David Lewis Publications

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

David Lewis Publications David Lewis Publications [1] Wilfrid Hodges and David Lewis. Finitude and infinitude in the atomic calculus of individuals. Nousˆ , 2(4):405–410, 1968. Reprinted in Papers in Philosophical Logic, pp. 180-185. [2] Rae Langton and David Lewis. Defining ’intrinsic’. Philosophy and Phe- nomenological Research, 58(2):333–345, 1998. Reprinted in Papers in Metaphysics and Epistemology, pp. 116-132. [3] Rae Langton and David Lewis. Marshall and Parsons on ’intrinsic’. Phi- losophy and Phenomenological Research, 63(2):353–355, 2001. [4] Bruce LeCatt. Censored vision. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 60(2):158–162, 1982. Written by David Lewis, but published under the name ‘Bruce LeCatt’. [5] David Lewis. An argument for the identity theory. Journal of Philosophy, 63(2):17–25, 1966. Reprinted with additions as [17]. [6] David Lewis. Percepts and color mosaics in visual experience. Philosophi- cal Review, 75(3):357–368, 1966. Reprinted in Papers in Metaphysics and Epistemology, pp. 359-372. [7] David Lewis. Counterpart theory and quantified modal logic. Journal of Philosophy, 65(5):113–126, 1968. Reprinted in Philosophical Papers, Volume I, pp. 26-39. [8] David Lewis. Convention: A Philosophical Study. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, 1969. [9] David Lewis. Lucas against mechanism. Philosophy, 44(June):231–3, 1969. Reprinted in Papers in Philosophical Logic, pp. 166-169. [10] David Lewis. Policing the Aufbau. Philosophical Studies, 20(1-2):13–17, 1969. Reprinted in Papers in Philosophical Logic, pp. 174-179. [11] David Lewis. Review of W. H. Capitan and D. D. Merill, eds. Art, Mind and Religion. Journal of Philosophy, 66(1):22–27, 1969. [12] David Lewis. Anselm and actuality. Nousˆ , 4(2):175–188, 1970. Reprinted in Philosophical Papers, Volume I, pp. 10-20. [13] David Lewis. General semantics. Synthese, 22(1-2):18–67, 1970. Reprinted in Philosophical Papers, Volume I, pp. 189-229. 1 [14] David Lewis. How to define theoretical terms. Journal of Philosophy, 67(13):427–446, 1970. Reprinted in Philosophical Papers, Volume I, pp. 78-95. [15] David Lewis. Nominalistic set theory. Nousˆ , 4(3):225–240, 1970. Reprinted in Papers in Philosophical Logic, pp. 186-202. [16] David Lewis. Analog and digital. Nousˆ , 5(3):321–327, 1971. Reprinted in Papers in Philosophical Logic, pp. 159-165. [17] David Lewis. An argument for the identity theory. In David M. Rosenthal, editor, Materialism and the Mind-Body Problem, pages 162–171. Prentice- Hall, Englewood Cliffs, NJ, 1971. Reprinted in Philosophical Papers, Volume I, pp. 99-107. [18] David Lewis. Completeness and decidability of three logics of counterfac- tual conditionals. Theoria, 37(1):74–85, 1971. [19] David Lewis. Counterparts of persons and their bodies. Journal of Philos- ophy, 68(7):203–211, 1971. Reprinted in Philosophical Papers, Volume I, pp. 47-54. [20] David Lewis. Immodest inductive methods. Philosophy of Science, 38(1):54–63, 1971. [21] David Lewis. Psychophysical and theoretical identifications. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 50(4):249–58, 1972. Reprinted in Papers in Meta- physics and Epistemology, pp. 248-261. [22] David Lewis. Utilitarianism and truthfulness. Australasian Journal of Phi- losophy, 50(1):17–19, 1972. Reprinted in Philosophical Papers, Volume II, pp. 340-342. [23] David Lewis. Causation. Journal of Philosophy, 70(17):556–567, 1973. Reprinted in Philosophical Papers, Volume II, pp. 159-172. [24] David Lewis. Counterfactuals. Blackwell Publishers, Oxford, 1973. [25] David Lewis. Counterfactuals and comparative possibility. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 2(4):418–446, 1973. Reprinted in Philosophical Papers, Volume II, pp. 3-31. [26] David Lewis. Lingue e lingua. Versus, 4:2–21, 1973. A revised version of this was published in English as [33]. 2 [27] David Lewis. Intensional logics without interative axioms. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 3(4):457–466, 1974. Reprinted in Papers in Philo- sophical Logic, pp. 66-76. [28] David Lewis. Radical interpretation. Synthese, 27(3-4):331–344, 1974. Reprinted in Philosophical Papers, Volume I, pp. 108-118. [29] David Lewis. Semantic analyses for dyadic deontic logic. In Soren¨ Sten- lund, editor, Logical Theory and Semantic Analysis: Essays Dedicated to Stig Kanger on His Fiftieth Birthday, pages 1–14. Reidel, Dordrecht, 1974. Reprinted in Papers in Ethics and Social Philosophy, pp. 5-19. [30] David Lewis. Spielman and Lewis on inductive immodesty. Philosophy of Science, 41(1):84–85, 1974. [31] David Lewis. ’Tensions. In Milton K. Munitz and Peter K. Unger, editors, Semantics and Philosophy, pages 49–61. New York University Press, New York, 1974. Reprinted in Philosophical Papers, Volume I, pp. 250-260. [32] David Lewis. Adverbs of quantification. In Formal Semantics of Natural Language, pages 3–15. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1975. Reprinted in Papers in Philosophical Logic, pp. 5-20. [33] David Lewis. Languages and language. In Minnesota Studies in the Phi- losophy of Science, volume 7, pages 3–35. University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis, 1975. Reprinted in Philosophical Papers, Volume I, pp. 163- 188. [34] David Lewis. Convention: Reply to Jamieson. Canadian Journal of Phi- losophy, 6(1):113–120, 1976. Reprinted in Papers in Ethics and Social Philosophy, pp. 136-144. [35] David Lewis. The paradoxes of time travel. American Philosophical Quar- terly, 13(2):145–152, 1976. Reprinted in Philosophical Papers, Volume II, pp. 67-80. [36] David Lewis. Probabilities of conditionals and conditional probabilities. Philosophical Review, 85(3):297–315, 1976. Reprinted in Philosophical Papers, Volume II, pp. 133-152. [37] David Lewis. Survival and identity. In Amelie´ O. Rorty, editor, The Iden- tities of Persons, pages 17–40. University of California Press, Berkeley, 1976. Reprinted in Philosophical Papers, Volume I, pp. 55-72. 3 [38] David Lewis. Possible-world semantics for counterfactual logics: A rejoin- der. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 6(3):359–363, 1977. [39] David Lewis. Reply to McMichael. Analysis, 38(2):85–86, 1978. Reprinted in Papers in Ethics and Social Philosophy, pp. 34-36. [40] David Lewis. Truth in fiction. American Philosophical Quarterly, 15(1):37–46, 1978. Reprinted in Philosophical Papers, Volume I, pp. 261- 275. [41] David Lewis. Attitudes De Dicto and De Se. Philosophical Review, 88(4):513–543, 1979. Reprinted in Philosophical Papers, Volume I, pp. 133-156. [42] David Lewis. Counterfactual dependence and time’s arrow. Nousˆ , 13(4):455–476, 1979. Reprinted in Philosophical Papers, Volume II, pp. 32-52. [43] David Lewis. Lucas against mechanism II. Canadian Journal of Philos- ophy, 9(3):373–6, 1979. Reprinted in Papers in Philosophical Logic, pp. 170-173. [44] David Lewis. Prisoners’ dilemma is a Newcomb problem. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 8(3):235–240, 1979. Reprinted in Philosophical Papers, Volume II, pp. 299-304. [45] David Lewis. A problem about permission. In Esa Saarinen, Risto Hilpinen, Illka Niiniluoto, and Merrill Provence, editors, Essays in Hon- our of Jaakko Hintikka on the occasion of his fiftieth birthday on January 12, 1979, pages 163–175. Reidel, Dordrecht, 1979. Reprinted in Papers in Ethics and Social Philosophy, pp. 20-33. [46] David Lewis. Scorekeeping in a language game. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 8(1):339–359, 1979. Reprinted in Philosophical Papers, Volume I, pp. 233-249. [47] David Lewis. Index, context, and content. In Stig Kanger and Sven Ohman,¨ editors, Philosophy and Grammar, pages 79–100. Reidel, Dor- drecht, 1980. Reprinted in Papers in Philosophical Logic, pp. 21-44. [48] David Lewis. Mad pain and martian pain. In Ned Block, editor, Read- ings in the Philosophy of Psychology, volume I, pages 216–232. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, 1980. Reprinted in Philosophical Papers, Volume I, pp. 122-130. 4 [49] David Lewis. A subjectivist’s guide to objective chance. In Studies in In- ductive Logic and Probability, volume 2, pages 83–132. University of Cal- ifornia Press, Berkeley, 1980. Reprinted in Philosophical Papers, Volume II, pp. 83-113. [50] David Lewis. Veridical hallucination and prosthetic vision. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 58(3):239–249, 1980. Reprinted in Philosophical Papers, Volume II, pp. 273-286. [51] David Lewis. Are we free to break the laws? Theoria, 47(3):113–121, 1981. Reprinted in Philosophical Papers, Volume II, pp. 291-298. [52] David Lewis. Causal decision theory. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 59(1):5–30, 1981. Reprinted in Philosophical Papers, Volume II, pp. 305- 337. [53] David Lewis. Nachwort (1978). In Gunter¨ Posch, editor, Kausalitat:¨ Neue Texte, pages 124–126. Reclam, Stuttgart, 1981. A postscript to a German translation of [23]. [54] David Lewis. Ordering semantics and premise semantics for counterfac- tuals. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 10(2):217–234, 1981. Reprinted in Papers in Philosophical Logic, pp. 77-96. [55] David Lewis. What puzzling Pierre does not believe. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 59(3):283–289, 1981. Reprinted in Papers in Metaphysics and Epistemology, pp. 408-417. [56] David Lewis. Why ain’cha rich? Nousˆ , 15(3):377–380, 1981. Reprinted in Papers in Ethics and Social Philosophy, pp. 37-41. [57] David Lewis. Logic for equivocators. Nousˆ , 16(3):431–441, 1982. Reprinted in Papers in Philosophical Logic, pp. 97-110. [58] David Lewis. ‘Whether’ report. In Tom Pauli, editor, 320311: Philosoph- ical Essays Dedicated to Lennart Aqvist˚ on his Fiftieth Birthday, pages 194–206. University of Uppsala Press, Uppsala, 1982. Reprinted in Papers in Philosophical Logic, pp. 45-56. [59] David Lewis. Extrinsic properties. Philosophical Studies, 44(2):197–200, 1983. Reprinted in Papers in Metaphysics and Epistemology, pp. 111-115. [60] David Lewis. Individuation by acquaintance and by stipulation. Philosoph- ical Review, 92(1):3–32, 1983. Reprinted in Papers in Metaphysics and Epistemology, pp. 373-402. 5 [61] David Lewis. Levi against u-maximization. Journal of Philosophy, 80(9):531–534, 1983. [62] David Lewis. New work for a theory of universals.
Recommended publications
  • Please Do Not Cite. a PROBLEM for CHRISTIAN MATERIALISM
    This is a Draft! Please do not Cite. WHEN CITING ALWAYS REFER TO THE FINAL VERSION PUBLISHED IN EUROPEAN JOURNAL FOR PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION, VOL. 10, NO. 3., 205–213. WITH DOI: 10.24204/EJPR.V10I3.2631 A PROBLEM FOR CHRISTIAN MATERIALISM Elliot Knuths1 Northwestern University Peter van Inwagen and Dean Zimmerman have attempted to demonstrate the metaphysical compatibility of materialism and life after death as it is understood in orthodox Christianity. According to van Inwagen’s simulacrum account of resurrection, God replaces either the whole person or some crucial part of the “core person” with an exact replica at the moment of the person’s death.2 This removed original person — or frag- ment of an original person — provides the basis for personal continuity between an individual in her previ- DOI: 10.24204/EJPR.V10I3.2631 ous life and her post-resurrection life in the world to come. Alternatively, Zimmerman’s “Falling Elevator Model” of resurrection claims that, at the moment just before death, the body undergoes fission, leaving a nonliving lump of matter (a corpse) in the present and a living copy at some other point in space-time.3 In a recent paper, Taliaferro and I criticized these positions,4 arguing that each one lacks phenomenological realism, the quality of satisfactorily reflecting ordinary experience. That article focused primarily on what we consider the methodological shortcomings of van Inwagen’s and Zimmerman’s accounts of resurrection . Citable Version has Version . Citable in materialist terms and other philosophical explanations and thought experiments which clash with ordi- nary experience. We also raised in passing a more substantive challenge for explanations of resurrection in materialist terms which arises from scripture rather than a priori contemplation.
    [Show full text]
  • Physicalism and the Possibility of Life After Death
    Resurrection of the Body?: Physicalism and the Possibility of Life After Death The 2012 Winifred E. Weter Faculty Award Lecture Seattle Pacific University April 17, 2012 Rebekah L.H. Rice, Ph.D. Associate Professor of Philosophy College of Arts and Sciences Resurrection of the Body?: Physicalism and the Possibility of Life After Death 2012 Winifred E. Weter Lecture April 17, 2012 Seattle Pacific University Rebekah L. H. Rice, Ph.D. Department of Philosophy 1 To Jeremy, Lydia, and Silas Rice (For unparalleled love, support, and bear hugs) To Ken Harrower (Who taught me that when faced with a perplexing question, one might do well to crack open a book.) To Steve Layman, Patrick McDonald, and Leland Saunders (Colleagues than which none better can be conceived!) 2 I. Introduction Christians maintain that, as a result of divine grace, human persons can survive their deaths. This occurs as a result of a remarkable divine act—something we call “resurrection.” And it constitutes an important piece of the “good news” that Christians profess. Conceptually, this is a baffling claim. How can it be that I (God willing) will exist after my bodily death? One answer is to suggest—as Rene Descartes famously did—that I am not my body, and that I am instead an immaterial mind, or “soul.” This yields the following account of post-mortem survival: Upon my bodily death, my soul persists. Since I am my soul, and not my body, I persist. Where (or in what conditions) I will persist is a matter left to divine judgment, but the fact of my persistence is owing to the fact that though my bodily processes cease and my body decays – or worse, that it is obliterated and cast into a billion pieces – my soul persists to become the occupant of a new (glorified) body, or in any case to enjoy continued existence.
    [Show full text]
  • Saving God from "Saving God." | Books and Culture | a Christian Review
    8/13/12 Saving God from "Saving God." | Books and Culture | A Christian Review Print this page Close this page The following article is located at: http://www.booksandculture.com/articles/2012/mayjun/savinggod.html Saving God from "Saving God." Is traditional supernaturalism idolatrous? Andrew Chignell and Dean Zimmerman | posted 4/24/201 2 1. Princeton philosopher Mark Johnston was educated by Jesuits and briefly considered taking priestly orders before opting for a PhD in philosophy instead. He went on to make important contributions to several subfields of philosophy— metaphysics, ethics, philosophy of perception. But his work, like that of most analytic philosophers, has appeared mainly in professional journals, and is too technical for most of those outside the guild. Johnston's Saving God, together with its sequel Surviving Death, marks a bold and very public return to the theological questions that he seemed to have left behind upon entering philosophy. It's not clear what roused him from his technical slumbers, though one gets a hint when Saving God begins with a deliciously dismissive critique of the "undergraduate atheisms" of Dawkins, Harris, Hitchens, and company. It soon becomes clear, however, that Johnston is just as intent upon demolishing the traditional forms of religion targeted by these "New Atheists"; what they lack, he suggests, is sufficient philosophical firepower to carry out the job. They also lack the religious sensitivity to see that there might be a deeper truth in the traditional monotheisms that goes beyond
    [Show full text]
  • Religion, Science, and the Conscious Self: Bio-Psychological Explanation and the Debate Between Dualism and Naturalism
    Loyola University Chicago Loyola eCommons Dissertations Theses and Dissertations 2011 Religion, Science, and the Conscious Self: Bio-Psychological Explanation and the Debate Between Dualism and Naturalism Paul J. Voelker Loyola University Chicago Follow this and additional works at: https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_diss Part of the Religious Thought, Theology and Philosophy of Religion Commons Recommended Citation Voelker, Paul J., "Religion, Science, and the Conscious Self: Bio-Psychological Explanation and the Debate Between Dualism and Naturalism" (2011). Dissertations. 242. https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_diss/242 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Theses and Dissertations at Loyola eCommons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Loyola eCommons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 3.0 License. Copyright © 2011 Paul J. Voelker LOYOLA UNIVERSITY CHICAGO RELIGION, SCIENCE, AND THE CONSCIOUS SELF: BIO-PSYCHOLOGICAL EXPLANATION AND THE DEBATE BETWEEN DUALISM AND NATURALISM A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED TO THE FACULTY OF THE GRADUATE SCHOOL IN CANDIDACY FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY PROGRAM IN THEOLOGY BY PAUL J. VOELKER CHICAGO, ILLINOIS MAY 2011 Copyright by Paul J. Voelker, 2011 All rights reserved. ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS Many people helped to make this dissertation project a concrete reality. First, and foremost, I would like to thank my advisor, Dr. John McCarthy. John’s breadth and depth of knowledge made for years of stimulating, challenging conversation, and I am grateful for his constant support. Dr. Michael Schuck also provided for much good conversation during my time at Loyola, and I am grateful to Mike for taking time from a hectic schedule to serve on my dissertation committee.
    [Show full text]
  • Oxford Studies in and Semantic Plasticity’
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 76 (2008), 279–285. Dean ZIMMERMAN (ed.): Oxford Studies in and Semantic Plasticity’. IV. Metaphysics and Metaphysics, Vol. 2. Oxford: Oxford Uni- Th eism: Brian Leftow, ‘God and the Problem versity Press, 2006. x + 400 pp. ISBN 0- of Universals’; Michael Bergmann and Jeff rey 19-929059-8. £55.00, €105.50, $99.00 Brower, ‘A Th eistic Argument Against Pla- hardcover; £18.99, €25.34, $35.00 tonism (and in Support of Truthmakers and paper. Divine Simplicity)’; Hud Hudson, ‘Beauti- ful Evils’. Taken together, the essays consti- This book brings together an interest- tute a valuable sampling of current work in ing selection of contemporary writing on a metaphysics, and there are surprising, surely cross-section of important topics in analytic unintentional thematic connections between metaphysics. Oxford Studies in Metaphysics, papers from one section to another. What one under the general editorship of Dean Zim- learns from such a collection is not merely merman, publishes new work in many areas what topics are of interest to this medley of of ontology, philosophy of mind, time and writers and what philosophical conclusions causation, and philosophical theology. Th e they fi nd most defensible, but also the style papers provide a snapshot of the topics and in which metaphysics is now being practiced arguments currently of interest to profession- by these leading fi gures in the fi eld. al metaphysicians. Th e same general function Th e fi rst suite of three papers centers on could in principle be served by journal pub- a target essay by Block.
    [Show full text]
  • Presentism and the Space-Time Manifold* Dean Zimmerman, Rutgers University I. Introduction: Presentism Among the A-Theories Th
    Presentism and the Space-Time Manifold* Dean Zimmerman, Rutgers University I. Introduction: Presentism Among the A-Theories The A-Theory of Time and the B-Theory of Time McTaggart gave the name “A-series” to “that series of positions which runs from the far past through the near past to the present, and then from the present through the near future to the far future, or conversely”; and the name “B-series” to “[t]he series of positions which runs from earlier to later, or conversely”.1 McTaggart’s rather bland labels have stuck, and been put to further use. The “determinations” (his word), or properties, being past, being present, and being future are generally called the “A-properties”. The relations of being earlier than, being later than, and being simultaneous with, are the “B-relations”. These days, philosophers are said to hold an “A-theory of time” or a “B-theory of time”, depending upon their attitudes to these properties and relations. Some philosophers suppose that there are objective distinctions between what is present and what is past and what is future. In order to tell the full truth about time, they think, one must advert to the A-properties. Naturally enough, such philosophers are called “A-theorists”. Although A-theorists disagree about many details, they agree that the present is distinguished from past and future in a deep and important way. Exactly how to describe this difference is a vexed question, and some philosophers have argued that would-be A-theorists inevitably fail to stake out a coherent position.2 I shall
    [Show full text]
  • Bricker CV 2017
    ` August, 2017 Curriculum Vitae Phillip Bricker Personal Department of Philosophy 72 Columbus Ave. E305 South College Northampton, MA 01060 150 Hicks Way 413-244-3151 (cell) University of Massachusetts 413-586-8644 (home) Amherst, MA 01003 e-mail: [email protected] Birth: January 5, 1954, Los Angeles, CA Education A.B. Philosophy, University of California Berkeley, 1975 A.B. Mathematics, University of California Berkeley, 1975 M.A. Princeton University, 1978 Ph.D. Princeton University, 1983 Dissertation: Worlds and Propositions: The Structure and Ontology of Logical Space. Directed by David Lewis Academic Positions Professor of Philosophy, University of Massachusetts, Amherst, 1998-present Associate Professor of Philosophy, University of Massachusetts, Amherst, 1989-98 Associate Professor, Yale University, 1987-89 Assistant Professor, Yale University, 1983-87 Lecturer, Yale University, 1981-83 Instructor, University of Notre Dame, 1980-81 Publications Book (edited) Philosophical Perspectives on Newtonian Science, edited with RIG Hughes, Bradford Books, MIT Press (1990). 2 Articles “Is There a Humean Account of Quantities?” Philosophical Issues (Supplement to Nous), edited by Enrique Villanueva and Ernest Sosa. Forthcoming Oct., 2017. “Composition as a Kind of Identity,” Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy Vol. 59 (April-May 2016), 264-94. Published on-line May, 2015. “Truthmaking: With and Without Counterpart Theory,” in The Blackwell Companion to David Lewis, Barry Loewer and Jonathan Schaffer (eds.), Wiley Blackwell Publishing (2015), 159-187. “Ontological Commitment,” Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Edward N. Zalta (ed.) (2014). “The Methodology of Modal Logic as Metaphysics,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 88 (2014), 717-725. “Concrete Possible Worlds,” in Contemporary Debates in Metaphysics, Dean Zimmerman, Ted Sider, John Hawthorne (eds.), Blackwell Publishing (2008), 111-134.
    [Show full text]
  • 22 Roderick Chisholm (1916–1999)
    Blackwell Companions to Philosophy: A Companion to Analytic Philosophy Edited by A. P. Martinich, David Sosa Copyright © Blackwell Publishers Ltd 2001 22 Roderick Chisholm (1916–1999) Part I: Epistemology RICHARD FOLEY Part II: Metaphysics DEAN ZIMMERMAN Roderick Chisholm’s work spans six decades and an impressive range of subjects. His books and articles on Brentano and Meinong, together with his work as a translator and editor, and as director of the Brentano Foundation, brought Anglo-American ana- lytic philosophy back into contact with the riches of the Austrian philosophical tradi- tion. He wrote several important papers on the foundations of ethics and axiology (e.g. Chisholm 1963, 1974). But Chisholm is best known for his many contributions to epistemology and metaphysics. Part I: Epistemology The most important of Roderick Chisholm’s writings on epistemology are Perceiving, The Foundations of Knowing, and the three editions of Theory of Knowledge. In these and in his other works, Chisholm addressed virtually every major problem in epistemology. At the heart of his epistemological system is a set of epistemic principles that are intended to generate intuitively plausible results about the degree to which various propositions are justified for an individual. The key to Chisholm’s epistemology is under- standing how these principles fit together and also understanding both their epistemol- ogical status (how is it that we can come to know them?) and their metaphysical status (are they necessary or contingent, and what is it that makes them true?). Terms of epistemic appraisal In formulating his epistemological principles, Chisholm presents a set of terms of epis- temic appraisal, which he defines using a basic, prephilosophical notion of justification.
    [Show full text]
  • Discussion of Jaegwon Kim's Supervenience and Mind
    Critical Notice of Jaegwon Kim’s Supervenience and Mind* Trenton Merricks Philosophical Books 36 (1995): 156-161. Jaegwon Kim has certainly done the most important work on supervenience. Further, he has proposed the most influential account of the nature of events. And since many (Kim included) hold that mental events “supervene upon” physical events, it is no surprise that Kim’s work on events and supervenience lead directly into the philosophy of mind; more specifically, Kim’s work leads directly into the topic of mental causation, which, according to Kim, is the central question in philosophy of mind (xv). In Supervenience and Mind, these and related issues are addressed with clarity, originality, and power. Excepting the preface, a very helpful index, and two postscripts (one on supervenience and one on mental causation), all of the material in this book is available elsewhere. However, it is useful to have Kim select for us those papers that, presumably, he takes to be his eighteen most important on these topics. Many issues are addressed in these essays: various concepts of supervenience and how they relate one to another (Essays 4 and 5); the claim that only the very strongest sort of supervenience is sufficient to capture the kind of dependency supervenience is typically thought to involve (143ff); supervenience applied to multiple domains (Essay 7); Davidson’s work on events and the philosophy of mind (Essays 3 and 11); Quine’s goal of epistemology “naturalized” (Essay 12); and much more. But rather than discuss the various essays individually, I will focus my comments on a few principles that appear and reappear throughout the book, and on which Kim’s *Thanks to the following for helpful advice on this review: Andrew Cortens, Mark Murphy, Alvin Plantinga, Michael Rea, Leopold Stubenberg, Thomas Williams, and Dean Zimmerman.
    [Show full text]
  • Personal Identity and the Survival of Death
    OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 08/02/12, NEWGEN C h a p t e r 4 PERSONAL IDENTITY AND THE SURVIVAL OF DEATH d e a n z i m m e r m a n . If by any means I might attain unto the resurrection of the dead. St. Paul, Philippians 3: 11, King James Version 1 . I n t r o d u c t i o n 1.1 “Surviving Death,” Criteria of Personal Identity, and Two Metaphysical Debates Physical bodies belonging to the kind Homo sapiens appear, one and all, to be headed for disaster. Each body’s ongoing existence depends upon the activities of cells, organs, and larger biological systems. There comes a time when, for one reason or another, the parcels of matter that constitute these structures stop doing their jobs. At one moment, a bunch of atoms are caught up in the life of an organism: oxygen is being transported by red blood cells, sodium and potassium ions are being shuttled around in nerve cells, and so on. Suddenly, the self-same atoms cease to perform these biological functions—they come to constitute a 005_Bradley_Ch04.indd5_Bradley_Ch04.indd 9977 88/2/2012/2/2012 112:09:092:09:09 AAMM OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 08/02/12, NEWGEN THE OXFORD HANDBOOK OF THE PHILOSOPHY OF DEATH corpse, in which all the living cells are rapidly dying. Let us call this sort of fail- ure, in which the matter making up one’s entire body abruptly stops sustaining crucial biological processes like respiration and circulation, “the death of the body” (for the difficulties of providing a real definition of “death,” see chapter 1, this volume).
    [Show full text]
  • Infinitesimals for Metaphysics: Consequences for the Ontologies Of
    Infinitesimals for Metaphysics: Consequences for the Ontologies of Space and Time Dissertation Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of The Ohio State University By Patrick Reeder, MA Graduate Program in Philosophy The Ohio State University 2012 Dissertation Committee: Stewart Shapiro, Advisor Ben Caplan Neil Tennant Copyright by Patrick Reeder 2012 Abstract In this dissertation, I defend unorthodox conceptions of continuity: I argue that they're both conceptually viable and philosophically fruitful. After a brief introduc- tion in the first chapter, I argue in the second chapter that the standard conception of continuity|which comes to us from Georg Cantor and Richard Dedekind, and which uses the real numbers as a model|doesn't satisfy all of pretheoretic intuitions about continuity and indeed that no conception of continuity does. This opens up conceptual room for unorthodox conceptions of continuity. In the second chapter, I argue that an unorthodox conception of continuity based on infinitesimals|numbers as small as infinity is large|provides the basis for a novel account of contact: of when two material bodies touch. In the third chapter, I argue that two other unorthodox conceptions of continuity provide the basis for novel solutions to Zeno's paradox of the arrow. ii Dedication For Faye Bartlett Reeder, Ph.D. (1892-1973) iii Acknowledgments I would like to thank all those who have read and commented on significant por- tions of this dissertation: Scott Brown, Steven Brown, Wesley Cray, Justin D'Arms, Matthew Davidson, Salvatore Florio, Peter Forrest, Timothy Fuller, Alison Kerr, Teresa Kouri, Nicholaos Jones, Lindsey Mason, James McGlothlin, Michael Miller, Cathy Muller, Bradley Rettler, Tony Roy, David Sanson, Kevin Scharp, Timothy Schroeder, Lisa Shabel, Nathan Smith, Declan Smithies, William Taschek, Gabriel Uzquiano and Daniel Wilkenfeld.
    [Show full text]
  • On Alvin Plantinga's Evolutionary Argument Against Naturalism
    University of Tennessee, Knoxville TRACE: Tennessee Research and Creative Exchange Doctoral Dissertations Graduate School 8-2010 On Alvin Plantinga’s Evolutionary Argument against Naturalism Emmett Frank Mashburn University of Tennessee - Knoxville, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://trace.tennessee.edu/utk_graddiss Part of the Epistemology Commons, and the Metaphysics Commons Recommended Citation Mashburn, Emmett Frank, "On Alvin Plantinga’s Evolutionary Argument against Naturalism. " PhD diss., University of Tennessee, 2010. https://trace.tennessee.edu/utk_graddiss/824 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at TRACE: Tennessee Research and Creative Exchange. It has been accepted for inclusion in Doctoral Dissertations by an authorized administrator of TRACE: Tennessee Research and Creative Exchange. For more information, please contact [email protected]. To the Graduate Council: I am submitting herewith a dissertation written by Emmett Frank Mashburn entitled "On Alvin Plantinga’s Evolutionary Argument against Naturalism." I have examined the final electronic copy of this dissertation for form and content and recommend that it be accepted in partial fulfillment of the equirr ements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy, with a major in Philosophy. John E. Nolt, Major Professor We have read this dissertation and recommend its acceptance: Richard E. Aquila, E. J. Coffman, John R. Hardwig, Carl G. Wagner Accepted for the Council: Carolyn R. Hodges Vice Provost and Dean of the Graduate School (Original signatures are on file with official studentecor r ds.) To the Graduate Council: I am submitting herewith a dissertation written by Emmett Frank Mashburn, Jr. entitled “On Alvin Plantinga’s Evolutionary Argument against Naturalism.” I have examined the final electronic copy of this dissertation for form and content and recommend that it be accepted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy, with a major in Philosophy.
    [Show full text]