry James and Modern Moral Life. He is winner of the Mellon Distin- guished Achievement Award in the Humanities and was a Fellow at the Wissenschaftskolleg in Berlin. i P1: JZP 052184858Xagg.xml CY536B/Pippin 0521 84858 X February 25, 2005 11:11 ii P1: JZP 052184858Xagg.xml CY536B/Pippin 0521 84858 X February 25, 2005 11:11 The Persistence of Subjectivity On the Kantian Aftermath ROBERT B. PIPPIN University of Chicago iii Cambridge, New York, Melbourne, Madrid, Cape Town, Singapore, São Paulo Cambridge University Press The Edinburgh Building, Cambridge ,UK Published in the United States of America by Cambridge University Press, New York www.cambridge.org Information on this title: www.cambridg e.org /9780521848589 © Robert B. Pippin 2005 This book is in copyright. Subject to statutory exception and to the provision of relevant collective licensing agreements, no reproduction of any part may take place without the written permission of Cambridge University Press. First published in print format 2005 - ---- eBook (EBL) - --- eBook (EBL) - ---- hardback - --- hardback - ---- paperback - --- paperback Cambridge University Press has no responsibility for the persistence or accuracy of s for external or third-party internet websites referred to in this book, and does not guarantee that any content on such websites is, or will remain, accurate or appropriate. P1: JZP 052184858Xagg.xml CY536B/Pippin 0521 84858 X February 25, 2005 11:11 Contents Acknowledgments page vii 1 Introduction: “Bourgeois Philosophy” and the Problem of the Subject 1 part i setting 2 The Kantian Aftermath: Reaction and Revolution in Modern German Philosophy 27 part ii theorists 3 Necessary Conditions for the Possibility of What Isn’t: Heidegger on Failed Meaning 57 4 Gadamer’s Hegel: Subjectivity and Reflection 79 5 Negative Ethics: Adorno on the Falseness of Bourgeois Life 98 6 The Unavailability of the Ordinary: Strauss on the Philosophical Fate of Modernity 121 7 Hannah Arendt and the Bourgeois Origins of Totalitarian Evil 146 8 On Not Being a Neo-Structuralist: Remarks on Manfred Frank and Romantic Subjectivity 168 9 Leaving Nature Behind, or Two Cheers for Subjectivism: On John McDowell 186 Postscript: On McDowell’s Response to “Leaving Nature Behind” 206 v P1: JZP 052184858Xagg.xml CY536B/Pippin 0521 84858 X February 25, 2005 11:11 vi Contents part iii modern mores 10 The Ethical Status of Civility 223 11 Medical Practice and Social Authority in Modernity 239 part iv expression 12 “The Force of Felt Necessity”: Literature, Ethical Knowledge, and Law 261 13 What Was Abstract Art? (From the Point of View of Hegel) 279 14 On “Becoming Who One Is” (and Failing): Proust’s Problematic Selves 307 Bibliography 339 Name Index 353 Subject Index 358 P1: JZP 052184858Xagg.xml CY536B/Pippin 0521 84858 X February 25, 2005 11:11 Acknowledgments Earlier versions of these chapters have appeared in the following pub- lications and I am grateful for permission to reprint. In most cases the revisions for this volume have involved brief expansions or qualifications, or most often additions to the footnotes. The postscript to chapter 9 ap- pears here for the first time. Two are reprinted with permission of Cambridge University Press: “The Kantian Aftermath: Reaction and Revolution in Modern German Philosophy” will appear soon in The Cambridge History of Nineteenth Century Philosophy, edited by Allen Wood, and “Gadamer’s Hegel: Subjectivity and Reflection” appeared in The Cambridge Companion to Gadamer, edited by Robert J. Dostal (2002). “Negative Ethics: Adorno on the Falseness of Bourgeois Life” will appear in German in early 2005 in a collection of conference papers edited by Axel Honneth and published by Suhrkamp. “The Unavailability of the Ordinary: Strauss on the Philosophical Fate of Modernity” appeared in Political Theory 31, no. 3 ( June 2003), pub- lished by Sage Publishing. “Hannah Arendt and the Bourgeois Origins of Totalitarian Evil” will appear in a collection of essays, Modernity and the Problem of Evil, edited by Alan Schrift for Indiana University Press. “On Not Being a Neo-Structuralist: Remarks on Manfred Frank and Romantic Subjectivity” appeared in Common Knowledge 6, no. 2 (Fall 1996). “Leav- ing Nature Behind: Or Two Cheers for Subjectivism: On John McDowell” appeared in Reading McDowell: Essays on Mind and World, ed. Nick Smith, with responses by McDowell (New York and London: Routledge, 2002). “The Ethical Status of Civility” appeared in Civility, ed. Leroy S. Rouner (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 2000). “Medical Practice and Social Authority in Modernity” appeared in the Journal of Medicine vii P1: JZP 052184858Xagg.xml CY536B/Pippin 0521 84858 X February 25, 2005 11:11 viii Acknowledgments and Philosophy 21 (1996). “‘The Felt Necessities of the Time’: Literature, Ethical Knowledge, and Law” first appeared in Italian as “‘Percepire le necessit`a del tempo’: Letteratura, conoscenza morale e diritto,” Ars In- terpretandi 7 (2002). “What Was Abstract Art? (From the Point of View of Hegel)” appeared in Critical Inquiry 29, no. 1 (Fall 2002). “On Becom- ing Who One Is: Proust’s Problematic Selves” will appear in Philosophical Romanticism, ed. Nikolas Kompridis, to be published by Routledge Press. Iamespecially grateful to two institutions: the Wissenschaftskolleg zu Berlin, where I was in residence in 2003–4 and so could complete work on the introduction, the postscript to chapter 9, and the revisions to various chapters; and the Andrew M. Mellon Foundation, whose Distinguished Achievement Award in 2001 supported much of the final editorial work on this volume. Special thanks to Thomas Bartscherer, Bo Earle, Hugh Liebert, and Jonny Thakkar for their assistance in preparing the manuscript and index. P1: JZP 052184858Xagg.xml CY536B/Pippin 0521 84858 X February 25, 2005 11:11 The Persistence of Subjectivity On the Kantian Aftermath ix P1: JZP 052184858Xagg.xml CY536B/Pippin 0521 84858 X February 25, 2005 11:11 x P1: JYD/... P2: JZP/... 052184858Xc01.xml CY536B/Pippin 0521 84858 X February 25, 2005 21:20 1 Introduction “Bourgeois Philosophy” and the Problem of the Subject I Nowadays the term “bourgeois philosophy” no doubt sounds an immedi- ate ironic note. It invokes a still polemical, if also a stale and overused char- acterization of a distinct historical condition, our historical condition, the “modern West.” The phrase suggests that there is a sort of philosophy ap- propriate to a historical epoch and a kind of society, that pursuing some questions makes sense only under certain historical conditions: a certain level of cultural development or prosperity, a certain sort of economic organization, a certain distribution of social power, a certain relation to religion, and so forth. “Bourgeois” is an adjective that is supposed to help direct us to the specific conditions among the possibilities most relevant for understanding why our philosophy looks the way it does, so different from past versions of our own, and perhaps from anyone else’s. Since the term has become a kind of epithet, it also suggests a high-minded defense of a commitment to a value, when that commitment is actually motivated by low-minded interests. If we were to characterize epochs and societies by reference to “highest values,” then the heart of such a bourgeois philosophy would have to be a philosophy of freedom. This would be a philosophy that explains how it is possible (whether it is possible) that individual subjects could uniquely, qua individuals, direct the course of their own lives, why it has become so important that we seek to achieve this state maximally, consistent with a like liberty for all, what that means, why it is just to call on the coercive force of law to ensure such a possibility (the protection of liberty, the “one natural right”), and so forth. The basic philosophical claim underwriting 1 P1: JYD/... P2: JZP/... 052184858Xc01.xml CY536B/Pippin 0521 84858 X February 25, 2005 21:20 2 The Persistence of Subjectivity such an enterprise is the notion of the independent, rational, reflective individual, one who can act in the light of such reflective results. This is the ontological and the value claim that underwrites rights protection, claims of entitlement, and just deserts, and that begins to make pressing new sorts of philosophical problems: the distinct nature of self-knowledge, the problem of personal identity, skepticism about the external world and other minds, and so forth.
Recommended publications
  • Aesthetic Interpretation and the Claim to Community in Cavell
    CONVERSATIONS 5 Seeing Selves and Imagining Others: Aesthetic Interpretation and the Claim to Community in Cavell JON NAJARIAN Politics is aesthetic in principle. JACQUES RANCIÈRE From his early childhood, Stanley Cavell learned to tread carefully the intervening space between twin pillars: of aesthetic sensibility on the one hand, and political be- longing on the other. Early in his memoir Little Did I Know, Cavell establishes a set of differences between his mother and father that far exceed both gender and age (his father was ten years older than his mother), as he notes the starkly contrasting dis- pensations of their respective families: The artistic temperament of my mother’s family, the Segals, left them on the whole, with the exception of my mother and her baby brother, Mendel, doubt- fully suited to an orderly, successful existence in the new world; the orthodox, religious sensibility of my father’s family, the Goldsteins, produced a second generation—some twenty-two first cousins of mine—whose solidarity and se- verity of expectation produced successful dentists, lawyers, and doctors, pillars of the Jewish community, and almost without exception attaining local, some of them national, some even a certain international, prominence.1 From his mother’s family, Cavell would inherit the musical sensibility that, had he not ventured into the world of academic philosophy, might have led him towards a career as a musician or in music. In his father’s family Cavell observes a religious belonging that, in the decades in which Cavell is raised, becomes morally inseparable from politi- $1. Cavell, Little Did I Know: Excerpts from Memory (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2010), 3.
    [Show full text]
  • Art and Emancipation: Habermas's
    New German Critique Art and Emancipation: Habermas’s “Die Moderne— ein unvollendetes Projekt” Reconsidered Gili Kliger The Fate of Aesthetics While, by Habermas’s own admission, his remarks on aesthetic modernity always had a “secondary character to the extent that they arose only in the context of other themes,” aesthetics and aesthetic modernity do occupy an important position in his overall oeuvre.1 Much of Habermas’s work is charac- terized by an effort to restore the modern faith in reason first articulated by Enlightenment thinkers. It was, on Habermas’s terms, problematic that the cri- tique of reason launched by the first generation of Frankfurt School theorists, notably Theodor W. Adorno and Max Horkheimer, left them without a basis on which any reasoned critique of society could be pursued.2 For those theo- rists, Adorno especially, aesthetic experience held the promise of a reconciled relation between the sensual and the rational, posing as an “other” to the dom- inating force of instrumental reason in modern society and offering a way to I wish to thank Martin Ruehl, the Department of German at the University of Cambridge, Peter Gordon, John Flower, and the anonymous reviewers for their indispensable guidance and helpful suggestions. 1. Jürgen Habermas, “Questions and Counterquestions,” in Habermas and Modernity, ed. Rich- ard J. Bernstein (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1985), 199. 2. Jürgen Habermas, Der philosophische Diskurs der Moderne (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1985), 138–39. New German Critique 124, Vol. 42, No. 1, February
    [Show full text]
  • The Fear of Aesthetics in Art and Literary Theory Sam Rose
    The Fear of Aesthetics in Art and Literary Theory Sam Rose New Literary History, Volume 48, Number 2, Spring 2017, pp. 223-244 (Article) Published by Johns Hopkins University Press DOI: https://doi.org/10.1353/nlh.2017.0011 For additional information about this article https://muse.jhu.edu/article/663805 Access provided at 2 May 2019 15:33 GMT from University of St Andrews The Fear of Aesthetics in Art and Literary Theory Sam Rose eading the preface to the new edition of the Encyclopedia of Aesthetics, one might think that the battle over the status of aes- Rthetics is over. According to the narrative of its editor Michael Kelly, aesthetics, held in generally low esteem at the time of the 1998 first edition, has now happily overcome its association with “an alleg- edly retrograde return to beauty,” or its representation as “an ideology defending the tastes of a dominant class, country, race, gender, sexual preference, ethnicity, or empire.”1 The previously “rather pervasive anti- aesthetic stance” of the 1990s passed away with that decade.2 Defined as “critical reflection on art, culture, and nature,” aesthetics is now a respectable practice once again.3 The publication of the Encyclopedia’s latest iteration is a timely moment to review the current state of its much-maligned subject. The original edi- tion of 1998 faced major difficulties, with Kelly writing that his requests for contributions were greeted not only with silence from some, but also with responses from angry callers keen to tell him how misguided the entire project was.4 And while Kelly emphasizes the change toward a more positive view, in some critics, it seems, the fear of aesthetics in art and literary theory has only increased.
    [Show full text]
  • A Call to Act.Witness.Testimony.Politicalrenewal
    UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA, IRVINE A Call to Act: Witness, Testimony, and Political Renewal in Shakespeare’s Plays DISSERTATION submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY in English By Tracy Clare Cummings Dissertation Committee: Professor Julia R. Lupton, Chair Associate Professor Rebeca Helfer Associate Professor Ian Munro 2015 © 2015 Tracy Clare Cummings DEDICATION To My family, my committee, and my friends in gratitude for their great help to me while I pursued my dreams and neglected theirs. “There is no agony like bearing an untold story inside you.” Zora Neale Hurston “The Puritans? The Puritans? I have no respect for them. They left England when Shakespeare was writing for the stage.” Virginia Berry Cummings ii TABLE OF CONTENTS PAGE ACKNOWLEDGMENTS v CURRICULUM VITAE vii ABSTRACT OF THE DISSERTATION ix INTRODUCTION 1 CHAPTER 1: “Better play the orator”: III Henry VI 12 and the Power of Self-Disclosing Speech CHAPTER 2: “The time of good neighbors”: Much Ado 99 About Nothing and the Danger of Public Speech CHAPTER 3: “It nips me into listening”: Pericles and the 156 Power of Shared Narratives BIBLIOGRAPHY 208 iii ACKNOWLEDGMENTS It has been an honor and a pleasure to work with my committee, Julia R. Lupton, Rebeca Helfer, and Ian Munro. Their insights into literature, philosophy, and theater, as well as the patience they have shown me, have helped me learn what it takes to be a scholar and a person who treats others with respect and compassion. When I faltered, they stood firm, and when I achieved what grace I could, they welcomed my success.
    [Show full text]
  • Cavellian Meditations1
    CONVERSATIONS 2! Cavellian Meditations1 ROBERT SINNERBRINK 1. Film and Philosophy Stanley Cavell’s coming to philosophy was inspired, as he recounts, by the contingent encounter between philosophical and non-philosophical texts. He singles out Witt- genstein’s Philosophical Investigations, for example, as one that “staked its teaching on showing that we do not know, or make ourselves forget, what reading is.”2 He also names three films — Bergman’s Sommarnattens leende (Smiles of a Summer Night, 1955), Resnais and Duras’ Hiroshima Mon Amour (1959), and Antonioni’s L’Avventura (1960) — that suggested to him what philosophy might become should it re-orient itself towards different modes of thought.3 These three films, for Cavell, not only altered American perceptions of what “foreign” (indeed “Continental”) films could do, they also opened up the question of what constitutes “a medium of thought.” Indeed, they were films that served “to alter the iconography of intellectual conversation,”4 not least the possibility that film might be a partner to philosophy, or that some kind of marriage between the two might be possible. I take Cavell’s anecdote to be significant for understanding the possibilities of our philosophical engagement with film. It raises the question of how we should ap- proach film-philosophy, understood as a distinctive way of writing philosophically about film that Cavell, more than most, has made intelligible. By “film-philosophy” I mean aesthetically-receptive writing that develops philosophical insights from our experience of film rather than by applying to film the traditional problems or techni- !!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!! 1. A longer, modified version of this paper will appear in the journal Film-Philosophy, “The Stanley Cavell Issue” (2014).
    [Show full text]
  • Adorno, Habermas, and Artistic Truth
    r Imaginative Disclosure: Adorno, Habermas, and Artistic Truth LAMBERT ZUIDERVAART, Institute for Christian Studies (Toronto) All aesthetic questions terminate in those of the truth content of artworks. - Theodor W. Adorno The aesthetic 'validity' ... that we attribute to a work [of art] refers to its singularly illuminating power ... to disclose anew an apparently familiar reality. - Jurgen Habermas1 The idea of artistic truth is a crossroad for third-generation critical theorists. Few ideas were more crucial for Theodor W. Adorno's negative dialectic, arguably the most important philosophical contribution to critical theory by the first generation.2 Yet it finds no place in Jurgen Habermas's theory of communicative action, the dominant paradigm among second-generation critical theorists. The divergence of paths between "Adornians" and "Haber­ masians" in the third generation cuts directly through this idea. A scholar who thinks both sides have important insights on the topic faces an apparent dilemma. If one tries to retrieve Adorno's intuitions about artistic truth, one runs the danger of becoming unintelligible to postmetaphysical theorists. Alternatively, one can soldier on using Habermasian concepts, and risk losing the critical-utopian import of Adorno's negative dialectic. Kant famously suggested in a very different context that concepts with­ out intuitive content are empty, and intuitions without concepts are blind. Adorno would add, in a Hegelian critique of Kant, that neither intuitions nor concepts can be pure. 3 Accordingly, one might be able to mediate the apparently incompatible positions of Adorno and Habermas and, modifying both sides, to develop a fruitful account of artistic truth. That is what this essay attempts, drawing upon a larger study of the idea of artistic truth.4 First the essay reviews Adorno's idea of artistic truth content (Wahrheit­ sgeha/f) in light of Habermasian concerns about a general conception of truth.
    [Show full text]
  • The Politics of Aesthetic Affect —A Reconstruction of Habermas' Art
    PARRHESIA NUMBER 13 • 2011 • 62-78 THE POLITICS OF AESTHETIC AFFECT —A RECONSTRUCTION OF HABERMAS’ ART THEORY Geoff Boucher Raymond Williams once declared that works of art—he was speaking specifically of literary works, but the claim has broader implications—are “structures of feeling,” not “pictures of reality.”1 The politics of art therefore result from a politicised understanding of the ways in which the judgement of taste is shaped by hegemonic norms of interpretation, where the common-sense of an historical epoch supplies, at the unconscious level, a typology of judgements that delimits possible constructions of meaning. New semantic contents, he proposed, released new feelings, promoting constructions of subjectivity that potentially defied conventional identities and commonsensical evaluations of works.2 But this penetrating insight, so different from subsequent efforts to direct a politicisation of aesthetics through cognitive forms of ideology critique, was only cashed out by Williams in terms of “residual,” “dominant,” and “emergent” cultural structures.3 The linear and progressive notion of history implied by these categories mortgages a politicisation of aesthetics to the conceptual framework of a philosophy of history, which is driven by an historical teleology that is no longer credible. As part of a larger project of developing a critique of the contemporary Frankfurt School, and particularly the work of Jürgen Habermas, I want to draw attention in this connection to his aesthetics. Habermas’s art theory attempts, from a post-metaphysical perspective, to concretise the emancipatory intentions of Critical Theory through understanding artworks as structures of feeling. Here is a project, then, that takes up the same sort of insight as that of Williams, yet which tries to develop it without reference to metaphysical teleology and the utopian idea that art anticipates a de-alienated society.
    [Show full text]
  • Presentation of the Colloquium Project
    Traditional and New Enhancing Human Cybernetic and Nanotechnological Body Modification Technologies: A Comparative Study of Roman Catholic and Transhumanist Ethical Approaches Michael J. Caligiuri A thesis submitted to the Faculty of Graduate and Postdoctoral Studies in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the PhD degree in Religious Studies Department of Classics and Religious Studies Faculty of Arts University of Ottawa © Michael Caligiuri, Ottawa, Canada 2013 ii Acknowledgements in memoriam matris carissimae Ninetta Gaetana Caligiuri manus cui cunabula curae mundum regit For Theodore and Calum Model teachers and men For my Surrogate Family in Ottawa This work happened because of you For the Crowned One Always loved and remembered For my Professors in Religious Studies at the University of Ottawa Professional of course but also caring gratias vobis ago iii Abstract Advances in cybernetic and nanotechnological body modifications currently allow for enhancements to human physical and mental function which exceed human species-based norms. This thesis examines body modification and human enhancement from two perspectives—Roman Catholicism and Transhumanism— in order to contribute to bioethical deliberations regarding enhancement technologies. Roman Catholicism has a longstanding tradition of bioethical discourse, informing the healthcare directives of Roman Catholic institutions. Transhumanism is more recent movement that endorses body modifications and human enhancements as a means of individual betterment and social evolution.
    [Show full text]
  • A Defence of Jilrgen Habermas's Discourse Ethics
    A DEFENCE OF JURGEN HABERMAS'S DISCOURSE ETHICS SO IS THERE A PLACE FOR MORALITY? A DEFENCE OF JORGEN HABERMAS'S DISCOURSE ETHICS By CRAIG FAUCETTE, RA. A Thesis Submitted to the School ofGraduate Studies in Partial Fulfilment ofthe Requirements for the Degree Master ofArts McMaster University © Copyright by Craig Faucette, September 2000 MASTER OF ARTS (2000) McMaster University (Philosophy) Hamilton, Ontario TITLE: So is There a Place for Morality? A Defence ofJilrgen Habermas's Discourse Ethics. AUTHOR: Craig Faucette, B.A. (Wilfrid Laurier University) SUPERVISOR: Professor E. Boetzkes NUMBER OF PAGES: vi, 93 11 Abstract The purpose ofthis thesis is to offer a defence of Jlirgen Habermas's discourse ethics against rival ethical theories that are oriented toward questions ofthe good life. Habermas's discourse ethics is founded on the Kantian distinction between the right and good. This distinction has come under fire from hermeneutically informed theorists, such as Georgia Warnke and Charles Taylor, as being either unattainable and unnecessary (Warnke), or contradictory as it must rely on the cultural contextuality in which it is formed (Taylor). But since Habermas's discourse ethics is discursive in nature and founded on the structural pragmatics of language use, it is able to effectively answer both Warnke's and Taylor's concerns. I attempt to prove this by showing that Habermas grounds discourse ethics through linking it with the perspective in which participants partake in actual discourse; thus providing a quasi-contextual basis, while it still remains Kantian in nature, as its scope and function is cognitive, universal and formal. 11l Acknowledgements I would like to thank my family, Brenda, Michael and Paul Faucette, for providing support, both emotional and financial.
    [Show full text]
  • Of Culture Properly Interpreted: Response to Nikolas Kompridis Author(S): Seyla Benhabib Reviewed Work(S): Source: Political Theory, Vol
    The "Claims" of Culture Properly Interpreted: Response to Nikolas Kompridis Author(s): Seyla Benhabib Reviewed work(s): Source: Political Theory, Vol. 34, No. 3 (Jun., 2006), pp. 383-388 Published by: Sage Publications, Inc. Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/20452464 . Accessed: 30/11/2011 17:30 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Sage Publications, Inc. is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Political Theory. http://www.jstor.org *:::fiA ...... wa:..:... mber A3i.x ..2006 383-388 0 WON06 Publi ations The "Claims" of Culture 10.1ht/pt.k agepube.om hsted at Properly Interpreted http:H_o epub.com Response to Nikolas Kompridis Seyla Benhabib Yale University, New Haven, Connecticut In his strident article on "Normativizing Hybridity/Neutralizing Culture," Nikolas Kompridis sharply criticizes a view of culture "which often exag gerates the fluidity, permeability, and renegotiability of culture."' Although Kompridis admits that this anti-essentialist view has much to recommend it, he finds that the exaggerated emphasis on the hybridity of cultures results in "a concept that undermines the conditions of its own application, such that nothing empirically can actually conform to it" (319).
    [Show full text]
  • The Idea of a Critical Political Theory
    Columbia University Center for Contemporary Critical Thought Fall 2015 Seminar The Idea of a Critical Political Theory Professor Linda Zerilli Monday Through Friday, October 19-23, 2015 Seminar Description Anyone who goes beyond procedural questions of a discourse theory of morality and ethics and, in a normative attitude . embarks on a theory of the well- ordered, or even emancipated, society will quickly run up against the limits of his own historical situation. --Habermas For some time now, a certain strand of contemporary critical theory has understood its task not in terms of providing a substantive critique of real world power relations, let alone an alternative normative conception of what social relations might be, but of how to justify critique as such: how to “justify those elements which critique owes to its philosophical origins” (Habermas), albeit in a nonfoundationalist manner. This focus on—if not obsession with—the theoretical problem of how to ground one’s own critique arose largely as an intervention into the now longstanding debate over positivism and scientism in figurations of the relation between theory and practice. As important as this intervention has been for exposing the dangers of, and social/political philosophy’s implication in, a purely technocratic order, it has not been without costs to the very idea of critique itself: namely the crucial connection between critique and social/political transformation. Seyla Benhabib has usefully characterized the two tasks of critical theory as “explanatory-diagnostic” and “anticipatory-utopian.” In this seminar we aim to explore what each of these tasks might be and how they are connected.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction
    INTRODUCTION The overarching aim of this thesis is the articulation of a philosophical notion of an “ethics of thinking,” a kind of thinking that is receptive to the non‑identical character of the world of human and non‑human objects. The task of explicating an ethical way of thinking requires the gesture of stepping out of the common conception of ethics inasmuch as I would like to construe the ethical life as not necessarily constituting a moral system, but something that has real ethical efficacy despite the absence of a transcendental moral system. In this sense, to think about ethics, as “philosophical praxis,” is to think outside ethics, as a system of moral code. The political philosopher Raymond Geuss distinguishes two senses of the word ethics. First is the more common usage as a set of “rules that contain restrictions on the ways in which it is permissible to act toward other people,” and the second refers to a “whole way of seeing the world and thinking about it.”1 The second sense has a broader signification, yet one which has less common usage. In attempting to make sense of what I call the “ethics of thinking,” I would like to follow Geuss’ second description of ethics. Philosophical thinking has always been a way of looking at or thinking about the world and the objects within it. It is in this very rough context that I want the idea of ethics to be construed, that is to say, that philosophy is inextricably related to ethical thinking. This obviously entails a reconfiguration of the practice of 1 Raymond Geuss, Outside Ethics (Princeton University Press, New Jersey, 2005), 6.
    [Show full text]