Plato and His Contemporaries

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Plato and His Contemporaries V Plato and his Contemporaries 1. PLATO’S LIFE As a young man I went through the same experience as many others; I thought that, the very moment I became my own master, I should devote myself to public affairs. And by the hazard of politics a chance of this offered itself to me… thirty rulers were set up with supreme powers. Some of these happened to be relatives and friends of mine, and they at once called me to join in this as my proper work… I paid great attention to what they should do. but I saw that in a little time their behavior had made the former constitution seem a golden age by comparison. For among other crimes, there was their treatment of Socrates… When I saw all this and much else like it, I was indignant and withdrew myself from contact with the evils of that time… I considered these events and the kind of men that were engaged in politics, and the existing laws and customs, and the more I considered and the older I grew, the more difficult did it seem to me to conduct the affairs of the state properly. For it was not possible to effect anything without the aid of friends and associates. And it was not easy to discover such men, even when they existed… The laws and customs, also, went on deteriorating to an extraordinary degree. I did not cease to investigate all possible means of improving these points, and indeed, of reforming the whole constitution, while as far as action went I went on awaiting a favorable opportunity. But in the end I came to the conclusion that all the cities of the present age are badly governed… Plato’s Seventh Letter 324b-326a Plato was born, either in Athens or on the island of Aegina off the Attic coast, in 424/3 BCE.1 Pericles had died the year before in the plague, and Socrates was already forty-two years old. His parents, Ariston and Perictione, were distinctly upper-class. He was the youngest, with two brothers, Glaucon and Adeimantus 1So Debra Nails (2002), who provides the most sophisticated reconstruction of Plato’s life to date, and is to be consulted by anyone interested in the details of Plato’s biography. The date given by Appollodorus is 427. Some Ancient sources say 429. Our chief source for Plato’s life is his Seventh Letter, which is generally assumed to be authentic, but was written by someone near Plato not long after his death if not, and so bears some weight even in that case. We also have some information from later biographers, the best of whom is Diogenes Laertius. They all view Plato, like Pythagoras, as a divinity, and report more in the way of miracles than facts, but Diogenes at least names his sources, and so provides facts vouched for by near contemporaries of Plato himself. For an intelligent and thorough account of problems and sources, see Guthrie’s History IV (1975). For an attractive account of Plato’s life, both thorough and well written, see Field (1930). I.V. Plato and his Contemporaries 2 (who play a role in his Republic), and a sister, Potone, who was the mother of Speusippus, his successor in the Academy. Critias and Charmides, both members of the Thirty in the short-lived oligarchy of 404, were cousin and brother of Plato’s mother. While Plato was still a child his father died, and his mother remarried to her uncle,2 Pyrilampes, a man of political prominence who served as ambassador to Persia and other Asian powers. Pyrilampes’s son, Antiphon, figures in Plato’s Parmenides. Pyrilampes died by 413, and Adeimantus, at 19 years, became his mother’s guardian. The rich and noble families that at first accepted Periclean democracy had gradually been driven into opposition by the unending financial burdens of the war. While Plato was coming to manhood, many near him became determined opponents of the democratic constitution, but he remained somewhat in favor of it, following, it appears, his parents’ lead. He refused to participate in the violent actions of many of his older relatives, and approved of the renewed democracy and its moderation toward its erstwhile opponents, despite its uncharacteristically harsh treatment of his friend and teacher, Socrates. He believed, perhaps, that democracy is the best form of government if one had to endure corruption and incompetence, since it best guards the citizens against the injustice of their fellow citizens in power. Boyhood education in Greece emphasized physical training, a necessity if the boys were to serve well as soldiers. Moreover, athletic contests played an important diplomatic role—there would be a truce during important games, if any wars were on, allowing for negotiation, and games and festivals were established to memorialize, and help maintain, a new alliance. Plato took an interest in wrestling, and as a boy he represented Athens at the Isthmian games at Corinth. He may have been called ‘Plato’, ‘The Broad’, because of his broad shoulders, having been named ‘Aristocles’ by his parents. The arts also formed an important part of an upper-class education. It was a pastime in noble families to recite poetry at dinner parties, and anyone of even moderate culture could turn out passable verse. Plato displayed poetic gifts quite early, and intended a career as a dramatist before Socrates converted him to philosophy. With his education completed he would have served in the cavalry in the last five years of the Peloponnesian War, and probably saw action. It is notable and odd that Plato never married. The tradition is that he was homosexual, and had endured the loss of someone he profoundly loved in his youth, but that would not have ruled out marriage, which was generally regarded as a duty to one’s family. Plato almost certainly heard Socrates before twenty years of age. In 396, several years after Socrates’s 2Such marriages within the family were useful to preserve family estates intact. I.V. Plato and his Contemporaries 3 execution, the young man, now 28, cautiously withdrew to the nearby city of Megara, where he stayed with a fellow philosopher, Euclides. We don’t know how long he was there, but at the latest he would have been summoned home in 395 to serve in the Corinthian War. Possibly Plato wrote the Socratic dialogues at Megara, and it seems reasonable to assume they reflected his own views at the time as well as Socrates’s. After this he may, according to later sources, have visited the mathematician Theodorus in Cyrene, a Greek trading city in Egypt, and perhaps the Socratic Aristippus, living in the same city. He then, about 385, traveled to Syracuse and Sicily, where he saw the Pythagorean Philolaus, and Archytas. It was probably in Sicily that he learned mathematics and Pythagoreanism, and left some of his Socratic views behind. In particular, Plato developed his own views on matters of psychology, views less optimistic than Socrates’s about the possibility of bringing people to wisdom through rational discussion. After a series of preparatory dialogues, the Meno, Protagoras, Gorgias, Lysis and Republic I, in which he explored and criticized Socrates’s philosophy, Plato announced his new views in Republic II–X. He states there that only a few people can learn about the good through dialectic, and this only after long training, much of which is not intellectual training at all. He became convinced that there were multitudes of desires for different things, as opposed to a single desire for the good, many of them irrational inasmuch as they had no root in any belief about the good. He rejected, then, the Socratic view that people are always motivated by a rational desire for the good, following reason as well as they could in pursuit of a life of maximal pleasure, and he also rejected Socrates’s psychological egoism, for he thought one who loves the good rationally will seek the good wherever it is found, even when it is the good of others. Disillusioned by his political experience, he came to think that the personalities of most were distorted by habitual attention to non-rational desires, until many no longer took any interest in rational desires at all.3 The dramatic settings of Plato’s dialogues in the days of the Democracy and Socrates often draws attention to the precarious political situation in Athens. The Symposium is set just months before the incident of the mutilation of the Herms, which led to the political downfall of Alcibiades, Phaedrus, and other chief figures in the dialogue. The Laches, in an arch discussion of Nicias’s confession that divination is a form of wisdom, foreshadows the general’s disastrous delay in removing from Sicily in response to an eclipse of the Moon, a delay that doomed the Athenian army to destruction. Those who enlist Socrates in the discussion in the Republic would soon be executed by the Thirty, and old Cephalus’s profitable armament factory would be confiscated 3See Penner (1992). I.V. Plato and his Contemporaries 4 by their oligarchy. The freedom and rich life under the democracy is balanced by the instability and foolishness of the citizens, easily swayed by demagoguery and rhetoric. The natural and logical result is that Plato shows far less commitment to preserving others’ intellectual autonomy than Socrates. Socrates trusted people to work things out for themselves once they began to examine their own views, and thought it a bad idea to announce and argue for his own views, since that would tend to make people stop investigating the truth.
Recommended publications
  • The Roles of Solon in Plato's Dialogues
    The Roles of Solon in Plato’s Dialogues Dissertation Presented in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Degree Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of The Ohio State University By Samuel Ortencio Flores, M.A. Graduate Program in Greek and Latin The Ohio State University 2013 Dissertation Committee: Bruce Heiden, Advisor Anthony Kaldellis Richard Fletcher Greg Anderson Copyrighy by Samuel Ortencio Flores 2013 Abstract This dissertation is a study of Plato’s use and adaptation of an earlier model and tradition of wisdom based on the thought and legacy of the sixth-century archon, legislator, and poet Solon. Solon is cited and/or quoted thirty-four times in Plato’s dialogues, and alluded to many more times. My study shows that these references and allusions have deeper meaning when contextualized within the reception of Solon in the classical period. For Plato, Solon is a rhetorically powerful figure in advancing the relatively new practice of philosophy in Athens. While Solon himself did not adequately establish justice in the city, his legacy provided a model upon which Platonic philosophy could improve. Chapter One surveys the passing references to Solon in the dialogues as an introduction to my chapters on the dialogues in which Solon is a very prominent figure, Timaeus- Critias, Republic, and Laws. Chapter Two examines Critias’ use of his ancestor Solon to establish his own philosophic credentials. Chapter Three suggests that Socrates re- appropriates the aims and themes of Solon’s political poetry for Socratic philosophy. Chapter Four suggests that Solon provides a legislative model which Plato reconstructs in the Laws for the philosopher to supplant the role of legislator in Greek thought.
    [Show full text]
  • Peitho12.1-2
    Volume 12 Issue 1/2 SPRING/FALL 2010 Peitho www.cwshrc.org a publication of the coalition of women scholars in the history of rhetoric and composition In this issue: Editor’s Letter Holding Hands and Shaking Hands Intentional Mentoring Mentoring, an Incantation Women in Digital Spaces Roundtable Report A Selection of Secondary Texts Concerning Ancient Women Historical Methodology: Past and “Presentism”? Editor’s Letter Peitho fleeing the seduction of Dear all Leda appearing on an Apulian red I am pleased to present to you the combined Spring/Fall 2010 issues of figure vase, ca. 350-340 B.C.E. Peitho. Much of this combined issue focuses on the topic of the Coalition Wednesday night session at the 2010 C’s. Based on feedback from the 2009 J. Paul Getty Museum Used with permission session in San Francisco, the 2010 Louisville session attempted to examine new ways of mentoring and professional development—the remix, revisit, rethink, revise, renew of the conference’s call for papers. We are pleased to present here a number of the presentations from that Coalition Officers session. Marcy Tucker’s “Holding Hands and Shaking Hands: Learning to Profit from the Professional Mentor-Mentee Relationship” argues for looking President Nancy Meyers (Continued on page 5) University of North Carolina at Greensboro Holding Hands and Shaking Hands: Vice-President Elizabeth Tasker Learning to Profit from the Professional Stephen F. Austin State University Mentor-Mentee Relationship Treasurer Lisa Mastrangelo Marcy Tucker College of St. Elizabeth Secretary Scholars and students of feminist movement understand that we should Jenn Fishman never assume that anything is natural to any particular group; however, those University of Tennessee-Knoxville of us who teach rhetoric and composition, and especially those of us who are Member-at-Large female and who support interactive pedagogies, have long contended with Lynée Lewis Gaillet the assumption that we are (or should be) nurturing.
    [Show full text]
  • Olympiodorus the Life of Plato
    Olympiodorus The Life of Plato Translated by George Burges in The Works of Plato: a new and literal version (London: Henry G. Bohn, 1865), volume VI, pp. 232-240. Some of the translator’s notes have been omitted and there are some changes to the text to facilitate easier reading. This document is in the public domain. platonic-philosophy.org Come then, let us speak of the family of the philosopher, not for the sake of prolixity, but of benefit rather and instruction to those, who betake themselves to him. For he was not “a Nobody,” but rather— To many of mankind he was a care. For Plato is said to have been a son of his father Ariston, the son of Aristocles, from whom he carried up his family to Solon, the law-giver; and hence he wrote, in imitation of his ancestor, the Laws in twelve books, and a Political Constitution in eleven. He came into the world by his mother Perictione, who was descended from Neleus, the son of Codrus. For they say that Apollo in a vision had an intercourse with his mother Perictione, and, appearing in the night to Ariston, ordered him to have no connexion with Perictione until the time of her bringing forth. And so he acted. And his parents taking him after his birth, and when he was still an infant, placed him on Mount Hymettus, intending to make a sacrifice to the deities there, namely, Pan, and the Nymphs, and Apollo, who presides over shepherds. But while he was lying there, bees came and filled his mouth with honey from the comb, in order that it might be said truly of him— From his mouth flow’d a voice than honey far more sweet.
    [Show full text]
  • Plato's Defence of the Forms in the Parmenides
    1 Plato’s defence of the Forms in the Parmenides In Plato’s Parmenides we find objections against the Forms which Aristotle in the Metaphysics presents as arguments that refute the theory of Forms. Plato does not refute those objections. This led many philosophers to suppose that the Parmenides initiated a new, critical phase in Plato’s thought, in which he radically revised the theory of Forms presented in the Republic.i I shall argue that Plato in the Parmenides defends the Forms by pointing to his presentation of them in the Republic. Parmenides reflects on his criticism of the Forms in the Parmenides as follows: ‘And yet, these difficulties and many more still in addition necessarily hold of the characters (anankaion echein ta eidȇ), if these characteristics of things that are exist (ei eisin hautai hai ideai tȏn ontȏn), and one is to distinguish each character as something by itself (kai horieitai tis auto hekaston eidos). The result is that the hearer is perplexed and contends that they do not exist, and that even if their existence is conceded, they are necessarily unknowable by human nature. In saying this, he thinks he is saying something significant (kai tauta legonta dokein ti legein) and, as we just remarked (kai, ho arti elegomen), it’s astonishingly hard to convince him to the contrary. Only a man of considerable natural gifts will be able to understand that there is a certain kind of each thing, a nature and reality alone by itself, and it will take a man more remarkable still to discover it and be able to instruct someone else who has examined all these difficulties with sufficient care.’ (134e-135b, tr.
    [Show full text]
  • The Divine Plato Among Greeks and Romans: Banquet Literature and the Making of Cultural Memory in the Graeco-Roman Empire Anthony Andurand, Corinne Bonnet
    The divine Plato among Greeks and Romans: Banquet literature and the making of cultural memory in the Graeco-Roman Empire Anthony Andurand, Corinne Bonnet To cite this version: Anthony Andurand, Corinne Bonnet. The divine Plato among Greeks and Romans: Banquet literature and the making of cultural memory in the Graeco-Roman Empire. Archimède : archéologie et histoire ancienne, UMR7044 - Archimède, 2019, La République “ gréco-romaine ” des lettres : construction des réseaux savants et circulation des savoirs dans l’Empire romain, HS N°1, pp.42-53. halshs-02091579 HAL Id: halshs-02091579 https://halshs.archives-ouvertes.fr/halshs-02091579 Submitted on 5 Apr 2019 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. REVUE , RCHIMeDE ARCHÉOLOGIE ET HISTOIRE ANCIENNE HO, RS SERIE THE DIVINE PLATO AMONG GREEKS AND ROMANS: BANQUET LITERATURE AND THE MAKING OF CULTURAL MEMORY IN THE GRAECO-ROMAN EMPIRE [1] Anthony ANDURAND Corinne BONNET Docteur en Sciences de l’Antiquité Professeur d’Histoire grecque Université Toulouse – Jean Jaurès Université Toulouse – Jean Jaurès EA 4601 PLH-ERASME EA 4601 PLH-ERASME [email protected] [email protected] RÉSUMÉ Les grandes fi gures exemplaires et les épisodes mémorables du passé de la Grèce et de Rome constituent un des matériaux à partir desquels Paradigmatic fi gures and memorable episodes from s’élaborent, au présent, les discussions mises the Greek and Roman past are one of the key mate- en scène dans les Propos de table.
    [Show full text]
  • Women in Early Pythagoreanism
    Women in Early Pythagoreanism Caterina Pellò Faculty of Classics University of Cambridge Clare Hall February 2018 This dissertation is submitted for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Alla nonna Ninni, che mi ha insegnato a leggere e scrivere Abstract Women in Early Pythagoreanism Caterina Pellò The sixth-century-BCE Pythagorean communities included both male and female members. This thesis focuses on the Pythagorean women and aims to explore what reasons lie behind the prominence of women in Pythagoreanism and what roles women played in early Pythagorean societies and thought. In the first chapter, I analyse the social conditions of women in Southern Italy, where the first Pythagorean communities were founded. In the second chapter, I compare Pythagorean societies with ancient Greek political clubs and religious sects. Compared to mainland Greece, South Italian women enjoyed higher legal and socio-political status. Similarly, religious groups included female initiates, assigning them authoritative roles. Consequently, the fact that the Pythagoreans founded their communities in Croton and further afield, and that in some respects these communities resembled ancient sects helps to explain why they opened their doors to the female gender to begin with. The third chapter discusses Pythagoras’ teachings to and about women. Pythagorean doctrines did not exclusively affect the followers’ way of thinking and public activities, but also their private way of living. Thus, they also regulated key aspects of the female everyday life, such as marriage and motherhood. I argue that the Pythagorean women entered the communities as wives, mothers and daughters. Nonetheless, some of them were able to gain authority over their fellow Pythagoreans and engage in intellectual activities, thus overcoming the female traditional domestic roles.
    [Show full text]
  • Durham Research Online
    Durham Research Online Deposited in DRO: 05 August 2016 Version of attached le: Published Version Peer-review status of attached le: Peer-reviewed Citation for published item: Horky, Phillip Sidney. (2015) 'Pseudo-Archytas protreptics? On Wisdom in its context.', in Second sailing : alternative perspectives on Plato. Helsinki: Societas Scientiarum Fennica, pp. 21-39. Commentationes humanarum litterarum. (132). Further information on publisher's website: https://www.tiedekirja./default/second-sailing-alternative-perspectives-on-plato.html Publisher's copyright statement: Additional information: Use policy The full-text may be used and/or reproduced, and given to third parties in any format or medium, without prior permission or charge, for personal research or study, educational, or not-for-prot purposes provided that: • a full bibliographic reference is made to the original source • a link is made to the metadata record in DRO • the full-text is not changed in any way The full-text must not be sold in any format or medium without the formal permission of the copyright holders. Please consult the full DRO policy for further details. Durham University Library, Stockton Road, Durham DH1 3LY, United Kingdom Tel : +44 (0)191 334 3042 | Fax : +44 (0)191 334 2971 https://dro.dur.ac.uk Societas Scientiurom Fennica Commentationes Humanarum Litterarum 132 2015 The Finnish Society of Scknces and Letters Address: Fabianinkaru 4 B 16, FIN~ 00130 Helsinki, Finland In Swedish: Finska Vetenskaps-Societeten, Fabiansgatan 4 B 16, FIN-· 00130 Helsingfurs In Finnish: Suomen 11edeseura, Fabianinkaru 4 B 16,00130 Helsinki Commentationer. Humanarun Litterarum 1ht series, founded in 1923, publishes since 1996 monographs on antiquity and its tradition, SECOND SAILING: Editor: Alternative Perspectives on Plato Pro£ cm.
    [Show full text]
  • The Platonic Art of Philosophy
    THE PLATONIC ART OF PHILOSOPHY edited by GEORGE BOYSSTONES DIMITRI EL MURR and CHRISTOPHER GILL University Printing House, Cambridge CB 2 8 BS , United Kingdom Published in the United States of America by Cambridge University Press, New York Cambridge University Press is part of the University of Cambridge. It furthers the University’s mission by disseminating knowledge in the pursuit of education, learning and research at the highest international levels of excellence. www.cambridge.org Information on this title: www.cambridge.org/9781107038981 © Cambridge University Press 2013 Th is publication is in copyright. Subject to statutory exception and to the provisions of relevant collective licensing agreements, no reproduction of any part may take place without the written permission of Cambridge University Press. First published 2013 Printed in the United Kingdom by CPI Group Ltd, Croydon CR 0 4 YY A catalogue record for this publication is available from the British Library Library of Congress Cataloguing in Publication data Th e platonic art of philosophy / edited by George Boys-Stones, Dimitri El Murr and Christopher Gill. pages cm Includes bibliographical references and index. isbn 978-1-107-03898-1 1. Plato. I. Boys-Stones, G. R., editor of compilation. b395.p5375 2013 184–dc23 2013008186 isbn 978-1-107-03898-1 Hardback Cambridge University Press has no responsibility for the persistence or accuracy of URL s for external or third-party internet websites referred to in this publication, and does not guarantee that any content on such websites is, or will remain, accurate or appropriate. chapter fourteen Th e Atlantis poem in the Timaeus-Critias Mauro Tulli Introduction After his archonship in 594–592 BC , Solon went to visit Amasis in Egypt and Croesus in Lydia.
    [Show full text]
  • 4 the Problem of Women Philosophers in Ancient Greece
    er.. - - 71 •. r 4 The. Problem of Women philosophised is remarkahly small. Furthermore. I shall draw attention to nutjor methodological diffrculliesRichard involved Hawley in the study of the literary sources for the lives of these women. A pattern will develop that informs these sources, a patlern of women philosophers as anomalies whose depal1ure fro'." recognised social behaviour requires special explanation. These expla­ Philosophers in Ancient nations oflcn resort to the forniliar conccplUal link bclwcen women and the �orld of the senses, the physical, rather than that of the rational, the Greece· mtellectual. I shall confine my discussion to between the sixth century BC Hawley and the first century AD, thus avoiding Hypatia. The sources for Hypatia Richard are ate and bound up with the complexities involved in the study of any ! _ Chmtian ltterature of the period. As such she deserves to be studied sepa­ rately. Nor shall I discuss the complex and already well-documented case of Oh! There I met those few congenial maids Aspasia. Instead, I shall turn my attention to 'forgotten' woinen.' . Whom love hath warm'd, in philosophic shades; There still Leontium, on her sage's breast, Found lore and love, was tutor' d and caress' d; VIEWS OF THE MALE PHILOSOPHERS And there the clasp of Pythia's gentle arms ·Repaid the zeal which deified her char!ns. It is possible lha1 lhc fir.s1 .school to have encouraged the study of philoso­ The Attic Master, in Aspasia's eyes, phy by womc was lhat of the Pythagoreans in the mid-sixth century BC.
    [Show full text]
  • Plato's Philosophy of Education and the Common Core Debate
    Plato’s Philosophy of Education and the Common Core debate Conference Paper Association for the Development of Philosophy Teaching (ADOPT) Spring Conference, Chicago, IL. De Paul University April 25, 2015 Madonna Murphy, Ph.D., University of St. Francis EDUCATION IN ANCIENT GREECE In Greece we find the origins of many of our educational policies and systems as it is the originating sources of Western civilization. Greek ideas about education and their educational practices have been very influential to other cultures. One of Rome's greatest service to mankind is that it carried the Greek tradition to all the Western lands. Greek civilization developed between 1200 and 490 B.C. It is in the Age of Pericles, around 500 B.C., that we see the first organized effort in a Western society for formal education. 1 The study of ancient Greek civilization provides valuable lessons on citizenship and civic education that illustrates the important role of education in shaping good citizens. Textual analysis of his various dialogues reveals Plato’s views on the purpose of education, what it is that should be taught to others and how the teacher should impart this knowledge. Plato’s educational thought illuminates many problems today’s educators face: Who are worthy models for children to imitate? How does education help to shape good citizenship? How does education serve humankind’s search for truth? In particular we will extrapolate Plato’s response the current common core debate. PLATO’S LIFE AND FAMILY We know about Plato and his family from the comments he makes in his dialogues.
    [Show full text]
  • Copyrighted Material
    the life of plato of athens 1 The Life of Plato of Athens DEBRA NAILS Plato died in the first year of the hundred and eighth Olympiad in the thirteenth year of the reign of Philip of Macedon – 347 bce by contemporary reckoning – and was buried at the Academy.1 So venerable and so widespread was the philosopher’s repu- tation that mythologizing was inevitable and prolonged: Plato was sired by the god Apollo and born to the virgin Perictione; he was born on the seventh of Thargelion, Apollo’s birthday, and the bees of Mount Hymettus dripped honey into the mouth of the newborn babe. Renaissance Platonists celebrated Plato’s birth on the seventh of November, the same day his death was commemorated. Woodbridge’s 1929 The Son of Apollo begins, “The demand of history that we be accurate contends with the demand of admiration that we be just. Caught between the two, biographers of Plato have written, not the life of a man, but tributes to a genius.” Genius he certainly was, but he deserves better than a tribute and better than the standard vita cut to fit the pattern of the Alexandrian librarian Apollodorus who divided ancient lives into four twenty-year periods with an akmB at age 40.2 By this scheme, Plato is duly born in 427, meets Socrates at age 20 (when Socrates is 60), founds the Academy at 40, voyages to Sicily at 60, and dies at the age of 80. Ample evidence belies the neat fit. Plato of Collytus, son of Ariston – for that was his full legal name, under which he had rights of Athenian citizenship and by which his name will have been recorded on the Aegis tribal lists – was born in 424/3, the fourth child of Ariston of Collytus, son of Aristocles, and Perictione, daughter of Glaucon; Ariston and Perictione had married by 432.
    [Show full text]
  • Teaching Ancient Women Philosophers: a Case Study
    Feminist Philosophy Quarterly Volume 6 | Issue 3 Article 3 2020 Teaching Ancient Women Philosophers: A Case Study Sara Protasi University of Puget Sound [email protected] Recommended Citation Protasi, Sara. “Teaching Ancient Women Philosophers: A Case Study.” Feminist Philosophy Quarterly 6 (3). Article 3. Protasi – Teaching Ancient Women Philosophers Teaching Ancient Women Philosophers: A Case Study Sara Protasi Abstract In this paper I discuss in some detail my experience teaching women philosophers in the context of a survey course in ancient Greek philosophy at a small liberal arts college. My aim is to share the peculiar difficulties one may encounter when teaching this topic in a lower-level undergraduate course, difficulties stemming from a multiplicity of methodological hurdles that do not arise when teaching women philosophers in other periods, such as the modern era. In the first section, I briefly review some of what we know about ancient Greek women philosophers, which is not only very little but frustratingly uncertain and highly debated. I devote the second section to some of the scholarly debates surrounding these philosophers’ doctrines, the details of their biographies, and their very existence. The third section is about the corresponding pedagogical challenges, and the fourth and final section describes the strategies I implemented to face those challenges. Keywords: women philosophers, ancient female philosophers, Greek philosophy, Greek women, teaching ancient philosophy, teaching women philosophers, Hypatia, Diotima, neo-Pythagorean women The idea that we ought to expand the Western philosophical canon is gaining traction and becoming accepted in mainstream philosophy. Scholars and teachers in the anglophone world are actively and successfully incorporating non-Western traditions and figures and, more generally, neglected epistemic perspectives in their research and in their teaching.
    [Show full text]