Presentism and the Space-Time Manifold* Dean Zimmerman, Rutgers University I. Introduction: Presentism Among the A-Theories Th

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Presentism and the Space-Time Manifold* Dean Zimmerman, Rutgers University I. Introduction: Presentism Among the A-Theories Th Presentism and the Space-Time Manifold* Dean Zimmerman, Rutgers University I. Introduction: Presentism Among the A-Theories The A-Theory of Time and the B-Theory of Time McTaggart gave the name “A-series” to “that series of positions which runs from the far past through the near past to the present, and then from the present through the near future to the far future, or conversely”; and the name “B-series” to “[t]he series of positions which runs from earlier to later, or conversely”.1 McTaggart’s rather bland labels have stuck, and been put to further use. The “determinations” (his word), or properties, being past, being present, and being future are generally called the “A-properties”. The relations of being earlier than, being later than, and being simultaneous with, are the “B-relations”. These days, philosophers are said to hold an “A-theory of time” or a “B-theory of time”, depending upon their attitudes to these properties and relations. Some philosophers suppose that there are objective distinctions between what is present and what is past and what is future. In order to tell the full truth about time, they think, one must advert to the A-properties. Naturally enough, such philosophers are called “A-theorists”. Although A-theorists disagree about many details, they agree that the present is distinguished from past and future in a deep and important way. Exactly how to describe this difference is a vexed question, and some philosophers have argued that would-be A-theorists inevitably fail to stake out a coherent position.2 I shall not attempt a full-scale defense of the coherence of the A- theory here; but hopefully the following characterization will suffice to convey, in a rough-and- ready way, the nature of the A-theorists’ convictions about time: The A-theorist grants that every thing in time (setting aside the possibility of a beginning or end of time itself) is “past relative to” some things, “future relative to” others, and “present relative to” itself — just as every place on earth (setting aside the poles) is south relative to some places, north relative to others, and at the same latitude as itself. But the A-theorist insists that this attractive analogy between spatial and temporal dimensions is misleading; for, of any time or event that is past, present, or future in this merely relative way, one can also ask whether it is, in addition, past, present, or future in a non-relative way — past, present, or future simpliciter. The A-theorist takes the merely relative A-determinations to be based upon facts concerning which times and events are really past, present, or future, not merely relatively so. “B-theorists”, by contrast, deny the objectivity of the division of time into past, present, and future; they regard the spatial north-south analogy as deeply revelatory of the purely relative nature of this division (though many B-theorists admit that there is some intrinsic difference between spatial and temporal distances). To arrive at more objective facts about time, one must turn to relations like being earlier than, being later than, and being simultaneous with — the “B-relations”.3 The A-theory is almost certainly a minority view among contemporary philosophers with an opinion about the metaphysics of time.4 Nevertheless, it has many defenders — Ian Hinckfuss, J. R. Lucas, E. J. Lowe, John Bigelow, Trenton Merricks, Ned Markosian, Thomas Crisp, Quentin Smith, Craig Bourne, Bradley Monton, Ross Cameron, William Lane Craig, Storrs McCall, Peter Ludlow, George Schlesinger, Robert M. Adams, Peter Forrest, and Nicholas Maxwell, to name a few.5 Several of the most eminent 20th century philosophers were A- theorists, notably C. D. Broad, Arthur Prior, Peter Geach, and Roderick Chisholm.6 2 The B-theory can claim support from two of the founders of the analytic movement in philosophy: Gottlob Frege and Bertrand Russell.7 In the years since, it has achieved broad acceptance. D. C. Williams, W. V. O. Quine, Adolf Grünbaum, J. J. C. Smart, David Lewis, D. H. Mellor, Paul Horwich, Tim Maudlin, Frank Arntzenius, Theodore Sider, Robin Le Poidevin, Nathan Oaklander, Steven Savitt, and Thomas Sattig are just the tip of the B-theorist iceberg.8 B-theorists have raised many kinds of objections to the A-theory and to the particular kind of A-theory I find most attractive, namely, presentism.9 What follows is a defense of presentism in the face of just one of these: that the view has been refuted or at least badly undermined by discoveries in physics. The rejection of Newton’s substantival space by the natural philosophers and physicists of the nineteenth century had already created an environment somewhat hostile to presentism, as shall emerge in my discussion of one of Theodore Sider’s objections to presentism (the objection described near the end of Section III, based on cross- temporal relations involving motion). Einstein’s Special Theory of Relativity (SR) and General Theory of Relativity (GR) seem only to have made things worse. Both imply the “relativity of simultaneity”; and this raises obvious questions for all A-theorists. If, as A-theorists believe, there is an objective fact about what is presently happening, there must be an objective fact about which events are simultaneous with one another — in other words, a fact about simultaneity that is not relative to anything, including the frames of reference of SR, or the local frames of GR. But, on the face of it, these scientific theories require that simultaneity be frame-relative. Before launching into description of the variety of A-theories, and defense of the kind I prefer, I should mention some things that will not be discussed in this essay. The first is a philosophical debate that is sometimes conflated with the A-theory-B-theory dispute: namely, the question whether time has an intrinsic direction to it; that is, whether the relation being 3 earlier than holds between moments or space-time locations independently of the contents of space-time. No one, to my knowledge, has defended the following combination of views: time lacks an intrinsic direction but includes objective distinctions between past, present, and future. The idea is not completely incoherent: one might attempt to reconstruct the difference between distance-into-the-past and distance-into-the-future on the basis of facts about what is present and “direction-neutral” temporal distance facts.10 But the project will probably seem quixotic to most A-theorists (I know it does to me!). B-theorists, however, are sharply divided on the question whether time has an intrinsic direction. Two temporal directions are distinguishable from the spatial ones in the space-time of SR and in manifolds compatible with GR — at least, in the less bizarrely shaped ones. But some philosophers of physics deny that one direction is more deserving of the label “forward in time”, when considered all by itself, in abstraction from space- time’s material contents. These deniers of intrinsic direction claim that the actual difference between forward and backward in time does not supervene upon facts about intrinsic structure alone, but only upon such facts plus contingent facts about the contents of space-time, such as the distribution of matter. Both A-theorists and the friends of intrinsic temporal direction are often said to believe that “time flows”, or to believe in “objective passage”; and their opponents may be said to champion a more “static” conception of time. But the two controversies are obviously quite different. Only the bona fide A-theory–B-theory debate shall figure in this chapter; for an up-to-date discussion of the question whether time has an intrinsic direction, see Huw Price, “The Flow of Time”, in this volume.11 Many other important issues will be set aside, including the allegation that A-theorists and B-theorists are simply talking past one another. Some philosophers claim not to be able even to understand the A-theory–B-theory debate; and they cannily manage to extend this 4 inability so that it includes all the terms that might be used to explain it to them.12 Fortunately, a number of effective therapies have been developed for those who find themselves losing their grip on the nature of the disagreement between A-theorists and B-theorists, or between presentists and non-presentists. The best treatment for the condition is something I discuss elsewhere.13 Other issues to be set aside include the majority of the objections that have been raised against the A-theory in general and presentism in particular. Chief amongst these is the argument that truths about the past need “truthmakers” (where a truthmaker for a proposition is some part of the world in virtue of which the proposition is true), and that the presentist lacks the resources to provide them.14 In the face of this challenge, some presentists cast about for present states of the world that will ground truths about the past15; while others question the legitimacy of the demand for truthmakers.16 I shall take it for granted that presentists can appeal, unproblematically, to facts about what was the case at each instant in the past — at least, that purely qualitative facts about each past moment are well-grounded. Even granting so much as that, presentism’s critics can raise serious objections based on what physics seems to say about the nature of space-time. The two problems upon which I focus are these: (1) Determinate facts about the state of the universe at each instant may fail to provide an adequate basis for certain cross-temporal facts that are physically important and objective.
Recommended publications
  • 26-2 Spacetime and the Spacetime Interval We Usually Think of Time and Space As Being Quite Different from One Another
    Answer to Essential Question 26.1: (a) The obvious answer is that you are at rest. However, the question really only makes sense when we ask what the speed is measured with respect to. Typically, we measure our speed with respect to the Earth’s surface. If you answer this question while traveling on a plane, for instance, you might say that your speed is 500 km/h. Even then, however, you would be justified in saying that your speed is zero, because you are probably at rest with respect to the plane. (b) Your speed with respect to a point on the Earth’s axis depends on your latitude. At the latitude of New York City (40.8° north) , for instance, you travel in a circular path of radius equal to the radius of the Earth (6380 km) multiplied by the cosine of the latitude, which is 4830 km. You travel once around this circle in 24 hours, for a speed of 350 m/s (at a latitude of 40.8° north, at least). (c) The radius of the Earth’s orbit is 150 million km. The Earth travels once around this orbit in a year, corresponding to an orbital speed of 3 ! 104 m/s. This sounds like a high speed, but it is too small to see an appreciable effect from relativity. 26-2 Spacetime and the Spacetime Interval We usually think of time and space as being quite different from one another. In relativity, however, we link time and space by giving them the same units, drawing what are called spacetime diagrams, and plotting trajectories of objects through spacetime.
    [Show full text]
  • The Sundial, Beyond the Form and Time
    ISAMA BRIDGES The International Society of the Mathematical Connections Arts, Mathematics, and Architecture in Art, Music, and Science The Sundial, Beyond the Form and Time ... Andrzej Zarzycki 227 Brighton Street Belmont, MA 02478 E-mail: [email protected] Abstract Architecture (iir" k 1-t].lk" ch ... r) n. 1. The art and science of designing and erecting buildings. Can a building inspire scientific thinking? Can an architectural structure reflect the complexity of the universe? Is there a relationship between the artistic and scientific? This paper discusses an approach to design, which uses an architectural structure as a research apparatus to pursue scientifically driven beauty. Architecture could be defined as the man-made universe - the universe whose primary function was to shelter us from elements, animals and other people. Broadly speaking, to protect us from the "outer Uni­ verse". It is not surprising that the evolution of architecture follows the same trajectories as the evolution of our thinking and perception ofthe surrounding world. However, somewhere along the lines of history, archi­ tecture acquired another purpose and began to playa new role in our self-awareness. In ancient, medieval and even modem times, we have viewed architecture as a medium to express, symbolize, and address the meaning of our existence. Ancient temples reveal an intimate knowledge of geometry and human perception by purposefully distorting their forms to balance visual illusions. Medieval cathedrals manifested greatness of God through art and structural achievements, while contemporary monu­ ments address the social and philosophical aspirations of a present-day society. As a result of this centuries long evolution~ we now associate architecture with its less utilitarian and more symbolic values.
    [Show full text]
  • Persistence, Vagueness, and Location
    PERSISTENCE, VAGUENESS, AND LOCATION Antony Eagle University of Adelaide, antonyeagle.org Forthcoming in The Journal of Philosophy I will discuss two arguments in favor of perdurance. The first is Sider’s argument from vagueness.1 Sider regards this argument as “one of the most powerful” in favor of perdurantism. I make the observation – obvious once made, but I am unable to find it elsewhere in the literature – that endurantists have principled grounds to claim that the argument is unsound (§§I–III). Having made this observation, I use it to emphasize a somewhat neglected difference between endurantists and perdurantists with respect to their views on material objects (§IV). These views, in the case of endurantists, lead to a further, less than conclusive but nevertheless interesting argument against endurantism – the anti-fundamentality argument – which I discuss in the second half of the paper (§§V–VI). I. THE ARGUMENT FROM VAGUENESS To begin, some terminology. An assignment is a (possibly partial) function from times to a set of entities existing at each time; a D-fusion of an assignment is an entity that is, at each time for 1 Theodore Sider, Four-Dimensionalism: an Ontology of Persistence and Time (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2001), at §4.9.3. 1 which the assignment is defined, constituted by the fusion of the members of the set which is the value of the assignment at that time; a minimal D-fusion of an assignment is a D-fusion which exists only at the times for which the assignment is defined.2 In these terms, Sider’s argument aims to establish this conclusion: (U) “every assignment has a minimal D-fusion”.3 U swiftly entails the existence of temporal parts, because the singleton assignment {⟨�, �⟩} is well- formed for any � existing at �, and so has a minimal D-fusion – an entity which is the fusion of � at � and exists only at �, which meets Sider’s widely agreed criteria for being a temporal part of � at �.4 Note how important the word ‘minimal’ is in U.
    [Show full text]
  • Time Reversal Symmetry in Cosmology and the Creation of a Universe–Antiuniverse Pair
    universe Review Time Reversal Symmetry in Cosmology and the Creation of a Universe–Antiuniverse Pair Salvador J. Robles-Pérez 1,2 1 Estación Ecológica de Biocosmología, Pedro de Alvarado, 14, 06411 Medellín, Spain; [email protected] 2 Departamento de Matemáticas, IES Miguel Delibes, Miguel Hernández 2, 28991 Torrejón de la Calzada, Spain Received: 14 April 2019; Accepted: 12 June 2019; Published: 13 June 2019 Abstract: The classical evolution of the universe can be seen as a parametrised worldline of the minisuperspace, with the time variable t being the parameter that parametrises the worldline. The time reversal symmetry of the field equations implies that for any positive oriented solution there can be a symmetric negative oriented one that, in terms of the same time variable, respectively represent an expanding and a contracting universe. However, the choice of the time variable induced by the correct value of the Schrödinger equation in the two universes makes it so that their physical time variables can be reversely related. In that case, the two universes would both be expanding universes from the perspective of their internal inhabitants, who identify matter with the particles that move in their spacetimes and antimatter with the particles that move in the time reversely symmetric universe. If the assumptions considered are consistent with a realistic scenario of our universe, the creation of a universe–antiuniverse pair might explain two main and related problems in cosmology: the time asymmetry and the primordial matter–antimatter asymmetry of our universe. Keywords: quantum cosmology; origin of the universe; time reversal symmetry PACS: 98.80.Qc; 98.80.Bp; 11.30.-j 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Please Do Not Cite. a PROBLEM for CHRISTIAN MATERIALISM
    This is a Draft! Please do not Cite. WHEN CITING ALWAYS REFER TO THE FINAL VERSION PUBLISHED IN EUROPEAN JOURNAL FOR PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION, VOL. 10, NO. 3., 205–213. WITH DOI: 10.24204/EJPR.V10I3.2631 A PROBLEM FOR CHRISTIAN MATERIALISM Elliot Knuths1 Northwestern University Peter van Inwagen and Dean Zimmerman have attempted to demonstrate the metaphysical compatibility of materialism and life after death as it is understood in orthodox Christianity. According to van Inwagen’s simulacrum account of resurrection, God replaces either the whole person or some crucial part of the “core person” with an exact replica at the moment of the person’s death.2 This removed original person — or frag- ment of an original person — provides the basis for personal continuity between an individual in her previ- DOI: 10.24204/EJPR.V10I3.2631 ous life and her post-resurrection life in the world to come. Alternatively, Zimmerman’s “Falling Elevator Model” of resurrection claims that, at the moment just before death, the body undergoes fission, leaving a nonliving lump of matter (a corpse) in the present and a living copy at some other point in space-time.3 In a recent paper, Taliaferro and I criticized these positions,4 arguing that each one lacks phenomenological realism, the quality of satisfactorily reflecting ordinary experience. That article focused primarily on what we consider the methodological shortcomings of van Inwagen’s and Zimmerman’s accounts of resurrection . Citable Version has Version . Citable in materialist terms and other philosophical explanations and thought experiments which clash with ordi- nary experience. We also raised in passing a more substantive challenge for explanations of resurrection in materialist terms which arises from scripture rather than a priori contemplation.
    [Show full text]
  • Parts of Persons Identity and Persistence in a Perdurantist World
    UNIVERSITÀ DEGLI STUDI DI MILANO Doctoral School in Philosophy and Human Sciences (XXXI Cycle) Department of Philosophy “Piero Martinetti” Parts of Persons Identity and persistence in a perdurantist world Ph.D. Candidate Valerio BUONOMO Tutors Prof. Giuliano TORRENGO Prof. Paolo VALORE Coordinator of the Doctoral School Prof. Marcello D’AGOSTINO Academic year 2017-2018 1 Content CONTENT ........................................................................................................................... 2 ACKNOWLEDGMENTS ........................................................................................................... 4 INTRODUCTION ................................................................................................................... 5 CHAPTER 1. PERSONAL IDENTITY AND PERSISTENCE...................................................................... 8 1.1. The persistence of persons and the criteria of identity over time .................................. 8 1.2. The accounts of personal persistence: a standard classification ................................... 14 1.2.1. Mentalist accounts of personal persistence ............................................................................ 15 1.2.2. Somatic accounts of personal persistence .............................................................................. 15 1.2.3. Anti-criterialist accounts of personal persistence ................................................................... 16 1.3. The metaphysics of persistence: the mereological account .........................................
    [Show full text]
  • The Reionization of Cosmic Hydrogen by the First Galaxies Abstract 1
    David Goodstein’s Cosmology Book The Reionization of Cosmic Hydrogen by the First Galaxies Abraham Loeb Department of Astronomy, Harvard University, 60 Garden St., Cambridge MA, 02138 Abstract Cosmology is by now a mature experimental science. We are privileged to live at a time when the story of genesis (how the Universe started and developed) can be critically explored by direct observations. Looking deep into the Universe through powerful telescopes, we can see images of the Universe when it was younger because of the finite time it takes light to travel to us from distant sources. Existing data sets include an image of the Universe when it was 0.4 million years old (in the form of the cosmic microwave background), as well as images of individual galaxies when the Universe was older than a billion years. But there is a serious challenge: in between these two epochs was a period when the Universe was dark, stars had not yet formed, and the cosmic microwave background no longer traced the distribution of matter. And this is precisely the most interesting period, when the primordial soup evolved into the rich zoo of objects we now see. The observers are moving ahead along several fronts. The first involves the construction of large infrared telescopes on the ground and in space, that will provide us with new photos of the first galaxies. Current plans include ground-based telescopes which are 24-42 meter in diameter, and NASA’s successor to the Hubble Space Telescope, called the James Webb Space Telescope. In addition, several observational groups around the globe are constructing radio arrays that will be capable of mapping the three-dimensional distribution of cosmic hydrogen in the infant Universe.
    [Show full text]
  • Naturalness, Intrinsicality, and Duplication
    Naturalness, Intrinsicality, and Duplication Theodore Sider Ph.D. thesis, University of Massachusetts. Committee: Phillip Bricker (chair), Fred Feldman, Edmund Gettier, Angelika Kratzer May 1993 Acknowledgments I would like to thank various people for their verbal and written comments on earlier stages of this dissertation. Of course, none of these people are re- sponsible for the views I express. I am indebted to Mark Aronszajn, Lynne Baker, David Braun, Earl Conee, David Cowles, Max Cresswell, David Den- by, Fred Feldman, Richard Feldman, Edmund Gettier, Larry Holm, Ned Markosian, Deborah Modrak, and R. Cranston Paull. I am especially indebted to my dissertation director, Phillip Bricker. He consistently gave me excellent comments and helped me to see more mistakes than I care to remember. For whatever there is of value in this dissertation, he deserves much of the credit. i Abstract This dissertation explores the concepts of naturalness, intrinsicality, and du- plication. An intrinsic property is had by an object purely in virtue of the way that object is considered in itself. Duplicate objects are exactly similar, considered as they are in themselves. The perfectly natural properties are the most fundamental properties of the world, upon which the nature of the world depends. In this dissertation I develop a theory of intrinsicality, naturalness, and duplication and explore their philosophical applications. Chapter 1 intro- duces the notions, gives a preliminary survey of some proposed conceptual connections between the notions, and sketches some of their proposed ap- plications. Chapter 2 gives my background assumptions and introduces no- tational conventions. In chapter 3 I present a theory of naturalness.
    [Show full text]
  • The Age of the Universe, the Hubble Constant, the Accelerated Expansion and the Hubble Effect
    The age of the universe, the Hubble constant, the accelerated expansion and the Hubble effect Domingos Soares∗ Departamento de F´ısica,ICEx, UFMG | C.P. 702 30123-970, Belo Horizonte | Brazil October 25, 2018 Abstract The idea of an accelerating universe comes almost simultaneously with the determination of Hubble's constant by one of the Hubble Space Tele- scope Key Projects. The age of the universe dilemma is probably the link between these two issues. In an appendix, I claim that \Hubble's law" might yet to be investigated for its ultimate cause, and suggest the \Hubble effect” as the searched candidate. 1 The age dilemma The age of the universe is calculated by two different ways. Firstly, a lower limit is given by the age of the presumably oldest objects in the Milky Way, e.g., globular clusters. Their ages are calculated with the aid of stellar evolu- tion models which yield 14 Gyr and 10% uncertainty. These are fairly confident figures since the basics of stellar evolution are quite solid. Secondly, a cosmo- logical age based on the Standard Cosmology Model derived from the Theory of General Relativity. The three basic models of relativistic cosmology are given by the Friedmann's solutions of Einstein's field equations. The models are char- acterized by a decelerated expansion from a spatial singularity at cosmic time t = 0, and whose magnitude is quantified by the density parameter Ω◦, the present ratio of the mass density in the universe to the so-called critical mass arXiv:0908.1864v8 [physics.gen-ph] 28 Jul 2015 density.
    [Show full text]
  • Pre-Big Bang, Space-Time Structure, Asymptotic Universe
    EPJ Web of Conferences 71, 0 0 063 (2 014 ) DOI: 10.1051/epjconf/20147100063 C Owned by the authors, published by EDP Sciences, 2014 Pre-Big Bang, space-time structure, asymptotic Universe Spinorial space-time and a new approach to Friedmann-like equations Luis Gonzalez-Mestres1,a 1Megatrend Cosmology Laboratory, Megatrend University, Belgrade and Paris Goce Delceva 8, 11070 Novi Beograd, Serbia Abstract. Planck and other recent data in Cosmology and Particle Physics can open the way to controversial analyses concerning the early Universe and its possible ultimate origin. Alternatives to standard cosmology include pre-Big Bang approaches, new space- time geometries and new ultimate constituents of matter. Basic issues related to a possible new cosmology along these lines clearly deserve further exploration. The Planck collab- oration reports an age of the Universe t close to 13.8 Gyr and a present ratio H between relative speeds and distances at cosmic scale around 67.3 km/s/Mpc. The product of these two measured quantities is then slightly below 1 (about 0.95), while it can be exactly 1 in the absence of matter and cosmological constant in patterns based on the spinorial space- time we have considered in previous papers. In this description of space-time we first suggested in 1996-97, the cosmic time t is given by the modulus of a SU(2) spinor and the Lundmark-Lemaître-Hubble (LLH) expansion law turns out to be of purely geometric origin previous to any introduction of standard matter and relativity. Such a fundamen- tal geometry, inspired by the role of half-integer spin in Particle Physics, may reflect an equilibrium between the dynamics of the ultimate constituents of matter and the deep structure of space and time.
    [Show full text]
  • The Ups and Downs of Baryon Oscillations
    The Ups and Downs of Baryon Oscillations Eric V. Linder Physics Division, Lawrence Berkeley Laboratory, Berkeley, CA 94720 ABSTRACT Baryon acoustic oscillations, measured through the patterned distribution of galaxies or other baryon tracing objects on very large (∼> 100 Mpc) scales, offer a possible geometric probe of cosmological distances. Pluses and minuses in this approach’s leverage for understanding dark energy are discussed, as are systematic uncertainties requiring further investigation. Conclusions are that 1) BAO offer promise of a new avenue to distance measurements and further study is warranted, 2) the measurements will need to attain ∼ 1% accuracy (requiring a 10000 square degree spectroscopic survey) for their dark energy leverage to match that from supernovae, but do give complementary information at 2% accuracy. Because of the ties to the matter dominated era, BAO is not a replacement probe of dark energy, but a valuable complement. 1. Introduction This paper provides a pedagogical introduction to baryon acoustic oscillations (BAO), accessible to readers not necessarily familiar with details of large scale structure in the universe. In addition, it summarizes some of the current issues – plus and minus – with the use of BAO as a cosmological probe of the nature of dark energy. For more quantitative, arXiv:astro-ph/0507308v2 17 Jan 2006 technical discussions of these issues, see White (2005). The same year as the detection of the cosmic microwave background, the photon bath remnant from the hot, early universe, Sakharov (1965) predicted the presence of acoustic oscillations in a coupled baryonic matter distribution. In his case, baryons were coupled to cold electrons rather than hot photons; Peebles & Yu (1970) and Sunyaev & Zel’dovich (1970) pioneered the correct, hot case.
    [Show full text]
  • Physicalism and the Possibility of Life After Death
    Resurrection of the Body?: Physicalism and the Possibility of Life After Death The 2012 Winifred E. Weter Faculty Award Lecture Seattle Pacific University April 17, 2012 Rebekah L.H. Rice, Ph.D. Associate Professor of Philosophy College of Arts and Sciences Resurrection of the Body?: Physicalism and the Possibility of Life After Death 2012 Winifred E. Weter Lecture April 17, 2012 Seattle Pacific University Rebekah L. H. Rice, Ph.D. Department of Philosophy 1 To Jeremy, Lydia, and Silas Rice (For unparalleled love, support, and bear hugs) To Ken Harrower (Who taught me that when faced with a perplexing question, one might do well to crack open a book.) To Steve Layman, Patrick McDonald, and Leland Saunders (Colleagues than which none better can be conceived!) 2 I. Introduction Christians maintain that, as a result of divine grace, human persons can survive their deaths. This occurs as a result of a remarkable divine act—something we call “resurrection.” And it constitutes an important piece of the “good news” that Christians profess. Conceptually, this is a baffling claim. How can it be that I (God willing) will exist after my bodily death? One answer is to suggest—as Rene Descartes famously did—that I am not my body, and that I am instead an immaterial mind, or “soul.” This yields the following account of post-mortem survival: Upon my bodily death, my soul persists. Since I am my soul, and not my body, I persist. Where (or in what conditions) I will persist is a matter left to divine judgment, but the fact of my persistence is owing to the fact that though my bodily processes cease and my body decays – or worse, that it is obliterated and cast into a billion pieces – my soul persists to become the occupant of a new (glorified) body, or in any case to enjoy continued existence.
    [Show full text]