Naturalness, Intrinsicality, and Duplication

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Naturalness, Intrinsicality, and Duplication Naturalness, Intrinsicality, and Duplication Theodore Sider Ph.D. thesis, University of Massachusetts. Committee: Phillip Bricker (chair), Fred Feldman, Edmund Gettier, Angelika Kratzer May 1993 Acknowledgments I would like to thank various people for their verbal and written comments on earlier stages of this dissertation. Of course, none of these people are re- sponsible for the views I express. I am indebted to Mark Aronszajn, Lynne Baker, David Braun, Earl Conee, David Cowles, Max Cresswell, David Den- by, Fred Feldman, Richard Feldman, Edmund Gettier, Larry Holm, Ned Markosian, Deborah Modrak, and R. Cranston Paull. I am especially indebted to my dissertation director, Phillip Bricker. He consistently gave me excellent comments and helped me to see more mistakes than I care to remember. For whatever there is of value in this dissertation, he deserves much of the credit. i Abstract This dissertation explores the concepts of naturalness, intrinsicality, and du- plication. An intrinsic property is had by an object purely in virtue of the way that object is considered in itself. Duplicate objects are exactly similar, considered as they are in themselves. The perfectly natural properties are the most fundamental properties of the world, upon which the nature of the world depends. In this dissertation I develop a theory of intrinsicality, naturalness, and duplication and explore their philosophical applications. Chapter 1 intro- duces the notions, gives a preliminary survey of some proposed conceptual connections between the notions, and sketches some of their proposed ap- plications. Chapter 2 gives my background assumptions and introduces no- tational conventions. In chapter 3 I present a theory of naturalness. Although I take ‘natural’ as a primitive, I clarify this notion by distinguishing and explicating various conceptions of naturalness. In chapter 4 I give a theory of various notions related to naturalness, es- pecially intrinsicality and duplication. I show that ‘intrinsic’ and ‘duplicate’ are interde nable, and then give analyses of these and other notions in terms of naturalness. If, as I think likely, naturalness cannot be analyzed, then what is the proper response? David Lewis suggests: accept naturalness as a primitive. I am sympathetic to this proposal, but not to the form Lewis gives it: chapter 5 contains an argument against Lewis’s theory of naturalness. In chapter 6 I reject the idea that naturalness is analyzable in terms of immanent universals. I focus on the work of D. M. Armstrong. I also criticize Armstrong’s arguments against transcendent universals. In chapter 7 I address criticisms of David Lewis’s de nition of ‘intrinsic’ offered by Mike Dunn. ii ABSTRACT iii In chapter 8 I discuss the possibility of analyzing our three notions. I discuss de ning ‘natural’ in terms of supervenience and other concepts, and then criticize attempts by Jaegwon Kim and Michael Slote to analyze intrin- sicality in terms of “quasi-logical” concepts. Finally, in chapter 9 I present a new application for the notion of natu- ralness: the statement of “metrical realism” in the philosophy of space and time. Contents Acknowledgments i Abstract ii 1 Introducing Three Notions 1 1.1 Intrinsicality and Duplication . 1 1.2 Naturalness . 8 1.3 The Structure of the Dissertation . 11 2 Preliminaries 14 2.1 Metaphysical Assumptions . 14 2.2 Language . 21 3 Conceptions of Naturalness 23 3.1 Introduction . 23 3.2 Conception 1 . 25 3.2.1 Supervenience, Microphysicality, and Property “Com- binations” . 25 3.2.2 A Complication . 38 3.2.3 Relative Naturalness According to Conception 1 . 40 3.3 Conception 2 . 49 3.3.1 Perfect Naturalness . 49 3.3.2 Relative Naturalness According to Conception 2 . 52 3.4 Choosing a Conception of Naturalness . 54 3.5 Conclusion . 59 4 Intrinsicality, Duplication, and other Notions 61 4.1 Intrinsicality and Duplication Are “Interde nable” . 61 iv CONTENTS v 4.2 Duplication and Beyond . 65 4.2.1 Duplication . 66 4.2.2 Other Concepts . 71 4.2.3 Consequences of the de nitions . 73 5 Naturalness and Arbitrariness 77 5.1 Primitive Class Naturalism . 77 5.2 Against Primitive Class Naturalism . 79 5.2.1 Pairs and Relations . 79 5.2.2 Benacceraf’s Argument . 80 5.2.3 An Argument against Primitive Class Naturalism . 82 5.2.4 Response 1: “The Argument Proves Too Much” . 92 5.2.5 Response 2: Primitive Ordered Pairs . 94 5.3 Naturalness and “Kripkenstein” . 96 6 Properties, Universals, and Naturalness 99 6.1 Sparseness vs. Abundance; Immanence vs. Transcendence . 99 6.2 Universals and Naturalness . 106 6.3 Armstrong’s Objections to Transcendent Universals . 110 6.3.1 Two Theories of Abundant Universals . 110 6.3.2 Armstrong’s Arguments against Transcendent Univer- sals . 112 6.4 Conclusion . 128 7 Dunn on Intrinsicality 129 7.1 Dunn’s Criticisms of Lewis . 129 7.1.1 Dunn’s Formulation of Lewis’s View . 129 7.1.2 Dunn’s First Objection . 133 7.1.3 Dunn’s Second Objection . 134 7.2 Dunn’s Theory of Intrinsicality . 138 7.3 Two Conceptions of Intrinsicality . 140 8 Analysis of the Notions 144 8.1 Can We De ne ‘Natural’? . 144 8.2 Can We De ne ‘Intrinsic? . 147 8.2.1 Preliminaries . 148 8.2.2 Kim’s De nition . 149 8.2.3 Slote’s Project . 150 CONTENTS vi 8.2.4 Slote’s Analysis of Alteration . 150 8.2.5 Slote’s Analysis of Alikeness . 156 9 Naturalness and Metrical Realism 168 9.1 Preliminaries . 168 9.2 Metrical Realism . 170 9.2.1 Introduction to Metrical Realism . 170 9.2.2 Physical Distance Functions . 171 9.2.3 The Proposal Generalized . 173 9.2.4 The Proposal Re ned . 175 9.3 The Problem of Extra Relations . 178 9.4 Contingency of the Metric . 180 9.4.1 An Argument . 180 9.4.2 Rejecting Premise (1)—Relation splitting . 181 9.4.3 Rejecting Premise (2) . 184 List of Figures 4.1 Endlessly conjunctive properties . 69 6.1 Particulars: TU vs. IU . 104 vii Chapter 1 Introducing Three Notions 1.1 Intrinsicality and Duplication Today my brother got a haircut. Yesterday Mike had the property having long hair; today he does not. By losing this property my brother changed. When my only brother got his much-needed haircut, I too lost a property: the property having a long-haired brother. But when the haircut occurred, I did not change. Mike’s haircut changed Mike, not me, despite the fact that we each thereby lost properties we formerly had (and gained new ones as well). This is because the property Mike lost, having long hair, is an intrinsic property, whereas the property I lost, having a long-haired brother, is not. Consider the property having long hair. When someone has this property, he has it in virtue of the way he is in himself. In contrast, when a person has the property having a long-haired brother, he does not have this purely in virtue of the way he is himself; he has this property partly in virtue of the way someone else is (namely, his brother) and partly in virtue of the relations he bears to that someone else (namely, the being the only brother of relation). When an object x has an intrinsic property, then, this is in virtue of the way x is, and not a matter of the ways other objects are, nor of the way x stands with respect to other objects. Intrinsic properties are “non-relational” and “purely qualitative”. If an object has an intrinsic property, then so must any “perfect duplicate” of that object. In contrast, extrinsic (non-intrinsic) properties may differ between perfect duplicates. Marble A may be a perfect duplicate of marble B despite the fact that A has, while B lacks, the property being ten feet from Ted. Shapes, sizes, masses—these are intrinsic properties. 1 CHAPTER 1. INTRODUCING THREE NOTIONS 2 Locations, speeds, ownerships (e.g. being owned by Ted)—these are extrinsic properties. I hope that the preceding paragraph has helped you grasp the notion of an intrinsic property, if you were not already familiar with that notion. But I suspect that you distrust the value of what I have said as an analysis of the notion, on grounds of circularity. You may ask me to explain the locutions I used in that paragraph: ‘duplicate’, and ‘had in virtue of the way an object is in itself’, for example. What is the “way an object is in itself”, if not the conjunction of its intrinsic properties? What is it for two objects to be “duplicates”, if not for them to have exactly the same intrinsic properties? Let us focus a little more closely on the notion of duplication, and its re- lation to intrinsicality. Objects that are perfect duplicates are exactly similar, down to the last detail of the smallest part. It is likely that there are no actual pairs of macroscopic duplicates. Even two marbles made by the best manu- facturing techniques are bound to differ slightly—a stray atom here or there. The differences may not be perceptible, but if they are there then the marbles cannot be duplicates, for duplicates may not have any (intrinsic) differences whatsoever. Of course, no pair of objects, even a pair of perfect duplicates, will share all properties. For consider any two objects a and b—only a will have the property being a. Although it is likely that there are no two actual macroscopic duplicates, it may be that there are pairs of actual microscopic duplicates: perhaps pairs of duplicate electrons. And surely every object, microscopic or macroscopic, has a duplicate in some other possible world.1 One reason for the importance of the concept of duplication is that ‘in- trinsic’ may be de ned in terms of ‘duplicate’, as David Lewis has proposed:2 (D1) Property P is intrinsic iff for any possible individuals x and y, if x and y are duplicates then x has P iff y has P In fact, the direction of de nition can be reversed: ‘duplicate’ is de nable in terms of ‘intrinsic’: (D2) Possible individuals x and y are duplicates iff for any intrinsic property P, x has P iff y has P 1 I ignore sets, numbers, and the like.
Recommended publications
  • Persistence, Vagueness, and Location
    PERSISTENCE, VAGUENESS, AND LOCATION Antony Eagle University of Adelaide, antonyeagle.org Forthcoming in The Journal of Philosophy I will discuss two arguments in favor of perdurance. The first is Sider’s argument from vagueness.1 Sider regards this argument as “one of the most powerful” in favor of perdurantism. I make the observation – obvious once made, but I am unable to find it elsewhere in the literature – that endurantists have principled grounds to claim that the argument is unsound (§§I–III). Having made this observation, I use it to emphasize a somewhat neglected difference between endurantists and perdurantists with respect to their views on material objects (§IV). These views, in the case of endurantists, lead to a further, less than conclusive but nevertheless interesting argument against endurantism – the anti-fundamentality argument – which I discuss in the second half of the paper (§§V–VI). I. THE ARGUMENT FROM VAGUENESS To begin, some terminology. An assignment is a (possibly partial) function from times to a set of entities existing at each time; a D-fusion of an assignment is an entity that is, at each time for 1 Theodore Sider, Four-Dimensionalism: an Ontology of Persistence and Time (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2001), at §4.9.3. 1 which the assignment is defined, constituted by the fusion of the members of the set which is the value of the assignment at that time; a minimal D-fusion of an assignment is a D-fusion which exists only at the times for which the assignment is defined.2 In these terms, Sider’s argument aims to establish this conclusion: (U) “every assignment has a minimal D-fusion”.3 U swiftly entails the existence of temporal parts, because the singleton assignment {⟨�, �⟩} is well- formed for any � existing at �, and so has a minimal D-fusion – an entity which is the fusion of � at � and exists only at �, which meets Sider’s widely agreed criteria for being a temporal part of � at �.4 Note how important the word ‘minimal’ is in U.
    [Show full text]
  • Parts of Persons Identity and Persistence in a Perdurantist World
    UNIVERSITÀ DEGLI STUDI DI MILANO Doctoral School in Philosophy and Human Sciences (XXXI Cycle) Department of Philosophy “Piero Martinetti” Parts of Persons Identity and persistence in a perdurantist world Ph.D. Candidate Valerio BUONOMO Tutors Prof. Giuliano TORRENGO Prof. Paolo VALORE Coordinator of the Doctoral School Prof. Marcello D’AGOSTINO Academic year 2017-2018 1 Content CONTENT ........................................................................................................................... 2 ACKNOWLEDGMENTS ........................................................................................................... 4 INTRODUCTION ................................................................................................................... 5 CHAPTER 1. PERSONAL IDENTITY AND PERSISTENCE...................................................................... 8 1.1. The persistence of persons and the criteria of identity over time .................................. 8 1.2. The accounts of personal persistence: a standard classification ................................... 14 1.2.1. Mentalist accounts of personal persistence ............................................................................ 15 1.2.2. Somatic accounts of personal persistence .............................................................................. 15 1.2.3. Anti-criterialist accounts of personal persistence ................................................................... 16 1.3. The metaphysics of persistence: the mereological account .........................................
    [Show full text]
  • Theodore Sider, Logic for Philosophy, Oxford: Oxford Univer- Sity Press, 2010, 304
    114 Prolegomena 11 (1) 2012 Morange, Michel. 2000. A History of Molecular Biology (Cambridge, MA: Har- vard University Press). Müller-Wille, Staffan, and Hans-Jörg Rheinberger. 2009. Vererbung: Geschichte und Kultur eines biologischen Konzepts (Frankfurt/M: Fischer). Olby, Robert Cecil. 1974. The Path to the Double Helix: The Discovery of DNA (London: Macmillan). Rheinberger, Hans-Jörg. 1997. Toward a History of Epistemic Things: Synthesiz- ing Proteins in the Test Tube (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press). Stubbe, Hans. 1972. History of Genetics: From Prehistoric Times to the Redis- covery of Mendel’s Laws (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press). Sturtevant, Alfred Henry. 2001. A History of Genetics (Cold Spring Harbour, NY: CSHL Press). Waters, C. Kenneth. 2004. “What was classical genetics?” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 35, 783–809. Robert Meunier Max Planck Institute for the History of Science Boltzmannstraße 22 14195 Berlin [email protected] Theodore Sider, Logic for Philosophy , Oxford: Oxford Univer- sity Press, 2010, 304 pp. Sider’s book is a welcomed addition to the series of logic textbooks pub- lished by Oxford University Press, taking its place as a good introduction aiming to provide a great supportive textbook for students of philosophy from the beginning of their education to the very end, and serving as a valuable handbook afterwards helping them in their research in areas of philosophy which employ a considerable amount of formal logic, includ - ing, but not limited to, metaphysics, epistemology, philosophy of language and philosophy of science. It is interesting to notice that the book was dedicated to perhaps one of the most influential contemporary philosophers, Ed Gettier, and, while this is not worthwhile information per se, it sets the tone for the entire Recenzije • Book Reviews 115 book, setting its scope to provide a clear and precise logic textbook for students not specializing in logic.
    [Show full text]
  • Curriculum Vitae
    JOHN HAWTHORNE Updated October 2018 PERSONAL DETAILS: BORN: Birmingham, England May 25, 1964 ADDRESS: USC School of Philosophy 3709 Trousdale Parkway, Los Angeles CA 90089 EMAIL: [email protected] AWARDS AND FELLOWSHIPS Part of three person Templeton Award (with Yoaav Isaacs and Aron Wall) for two year project on fine-tuning. Fellow of British Academy (elected 2013) Visiting Fellowship, Australian National University (for Summer 2014) Project Leader of New Insights In Religious Epistemology, a three year project at Oxford funded by the Templeton Foundation (since 2012). Visiting Lecturership, University of Helsinki, 2012. Nelson Visiting Fellow, Michigan University, 2011. Centre for Study of Mind and Language Project at University of Oslo. Project Associate since 2009. Visting Fellowship at University of Oxford 2005. Visiting Astor Lecturer, Oxford 2004. Research Fellowship at Australian National University (1993-1995) Grant from Australian Research Council for work on Grammar of Meaning book, 1991- 1993. Dissertation Prize for best Dissertation at Syracuse University (1991) First Class Honors, University of Manchester (1985) ACADEMIC POSITIONS: 1 Professor of Philosophy, University of Southern California, Los Angeles, USA (part-time 2013-July 2015, full time from July 2015). Waynflete Professor of Metaphysical Philosophy, Magdalen College, Oxford, UK (2006 to July 2015) Professor of Philosophy (part-time), Princeton University (2009-2012) Professor, Rutgers University (2001-2006) Professor, Syracuse University (1996-2001) Assistant Professor, Arizona State University (1995-1996) Assistant Professor, University of New South Wales (1991-1995) EDUCATION: PhD. Syracuse University (1991) B.A. in Philosophy and Politics, University of Manchester (1985) 2 PUBLICATIONS: BOOKS Monographs Narrow Content (with Juhani Yli-Vakkuri, Oxford University Press, 2018).
    [Show full text]
  • 322 Theodore Sider Writing the Book of the World. Oxford
    Philosophy in Review XXXIII (2013), no. 4 Theodore Sider Writing the Book of the World. Oxford: Oxford University Press 2012. x + 318 pages $55.00 (cloth ISBN 978–0–19–969790–8) Those who write or read books of the world are familiar with the big questions of existence, like ‘Are there universals?’; ‘Are there numbers?’; ‘Are there holes?’, and also with the catchy questions about the nature of beings, such as ‘Are properties abstract or concrete?’; ‘Do material things have temporal parts or not?’ and so on. But there is a new wave of theorizing in metaphysics that raises new questions. Some of them are about the nature of reality itself: ‘Is reality objectively structured or is it more like an amorphous lump?’; ‘Does reality have a layered structure, or is it “flat”?’ Other questions are concerned with the nature of metaphysics itself: ‘Is metaphysics a meaningful enterprise at all?’; ‘Are metaphysical debates substantive, deep, objective or non-substantive, shallow and in some sense subjective?’ The latter sorts of questions about the structure and the objectivity of reality and the substantivity of metaphysical and ontological disputes are usually called metaontological or metametaphysical. Basically we are given two kinds of answers to these questions. A deflationist says that “reality lacks ontological structure” (v), and (some of) the ontological debates are not substantive. A realist tries to prove the contrary. (Note that metametaphysics is not another discipline, it is part of metaphysics (as metamathematics is part of mathematics). So if a deflationist says that reality is structureless and that (some) metaphysical debates are merely verbal, then she does pronounce metaphysical theses.) Sider presents and defends a full-blooded realism about the structure of reality.
    [Show full text]
  • Four Dimensionalism∗ Theodore Sider Philosophical Review 106 (1997): 197–231
    Four Dimensionalism∗ Theodore Sider Philosophical Review 106 (1997): 197–231 Persistence through time is like extension through space. A road has spatial parts in the subregions of the region of space it occupies; likewise, an object that exists in time has temporal parts in the various subregions of the total region of time it occupies. This view — known variously as four dimensionalism, the doctrine of temporal parts, and the theory that objects “perdure” — is opposed to “three dimensionalism”, the doctrine that things “endure”, or are “wholly present”.1 I will attempt to resolve this dispute in favor of four dimensionalism by means of a novel argument based on considerations of vagueness. But before argument in this area can be productive, I believe we must become much clearer than is customary about exactly what the dispute is, for the usual ways of formulating the dispute are awed, especially where three dimensionalism is concerned. 1. What is four dimensionalism? There is a need to look carefully into just what three and four dimensionalism amount to. These names for the doctrines, rst of all, are poor guides. If saying that an object is four dimensional means that it extends through the ∗Predecessors of parts of this paper were presented at the University of Massachusetts, the University of Arizona, the University of Michigan, and the 1994 Paci c APA meetings. For their helpful suggestions I would like to thank Mark Aronszajn, John G. Bennett, Phillip Bricker, Carol Cleland, Earl Conee, David Cowles, Fred Feldman, Rich Feldman, Kit Fine, Tove Finnestad, David Lewis, the editors of The Philosophical Review, and especially David Braun and Ned Markosian.
    [Show full text]
  • Writing the Book of the World, by Theodore Sider
    bs_bs_banner Reviews e21 REFERENCES Haslanger, S. (2012), Resisting Reality: Social Construction and Social Critique. Oxford: OUP. Langton, R. and West, C. (2009), ‘Scorekeeping in a Pornographic Language Game’, in R. Langton (ed.) Sexual Solipsism. Oxford: OUP, 173–195. Levinson, J. (2005), ‘Erotic Art and Pornographic Pictures’, Philosophy and Literature, 29: 228–40. Mag Uidhir, C. (2009), ‘Why Pornography Can’t Be Art’, Philosophy and Literature, 33: 193–203. Mikkola, M. (2013), ‘Pornography, Art and Pornoart’, in H. Maes (ed.) Pornographic Art and the Aesthetics of Pornography. Basingstoke: Palgrave-Macmillan, 27–42. Writing the Book of the World, by Theodore Sider. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2011, xiv + 318 pp. ISBN 978-0-19-969790-8 $55.00 The main aim of this ambitious and impressive recent book from Theodore Sider is to argue for realism about structure; to ‘generalize the concept of structure, investigate its nature, use it as the foundation of “metametaphysics”, and reconceptualize metaphysics in terms of it’ [5]. There is an objectively privileged way to write the book of the world, and, as such, merely specifying truths isn’t enough; our theories must also employ the right notions, notions that carve reality at its joints—notions that are structural. Siderian structure is a generalization and extension of Lewisian naturalness. According to the abundantist conception, for any set of objects, no matter how arbitrary, there corresponds a property. This resulting immense abundance is unable to properly perform many of the central tasks for which properties are postulated; in particular, any two objects both share infinitely many such properties. This leaves us unable to track genuine qualitative similarly and difference—two electrons would be as similar as an electron and a cow.
    [Show full text]
  • The Argument from Vagueness Daniel Z
    Philosophy Compass 5/10 (2010): 891–901, 10.1111/j.1747-9991.2010.00327.x The Argument from Vagueness Daniel Z. Korman* University of Illinois, Urbana-Champaign Abstract Universalism is the thesis that composition is unrestricted: for any non-overlapping objects, those objects compose something. One of the most influential arguments for universalism is the argu- ment from vagueness, first advanced by David Lewis and later elaborated and defended by Theo- dore Sider. I supply a reconstruction of the argument and survey a variety of responses to it. 1. Introduction Under what conditions do some objects compose something?1 The intuitive answer to the question is ‘sometimes’. When a hammer head and hammer handle are firmly attached to one another, they plausibly compose something, namely, a hammer. Before the handle and head were attached to one another, they plausibly did not compose anything. The universalist answer is ‘always’: for any non-overlapping objects, those objects compose something. The handle and head compose something even before they come into contact. There is even something composed of your nose and the Eiffel Tower – something partly located in Paris and partly located on your face. Despite such counterintuitive implications, universalism is widely accepted among metaphysicians, and its popularity is in large part due to the argument from vagueness.2 The argument from vagueness was first advanced by David Lewis and was later elabo- rated and defended by Theodore Sider.3 It runs as follows: (A1) If universalism is false, then there can be a sorites series for composition. (A2) Every sorites series for composition must contain either borderline cases of compo- sition or a cut-off with respect to composition.
    [Show full text]
  • Presentism and the Space-Time Manifold* Dean Zimmerman, Rutgers University I. Introduction: Presentism Among the A-Theories Th
    Presentism and the Space-Time Manifold* Dean Zimmerman, Rutgers University I. Introduction: Presentism Among the A-Theories The A-Theory of Time and the B-Theory of Time McTaggart gave the name “A-series” to “that series of positions which runs from the far past through the near past to the present, and then from the present through the near future to the far future, or conversely”; and the name “B-series” to “[t]he series of positions which runs from earlier to later, or conversely”.1 McTaggart’s rather bland labels have stuck, and been put to further use. The “determinations” (his word), or properties, being past, being present, and being future are generally called the “A-properties”. The relations of being earlier than, being later than, and being simultaneous with, are the “B-relations”. These days, philosophers are said to hold an “A-theory of time” or a “B-theory of time”, depending upon their attitudes to these properties and relations. Some philosophers suppose that there are objective distinctions between what is present and what is past and what is future. In order to tell the full truth about time, they think, one must advert to the A-properties. Naturally enough, such philosophers are called “A-theorists”. Although A-theorists disagree about many details, they agree that the present is distinguished from past and future in a deep and important way. Exactly how to describe this difference is a vexed question, and some philosophers have argued that would-be A-theorists inevitably fail to stake out a coherent position.2 I shall
    [Show full text]
  • BO MOU (February 2020 Short Version) Department of Philosophy (O) 408
    BO MOU (February 2020 short version) Department of Philosophy (O) 408-924-4513 San Jose State University Email: [email protected] San Jose, California 95192-0096 Or: [email protected] USA http://www.sjsu.edu/faculty/bmou ACADEMIC POSITIONS • Professor of Philosophy (tenured), San Jose State University, USA, 2009-present. • Director of the Center for Comparative Philosophy, San Jose State University, USA, 2007-13, 2019-present. • Associate Professor of Philosophy (tenured), San Jose State University, USA, 2005-2009. • Assistant Professor of Philosophy (tenure-track), San Jose State University, USA, 2000-2005. • Visiting Scholar, Department of Philosophy, University of California at Berkeley, USA, 1999-2000. • Visiting Assistant Professor of Philosophy, Le Moyne College, USA, 1998-1999. • Postdoctoral Fellow in philosophy, University of Rochester, USA, 1997-1998. • Instructor in Philosophy, University of Rochester, USA, Spring 1997 and Summer 1995. • Teaching Assistant in philosophy, University of Rochester, USA, 1990-1993. • Assistant Research Fellow (equivalent to the rank of Assistant Professor), Institute of Philosophy, Chinese Academy of Social Sciences, China, 1987-1989. • Philosophy Instructor (in training), Section for Humanities and Social Sciences, the PLA Foreign Language Institute, China, 1982-1984. EDUCATION • Ph.D. (Feb. 1997), M.A. (May 1993), Philosophy, University of Rochester, USA, 1989-1996. [Dissertation supervisors: Richard Feldman, Theodore Sider, Rolf Eberle; concentration areas: philosophy of language and metaphysics] • M.A. (July 1987), Philosophy, Graduate School of Chinese Academy of Social Sciences, China, 1984-1987. • Philosophy study, Department of Philosophy, Peking University, China (in “Ministry of Education’s Advanced-Studies Program for College Philosophy Teachers” (studying Chinese philosophy and philosophies in other traditions), 1982-1983 academic year.
    [Show full text]
  • Two Ways of Saying No to Quine
    Symposia Melitensia, 2021, Vol. 17, pp. 37-48 Two Ways of Saying No to Quine Michael Grech [email protected] Abstract: W. V. O. Quine holds that the raison d’etre of metaphysics is the drawing of two lists; the list of entities that are part of the world and of those that are not. To achieve this aim, he suggests regimenting true sentences belonging to ‘our best theories’ to determine their ontological commitments. Many accept Quine’s project, differing with each other regarding what are the best theories, the sentences that belong to these and the entities that are part of the world. Other philosophers find this characterization of metaphysics deficient. Jonathan Schaffer considers the issue of what exists as trivial or uninteresting. The important issue is whether the things said to exist exists derivatively or fundamentally. He believes that there is a set of fundamental entities, and metaphysics ought to be concerned primarily with delineating this set of entities. Philosophical debates ought to be reconsidered along these lines. Theodore Sider on the other hand, thinks that the world contains a distinctive structure, and the aim of metaphysics is to discover the notions that enable us to describe facts concerning structure. Some of the possibilities and limits of these two approaches are highlighted. Key words: Quine, Schaffer, Sider, existence, ontology, fundamentality, structure Introduction W. V. O. Quine’s understanding of the primary aim of metaphysics, as well as of the means to achieve this aim, has been prevailing in Analytic philosophy for the past seventy years or so.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Plurality of Worlds, by David Lewis
    On the Plurality of Worlds, by David Lewis Louis deRosset February 27, 2012 David Lewis is one of the most influential philosophers of our age, and On the Plurality of Worlds (henceforth, `OPW ') is his magnum opus. OPW offers an extended development and defense of the hypothesis that there are many universes, things of the same kind as the universe in which we all live, move, and have our being. Lewis calls these universes \worlds", deliberately recalling the notion of a \possible world" familiar from modal logic and the metaphysics of modality. The title invokes the thesis of the book: there are a plurality of worlds, things of the same kind as the world we inhabit, differing only with respect to what goes on in them. Lewis sought in earlier work (Lewis, 1973, pp. 84- 6) to offer a direct argument from common sense modal commitments to the existence of a plurality of worlds.1 OPW offers a less direct argument. Here, Lewis supports the hypothesis by arguing that, if we accept it, we have the material to offer a wide range of analyses of hitherto puzzling and problematic notions. We thereby effect a theoretical unification and simplification: with a small stock of primitives, we can analyze a number of important philosophical notions with a broad range of applications. But the analyses Lewis proposes are adequate only if we accept the thesis that there are a plurality of worlds. Lewis claims that this is a reason to accept the thesis. In his words, \the hypothesis is serviceable, and that is a reason to think that it is true." (p.
    [Show full text]