God and the Problem of Evil: a Reformed Analytic Inquiry

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

God and the Problem of Evil: a Reformed Analytic Inquiry God and the Problem of Evil: A Reformed Analytic Inquiry by Stephen Mutavdzija A Thesis submitted to the Faculty of Knox College and the Theology Department of the Toronto School of Theology In partial fulfilment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Theology awarded by Knox College and the University of Toronto © Copyright by Stephen Mutavdzija 2017 God and the Problem of Evil: A Reformed Analytic Inquiry Stephen Mutavdzija Master of Theology Knox College and the University of Toronto 2017 Abstract In this thesis I argue that a Reformed epistemological approach to the problem of evil is more than sufficient in demonstrating the coherence of theism through logical and probable reasoning. I do this by examining various objections and challenges to theism posited by J.L. Mackie and Paul Draper, and contrast them with reasoning found in the works of Alvin Plantinga and likeminded supporters of the Reformed epistemology using analytic philosophical methodology. ii To Jure and Milica Mutavdzija iii Acknowledgements In preparing this thesis I must acknowledge those who supported me throughout its construction, mainly, my advisors Charles Fensham, Peter Slater, and John Vissers. Thanks go out to Knox College for their financial support and resources, as well as St. Andrew’s Presbyterian Church, Hillsburgh, ON. Heather Paton Wright’s encouragement throughout the early stages of this undertaking must be noted. Finally, I owe a great debt of gratitude to Richard Brian Davis who introduced me to analytic philosophy many years ago and taught me the importance of loving God with all my mind. iv CONTENTS Chapter 1. Introduction .......................................................................................................... 1 2. Overview ………………………………………………………………………... 6 Preliminary Remarks: From Wittgenstein to Plantinga Ludwig Wittgenstein: Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus Philosophical Investigations Alvin Plantinga: Reformed Epistemology 3. Methodology ....................................................................................................... 15 The logical problem of evil Concepts pertaining to proper functionalism The evidential problem of evil Defining rational discourse 4. Critical Examination ........................................................................................... 24 The logical challenge Evil and omnipotence God, freedom, and evil The evidential challenge Pleasure and pain (the biological role of good and evil) On being evidentially challenged 5. Analysis and Evaluation ……………………………………………………….. 74 6. Conclusion .......................................................................................................... 88 Bibliography ............................................................................................................. 91 v Chapter 1 Introduction Some of the most vexing questions each one of us has to wrestle with are those pertaining to the problem of evil. Evil is something with which we are all familiar. It is constantly lurking in the background of the world in which we live, hurting the innocent and bringing pain to the most vulnerable and gentle of people in society. But what exactly is the problem of evil and for whom? How should we go about seeking some kind of resolution to it? As I see it, the problem of evil is more than simply a problem. It would be more accurate to say that there are various problems surrounding discourse on evil rather than the problem of evil, not only because the amount of evil in the world is so great, but also because there are multiple ways in which people interpret evil and the different perceptions cry out for answers. Some philosophers see the problem of evil as one belonging to God. How can the classically understood omnibenevolent, omnipotent, and omniscient god allow evil to exist in his created universe? This question has been the focus of debate within philosophy of religion for quite some time. Its Western historical written inquiry began with Epicurus sometime in the fourth century B.C.E. and since then has reared its head in the writings of people throughout the modern era such as Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz and David Hume, not to mention authors in the 20th and 21st century, in the works of Antony Flew, J.L. Mackie, and Paul Draper. Within analytic philosophy of religion, Christian philosophers have felt the need to engage the most powerful arguments against the existence of God. Taking seriously the undeniable presence of evil in the world, Christian thinkers have responded to attacks on belief in God’s existence with intellectual rigor and creativity. One of the greatest theist voices to enter contemporary dialogues and debates is Christian Reformed philosopher, Alvin Plantinga, 1 2 who, according to an article in Time magazine, published in April 1980, was said to be the “world’s leading Protestant philosopher of God.”1 Since the 1960s, Plantinga has had several books published in the areas of metaphysics, epistemology, and philosophy of religion.2 The focus of this thesis will seek to defend a Reformed theistic stance against the most pressing challenges posed by contemporary atheists and agnostics within analytic philosophy of religion. When analytic philosophers of religion discuss the problem of evil, they typically engage in discussion about whether or not affirmations of the existence of evil and the existence of God are compatible or plausible. Some philosophers have argued that the obviously warranted belief in the existence of evil and belief in an omnibenevolent, omniscient, and omnipotent god3 is incoherent or nonsensical and ought to be abandoned due to an implicit logical contradiction.4 Such was the case with Antony Flew and his employment of falsification 1 "Modernizing the Case for God", Time, April 5, 1980. 2 Some of his more current books are transcribed debates between the prominent atheist philosophers of our time. See Alvin Plantinga and Michael Tooley, Knowledge of God (Oxford: Blackwell, 2008), Alvin Plantinga and Daniel Dennett, Science and Religion: Are They Compatible? (New York: Oxford University Press, 2011). 3 Some Christian theologians and philosophers oppose this description of God, arguing that the properties mentioned above are formulations of Greek thought rather than Hebrew understandings of the divine. For example, in “The Divine Power and the Creature,” Paul Tillich has us consider thinking about God as Being itself: “With respect to time, omnipotence is eternity; with respect to space, it is omnipresence; and with respect to the subject-object structure of being, it is omniscience. These symbols must now be interpreted. Causality and substance in relation to being-itself were discussed in the symbol of God as the “creative ground” of being, in which the term ‘creative’ contained and transcended causality, while the term “ground” contained and transcended substance.” Linwood Urban and Douglas N. Walton, ed. The Power of God: Readings on Omnipotence and Evil (New York: Oxford University Press, 1978), 48. However, throughout this thesis, the concept of God should be understood to possess, among other things, the classical properties based on reasoning articulated by Thomas Williams. “We cannot know what scripture means unless we use reason to separate and distinguish defensible interpretations from indefensible ones. If scripture is interpreted to make God less than the greatest conceivable being or to imply that God is unjust, reason tells us that scripture does not mean that and gives us tools to discern the true meaning.” Reason and Faith: Philosophy in the Middle Ages, Thomas Williams (The Teaching Company, 2007), DVD. 4 In his chapter entitled “Can God’s Existence be Disproved?” J.N. Findlay states it as such. 3 theory5, and that of J.L. Mackie.6 Although these views held much sway in Western philosophy departments for decades on end in the 19th and 20th centuries, the debate has continued to remain an open case since the late 1960s. This thesis will briefly map out some of the early analytic developments of the 20th century works of those such as Gottlob Frege, Bertrand Russell, and Ludwig Wittgenstein in order to situate ourselves in current Western debates. Hopefully this will prove helpful to understanding the thesis as a whole because the tradition from which Alvin Plantinga, along with his interlocutors engage debate, find their roots in these early thinkers. The primary historical discussion will examine the early and later work of Wittgenstein, mainly because his work is still highly relevant within theological discourse at the Toronto School of Theology, but also because he captures much analytic thought as it progressed during early development. After writing some preliminary remarks about the historical development of the analytic method, I shall then go on to discuss some key concepts that are of utmost importance to understanding Plantinga’s thoughts and refutations. Such concepts include de re/de dicto distinctions, possible worlds, and essentialism, to name a few. This exposition will ensure that the thesis will be clear, concise, and intelligible. In addition, I shall also briefly introduce Bayesian methodology, which concerns itself with probability and rational belief. This seems necessary, not because “For we try to show that the Divine Existence can only be conceived, in a religiously satisfactory manner, if we also conceive it as something inescapable and necessary, whether for thought or reality. From which it follows that our modern denial of necessity
Recommended publications
  • Theodicy: an Overview
    1 Theodicy: An Overview Introduction All of us struggle at one time or another in life with why evil happens to someone, either ourselves, our family, our friends, our nation, or perhaps some particularly disturbing instance in the news—a child raped, a school shooting, genocide in another country, a terrorist bombing. The following material is meant to give an overview of the discussion of this issue as it takes place in several circles, especially that of the Christian church. I. The Problem of Evil Defined Three terms, "the problem of evil," "theodicy," and "defense" are important to our discussion. The first two are often used as synonyms, but strictly speaking the problem of evil is the larger issue of which theodicy is a subset because one can have a secular problem of evil. Evil is understood as a problem when we seek to explain why it exists (Unde malum?) and what its relationship is to the world as a whole. Indeed, something might be considered evil when it calls into question our basic trust in the order and structure of our world. Peter Berger in particular has argued that explanations of evil are necessary for social structures to stay themselves against chaotic forces. It follows, then, that such an explanation has an impact on the whole person. As David Blumenthal observes, a good theodicy is one that has three characteristics: 1. "[I]t should leave one with one’s sense of reality intact." (It tells the truth about reality.) 2. "[I]t should leave one empowered within the intellectual-moral system in which one lives." (Namely, it should not deny God’s basic power or goodness.) 3.
    [Show full text]
  • From Existential Feelings to Belief in God
    From Existential Feelings to Belief in God Submitted by Gorazd Andrejč to the University of Exeter as a thesis for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Theology In December 2012 This thesis is available for Library use on the understanding that it is copyright material and that no quotation from the thesis may be published without proper acknowledgement. I certify that all material in this thesis which is not my own work has been identified and that no material has previously been submitted and approved for the award of a degree by this or any other University. Signature: ………………………………………………………….. 2 This thesis is dedicated with deep gratitude to my wife Žaklina, my son Natan, and my parents Alojz and Jožica Andrejč. Their love and immeasurable sacrifice made this work possible. I also wish to express my sincere gratitude to my supervisor Dr Mark Wynn whose guidance, expertise, encouragement and friendship was invaluable; and to my friend Bradley Arnold, who spent countless hours discussing and critically engaging with the ideas presented here. SDG 3 4 ABSTRACT The question of the relation between religious experience and Christian belief in God is addressed in radically different ways within contemporary theology and philosophy of religion. In order to develop an answer which avoids the pitfalls of the ‘analytic perception model’ (Alston, Yandell, Swinburne) and the ‘over- linguistic’ model for interpreting Christian religious experience (Taylor, Lindbeck), this thesis offers an approach which combines a phenomenological study of feelings, conceptual investigation of Christian God-talk and ‘belief’-talk, as well as theological, sociological and anthropological perspectives.
    [Show full text]
  • Lebel Lecture in Christian Ethics, March 6, 2006 What Are They Saying About Conversion?
    Lebel Lecture in Christian Ethics, March 6, 2006 What are they Saying about Conversion? New Insights, Many Models By Douglas H. Shantz, PhD, University of Calgary Introduction 1. The Importance of this Topic There are several factors behind my choice of topic this evening. For one, conversions are in the news. There have been media reports of such famous converts as Anne Rice the novelist, Naomi Wolf the feminist, and Antony Flew the philosopher. Last October 31, Newsweek magazine reported, “Anne Rice: Queen of the Occult Finds God.” At age 64 Rice, the onetime chronicler of vampires and witches, has apparently returned to the Catholic Church she left at age 18, and says all her future books will be written “only for the Lord.” After experiencing a diabetic coma in 1998, the death of her husband of 41 years in 2002, almost dying herself in 2004, and sinking into despair, she now views Christ as the ultimate hero.1 Her most recent book is, Christ the Lord: Out of Egypt, a novel about the 7 year old Jesus as narrated by Christ himself. This past January 22, 2006 an article in the Sunday Herald began: “Naomi Wolf, one of America’s foremost feminist thinkers, has found a spiritual awakening in God after experiencing a ‘mystical encounter’ with Jesus.” “The most widely read feminist of her generation,” Wolf is best known as the author of The Beauty Myth, her 1991 book against the cosmetics industry. In therapy recently for writer’s block, while practicing meditation, she experienced a holographic (three dimensional) image of Jesus.
    [Show full text]
  • There Is a God
    godthere is a How the World’s Most Notorious Atheist Changed His Mind Antony Flew with Roy Abraham Varghese contents Preface v introduction 1 part i: my denial of the divine 7 1. The Creation of an Atheist 9 2. Where the Evidence Leads 31 3. Atheism Calmly Considered 65 part ii: my discovery of the divine 83 4. A Pilgrimage of Reason 85 5. Who Wrote the Laws of Nature? 95 6. Did the Universe Know We Were Coming? 113 7. How Did Life Go Live? 123 8. Did Something Come from Nothing? 133 9. Finding Space for God 147 10. Open to Omnipotence 155 iii iv contents Appendices 159 Appendix A The “New Atheism”: A Critical Appraisal of Dawkins, Dennett, Wolpert, Harris, and Stenger Roy Abraham Varghese 161 Appendix B The Self-Revelation of God in Human History: A Dialogue on Jesus with N.T. Wright 185 Notes 215 About the Author Praise Credits Cover Copyright About the Publisher preface “ amous Atheist Now Believes in God: One of World’s FLeading Atheists Now Believes in God, More or Less, Based on Scientific Evidence.” This was the head- line of a December 9, 2004, Associated Press story that went on to say: “A British philosophy professor who has been a leading champion of atheism for more than a half century has changed his mind. He now believes in God more or less based on scientific evidence, and says so on a video released Thursday.” Almost immediately, the announcement became a media event touching off reports and commentaries around the globe on radio and TV, in newspapers and on Internet sites.
    [Show full text]
  • A Philosophical Audacity
    A Philosophical Audacity Barth’s Notion of Experience Between Neo-Kantianism and Nietzsche1 Anthony Feneuil [email protected] This is the peer reviewed version of the following article: “A Philosophical Audacity: Barth’s Notion of Experience Between Neo-Kantianism and Nietzsche“, which has been published in final form at http://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/ijst.12077/full. This article may be used for non-commercial purposes in accordance With Wiley Terms and Conditions for self-archiving Abstract: This article addresses Barth’s dialectical notion of experience in the 1920s. I argue that the theoretical problem raised by recent studies on Barth’s notion of experience after his break with liberalism (i.e., the apparent inconsistency between Barth’s move towards an increasingly neo-Kantian understanding of experience and his emphasis on the existential and psychological dimensions of experience) can be solved by the hypothesis of a Nietzschean influence on Barth's epistemology in the 1920s. I defend not only the historical plausibility but also the conceptual fecundity of such a hypothesis, which casts a new light on Barth’s relation to philosophy and the notion of experience, and lays the basis for a consistent Barthian theology of experience. *** Theology is not a discreet slice of knowledge you could simply add to one philosophy or other. It exists nowhere but through philosophy, and that is why Barth’s theological innovation cannot manifest itself apart from philosophical innovation. Barth is not a philosopher, and he does not explicitly develop his concepts in a philosophical way. But Barth repeatedly claims we cannot grant theology an extraordinary status among human discourses.
    [Show full text]
  • Interpreting the Theology of Barth in Light of Nietzsche's Dictum “God Is Dead”
    Interpreting the theology of Barth in light of Nietzsche’s dictum “God is dead” André J Groenewald Pastor: Presbyterian Church of Scotland Edinburgh, Scotland Abstract Karl Barth responded with his theology to Nietzsche’s dictum “God is dead” by stating that God is the living God. God does not need the human race to exist. God reveals God self to humankind whenever God wills. Barth agreed with Nietzsche that the god of the nineteenth century was a “Nicht-Gott”. The article aims to discus Karl Barth’s respons to Nietzsche’s impulse towards the development of a concept of God that would lead to neither atheism nor theism. The article argues that Barth paved the way for talking about God by defining God as the “communicative God”. 1. INTRODUCTION In his book, Die fröhliche Wissenschaft, originally written in 1882, Nietzsche tells about a mad man who runs around in a marketplace looking for “God” (Nietzsche 1973:159). Since he cannot find God, he can only reach one conclusion. God is dead! Nietzsche did not per se deny or affirm the existence of God. He announced the death of the god of modernity (Ward [1997] 1998:xxix; Groenewald 2005:146). He had a problem with the notion of “Fortschritt” according to which history has proven that human beings develop to greater heights of their own accord and that the potential for progress is intrinsic to humankind (Nietzsche 1969a:169; 1972: 304, 309, 310; see Jensen 2006:47, 51). “God’s existence and providence could then be proven on account of this optimistic progress in the course of history” (Groenewald 2005:146).
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophia Christi Vol
    PHILOSOPHIA CHRISTI VOL. 9, NO. 2 © 2007 Antony Flew’s Deism Revisited A Review Essay on There Is a God GARY R. HABERMAS Department of Philosophy and Theology Liberty University Lynchburg, Virginia There Is a God: How the World’s Most Notorious Atheist Changed His Mind. By Antony Flew and Roy Abraham Varghese. New York: HarperCollins, 2007. 256 pages. $24.95. When preeminent philosophical atheist Antony Flew announced in 2004 that he had come to believe in God’s existence and was probably best con- sidered a deist, the reaction from both believers and skeptics was “off the chart.” Few religious stories had this sort of appeal and impact, across the spectrum, both popular as well as theoretical. No recent change of mind has received this much attention. Flew responded by protesting that his story really did not deserve this much interest. But as he explained repeatedly, he simply had to go where the evidence led. Some Background It was this last sentence, repeated often in interviews, that really inter- ested me. Having known Tony well over more than twenty years, I had heard him repeat many things like it, as well as other comments that might be termed “open minded.” He had insisted that he was open to God’s existence, to special revelation, to miracles, to an afterlife, or to David Hume being in error on this or that particular point. To be truthful, I tended to set aside his comments, thinking that while they were made honestly, perhaps Tony still was not as open as he had thought.
    [Show full text]
  • "The Presumptuousness of Atheism" by Paul Copan
    "The Presumptuousness of Atheism" by Paul Copan Atheist Antony Flew has said that the "onus of proof must lie upon the theist." 1Unless compelling reasons for God’s existence can be given, there is the "presumption of atheism." Another atheist, Michael Scriven, considers the lack of evidence for God’s existence and the lack of evidence for Santa Claus on the same level. 2However, the presumption of atheism actually turns out to be presumptuousness . The Christian must remember that the atheist also shares the burden of proof, which I will attempt to demonstrate below. First, even if the theist could not muster good arguments for God’s existence, atheism still would not be shown to be true. 3The outspoken atheist Kai Nielsen recognizes this: "To show that an argument is invalid or unsound is not to show that the conclusion of the argument is false....All the proofs of God’s existence may fail, but it still may be the case that God exists." 4 Second, the "presumption of atheism" demonstrates a rigging of the rules of philosophical debate in order to play into the hands of the atheist, who himself makes a truth claim. Alvin Plantinga correctly argues that the atheist does not treat the statements "God exists" and "God does not exist" in the same manner. 5The atheist assumes that if one has no evidence for God’s existence, then one is obligated to believe that God does not exist — whether or not one has evidence against God’s existence. What the atheist fails to see is that atheism is just as much a claim to know something ("God does not exist") as theism ("God exists").
    [Show full text]
  • On Flew's Compatibilism and His Objections to Theistic Libertarianism
    On Flew’s Compatibilism and His Objections to Theistic Libertarianism 2015/25 115 Kaygı Uludağ Üniversitesi Fen-Edebiyat Fakültesi Felsefe Dergisi Uludağ University Faculty of Arts and Sciences Journal of Philosophy Sayı 25 / Issue 25│Bahar 2015 / Fall 2015 ISSN: 1303-4251 Research Article Araştırma Makalesi Hakan GUNDOGDU* Doç.Dr. | Assoc.Prof.Dr. Gazi University, Faculty of Arts, Department of Philosophy, Ankara-Turkey [email protected] On Flew’s Compatibilism and His Objections to Theistic Libertarianism Abstract Flew strongly defends a compatibilist thesis in the free will debate before going on to totally object to theistic libertarianism. His objections basically rely on his compatibilism embracing the notion of agent causation, which is not very common in compatibilist theses. Since he is a strong proponent of ordinary language philosophy, he also holds that linguistic analyses can certainly solve the free will problem as well as many other problems of philosophy. In doing so, he first uses the paradigm cases based on our common sense experience and then assumes the verity of principle of alternative possibilities. This study attempts to show, on the one hand, that there are some serious difficulties in both his justification of compatibilism and his objections to theistic libertarianism, and on the other hand, that he cannot easily defend both at the same time. Keywords Antony Flew, Compatibilism, Free-Will, Agent, Causation, Theistic Libertarianism, Paradigm Case Argument, Principle of Alternative Possibility. * This study was funded by the Scientific and Research Council of Turkey (TUBITAK): 2219 / 1059B191400716. On Flew’s Compatibilism and His Objections to Theistic Libertarianism 116 2015/25 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Emergentism As an Option in the Philosophy of Religion: Between Materialist Atheism and Pantheism
    SURI 7 (2) 2019: 1-22 Emergentism as an Option in the Philosophy of Religion: Between Materialist Atheism and Pantheism James Franklin University of New South Wales Abstract: Among worldviews, in addition to the options of materialist atheism, pantheism and personal theism, there exists a fourth, “local emergentism”. It holds that there are no gods, nor does the universe overall have divine aspects or any purpose. But locally, in our region of space and time, the properties of matter have given rise to entities which are completely different from matter in kind and to a degree god-like: consciousnesses with rational powers and intrinsic worth. The emergentist option is compared with the standard alternatives and the arguments for and against it are laid out. It is argued that, among options in the philosophy of religion, it involves the minimal reworking of the manifest image of common sense. Hence it deserves a place at the table in arguments as to the overall nature of the universe. Keywords: Emergence; pantheism; personal theism; naturalism; consciousness 1. INTRODUCTION The main options among world views are normally classifiable as either materialist atheism, pantheism (widely understood) or personal theism. According to materialist atheism, there exists nothing except the material universe as we ordinarily conceive it, and its properties are fully described by science (present or future). According to personal theism, there exists a separate entity (or entities) of a much higher form than those found in the 2019 Philosophical Association of the Philippines 2 Emergentism as an Option in the Philosophy of Religion material universe, a god or gods.
    [Show full text]
  • The Dœtrine of Atondieni' in the Theology of Paul Tillich
    THE DŒTRINE OF ATONDIENI' IN THE THEOLOGY OF PAUL TILLICH Art.hington Frank Thompson, B.A., B.Th. A thesis submitted to the Faculty of Graduate Studies and Researeh in partial .f'ul.filment of the requirements for the degree of Mast er of Sa.cred Theology. Depa.rtment of Divinity, McGill UniversitT, Montreal. April, 1960. ii The author of this thesis wishes to express his gratitude to Dr. James S. Thomson of the Faculty of Divinity, McGill University for his patient direction of a sometimes hazardous enterprise. Mention should be made too of the author' s indebtedness to Dr. William R. Coleman, of Huron College, London, Ontario, through whom he was first intro­ duced to the writings of Paul Tillich. iii TABIE OF CONI'ENrS Page INI'RODUCTION 1 I. A SYSTEMATIC APOIDGETIC THEOLOGY 5 An Apologetic Theology 6 The Method of Correlation 13 Tillich t s Ontolo~ am The Problem of The ystem 20 II. THE HUMAN Sri'UATION 32 Existentialism and Atonement. 33 PhilosoJfly and The Fall 39 Estrangement 45 Evil 52 III. THE DOCTRINE OF GOD AND THE DOCTRINE OF ATONEMENT 59 God as 1Being-Itself' 60 Images and Atonement 69 God and The Processes of Atonement 74 IV. THE DOCTRINE OF ATOrmŒ:m' The New Being S5 Atonement in Christ 94 Atonement as The Act of God 100 Atonement in The Cross and The Reasurrection 106 Atonement in History llO COJ.CWSION ll7 BIBLIOGRAPHY INI'RODUCTION The doctrine of atonement attempts to elaborate the statement of the Creed that it was "for us men and for our salvation" that Jesus Christ was born, lived, died and rose again.
    [Show full text]
  • Patterns in Spiritual Awakening: a Study of Augustine, Coleridge and Eliot
    American University in Cairo AUC Knowledge Fountain Theses and Dissertations 6-1-2017 Patterns in spiritual awakening: A study of Augustine, Coleridge and Eliot Lucy Shafik Follow this and additional works at: https://fount.aucegypt.edu/etds Recommended Citation APA Citation Shafik, L. (2017).Patterns in spiritual awakening: A study of Augustine, Coleridge and Eliot [Master’s thesis, the American University in Cairo]. AUC Knowledge Fountain. https://fount.aucegypt.edu/etds/1366 MLA Citation Shafik, ucyL . Patterns in spiritual awakening: A study of Augustine, Coleridge and Eliot. 2017. American University in Cairo, Master's thesis. AUC Knowledge Fountain. https://fount.aucegypt.edu/etds/1366 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by AUC Knowledge Fountain. It has been accepted for inclusion in Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of AUC Knowledge Fountain. For more information, please contact [email protected]. The American University in Cairo School of Humanities and Social Sciences Patterns in Spiritual Awakening: A Study of Augustine, Coleridge and Eliot A Thesis Submitted to The Department of English and Comparative Literature In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements For the Degree of Master of Arts Lucy Shafik Under the supervision of Dr. William Melaney May 2017 The American University in Cairo Patterns in Spiritual Awakening: A Study of Augustine, Coleridge and Eliot A Thesis Submitted by Lucy Shafik To the Department of English and Comparative Literature May 2017 In partial fulfillment of the requirements for The degree of Master of Arts Has been approved by Dr. William Melaney Thesis Committee Advisor____________________________________________ Affiliation_________________________________________________________ Dr.
    [Show full text]