Literary Criticism and Aesthetic Education

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Literary Criticism and Aesthetic Education Useful Works: Literary Criticism and Aesthetic Education Samuel Joseph North Submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of Arts and Sciences COLUMBIA UNIVERSITY 2013 ©2013 Samuel Joseph North All rights reserved ABSTRACT Useful Works: Literary Criticism and Aesthetic Education Samuel Joseph North This dissertation identifies the scholarly historicist/contextualist paradigm on the basis of which most work in the discipline of English Literature now proceeds, and proposes a critical and materialist paradigm as an alternative. The first two chapters offer a new reading of the history of the discipline of English Literature. Chapter one traces the early history of the discipline from the 1920s through to the mid twentieth century, focussing on the project of literary criticism, as distinct from the project of literary scholarship. It demonstrates that literary criticism’s characteristic methodologies of “close reading” and “practical criticism” were initially created as the tools of a broader project of aesthetic education, where the category of the aesthetic was being rethought in instrumental or incipiently materialist terms. This model of criticism was then turned to quite different purposes by later critics, who were committed to an idealist account of the aesthetic. Chapter two traces the history of the discipline from the late 1970s to the present, identifying a “scholarly turn” that transformed it from a discipline housing both the project of literary criticism and the project of literary scholarship, into a discipline that housed the project of literary scholarship alone. On the basis of this history, the dissertation goes on to argue for the development of a new project of literary criticism, understood as the close engagement with literary texts for the purposes of cultivating readers’ aesthetic sensibilities. The third and fourth chapters begin to lay the foundation for such a project. Chapter three attempts to provide criticism with both a new philosophical basis in a materialist account of the aesthetic, and a new way to conceptualise its institutional site as a site of radical, rather than liberal, education. Chapter four attempts to provide criticism with the first elements of a methodology of reading by way of a case study of Virginia Woolf’s Mrs Dalloway (1925). The dissertation thus has four elements: in chapters one and two, a historical element; in chapter three, philosophical and institutional elements; and in chapter four, a methodological element. Taken together, these provide at least the few first sketches of a foundation on which a project of materialist aesthetic criticism might seek to establish itself today. Table of Contents Introduction 1 - 35 General Introduction to Chapters One and Two 36 - 37 Chapter One: From Richards to New Criticism 38 - 67 Chapter Two: From Williams to the Present 68 - 120 Chapter Three: Useful Works, Useful Work – Aesthetics, Education, Criticism 121 - 177 Chapter Four: Mrs Dalloway and Political Feeling 178 - 226 Bibliography 227 - 232 i Acknowledgements My dissertation advisors Sarah Cole, Nicholas Dames, and Erik Gray have been extraordinarily kind, generous, and trusting. I cannot thank them enough. Warm thanks also to Jennifer Davis, Anne Diebel, Matthew Hart, Jessica Fenn, Darragh Martin, Sarah Minsloff, Sherally Munshi, Bruce Robbins, Lytton Smith, Gayatri Spivak, and Kate Stanley. Janice, Samuel, Blainey, and Samuel Ingemar. Gaurav, of course. Special thanks to Adam Alexander, Jason Alexander, David Backer, Winter Casuccio, Aleksandra Perisic, and Jason Wozniak. My thinking is no longer separable from theirs. Thanks most of all to Katja Lindskog, for just about everything. ii For Katja iii 1 Introduction I Very few people, it seems to me, start reading a novel by Virginia Woolf with the primary aim of learning more about British cultural life in the 1920s. Most of those who do are scholars. What non-specialist readers are looking for in literature is rather less easy to define: perhaps the best we can do at the outset is to say that they are looking for something to go on with; something that will help them live their lives. Few resources now exist within the disciplines of literary study that can help us to respond to this observation. A whole range of mid-twentieth century critical practices that tried to put literature into contact with these kinds of vague and capacious terms, the central example perhaps being F.R. Leavis’ neo-Arnoldian “criticism of life,” now operate within the discipline only in residual, discredited, and nostalgic forms. In their place, today’s most influential methodologies for literary study are all, in their various ways, historicist/contextualist, not only in the broad and welcome sense that they see literature in other than transcendental, universalising, ahistorical terms, but also in the rather more specialised sense that they treat literary texts chiefly as opportunities for producing knowledge about the cultural contexts in which they were written and read. Recent efforts to break new ground – “New Formalism”; “Surface Reading”; “Distant Reading” – have been, in this sense, repetitions of the same.1 In contrast to the non-specialist reader, the majority of today’s literary scholarship is most interested in Woolf for what she can teach us about her time and place. One 1 For new formalism, see for example Marjorie Levenson, "What is New Formalism,” PMLA, vol.122, no. 2 March 2007, pp.557-569; and Caroline Levine, “Strategic Formalism: Towards a New Method in Cultural Studies,” Victorian Studies 48 (Summer 2006): 625-57. For surface reading, see Stephen Best and Sharon Marcus, “Surface Reading: An Introduction,” Representations Vol. 108, No. 1 (Fall 2009): 1-21. For distant reading, see the papers collected in Franco Moretti, Distant Reading (London: Verso, 2013). 2 might then say that Jameson’s slogan “always historicize” is the horizon beyond which the disciplines of literary study have so far been unable to see. It has certainly been a very useful slogan. Many of the advances made by the discipline in the 1980s and 1990s were made by those acting in its spirit, if not always directly under its banner – the paradigmatic advance being the movement from those mid-century critical practices that treated works of literature as repositories of timeless and universal human values, to our contemporary scholarly practices that treat texts, in the broadest sense of “texts,” as deeply embedded in particular histories. Yet it has seldom been noted that our period’s governing injunction to historicise is by no means a unitary one, and has in fact concealed within itself two rather different demands, neither of which is logically necessary to the other. On the one hand, it has called on us to demonstrate the historical and cultural contingency of categories elsewhere taken as timeless, essential, or universal; yet on the other hand it has called on us simply to write cultural history. The two projects are quite distinct, and neither is implied in the other: just as one can, if one likes, write history from a universalist standpoint, one can also critique essentialisms without having to act as a historian. Jameson’s slogan – from The Political Unconscious (1981) – comes to us from a turning-point in the history of literary studies: the point at which our own historicist / contextualist paradigm began to assume its present dominance.2 We can see something of the complexion of this moment by observing Perry Anderson in 1982, opening his first Wellek Library Lecture at U.C. Irvine.3 Not without a certain performance of archaism, Anderson begins by looking back to Leavis, reminding his audience that: literary criticism, whether ‘practical’ or ‘theoretical,’ is typically just that, criticism – its irrepressibly evaluative impulse spontaneously tending to transgress the frontiers of the text 2 Fredric Jameson, The Political Unconscious: Narrative as a Socially Symbolic Act (Durham: Duke UP, 1981). 3 Later published as Perry Anderson, In the Tracks of Historical Materialism (London: Verso, 1983). 3 towards the associated life beyond it Social theory as such paradoxically lacks a comparable discriminatory charge built into it. (9, emphasis in original) Here at, or perhaps just after, the inception of the new historicist/contextualist paradigm, it was still just possible for Anderson to speak in the old way, as if it were generally understood that “criticism” was something distinct from and even opposed to “social theory,” and that the former was primarily a matter of forming judgments about the relative aesthetic merits of literary works – judgments that would then be taken to have some bearing on the rest of “life.” This was, I think, about the last moment in the history of the discipline when one could speak in these kinds of terms and hope to be widely understood. Over the next thirty years, the terms “criticism” and “social theory” would both be absorbed into a single project of historicist/contextualist analysis, making them all but interchangeable. Today “literary critics” read texts in order to understand and theorise the social. The specific sense of “criticism” that Anderson relies on here has been lost. But at that moment the two categories were still so clearly distinct from one another that it was possible for Terry Eagleton to outline a provocative strategy for turning “criticism” into “social theory,” or as he put it, “cultural analysis.” In 1983 Eagleton wrote that: Such a strategy obviously has far-reaching institutional implications. It would mean, for example, that departments of literature as we presently know them in higher education would cease to exist… Whatever would in the long term replace such departments… would centrally involve education in the various theories and methods of cultural analysis…. The genteel amateurism which regards criticism as some spontaneous sixth sense has not only thrown many students of literature into understandable confusion for many decades, but serves to consolidate the authority of those in power.
Recommended publications
  • AH 302: the Idea of the Aesthetic Syllabus Course Description Texts
    Fall 2020 AH 302: The Idea of the Aesthetic Syllabus The schedule of classes/readings is subject to change. Registered students should consult the syllabus on Google Classrooms, which will be kept updated. Instructor: Katalin Makkai Course times: Monday and Wednesday 15:45-17:15 Email: [email protected] Office hours: TBA Office: P98 004 Course description “Aesthetics” and “aesthetic” are terms that are often taken for granted inside as well as outside academic discourse. We speak of aesthetic experiences and judgments and qualities, and we employ “aesthetics” to designate the study of such matters. Although their root is taken from the Greek, the now-familiar terms (in their now-familiar usages) are, however, comparatively new. They are commonly regarded as having been introduced into the philosophical lexicon in the eighteenth century—a few hundred years ago. This course studies some of the texts that were key to the discovery, or perhaps the invention, of the “aesthetic”. What work was the idea meant to do? How did its evolution retain or reconfigure its original senses and purposes? Is the idea of the aesthetic problematic, ideological, or chimerical? Do we need an idea of the aesthetic to think about art? Texts All readings will be provided during the semester electronically and are to be brought to class as printouts. Electronic devices Students may not use any electronic devices (laptop, tablet, mobile phone) in the classroom, unless an accommodation letter has been issued. Requirements ACADEMIC INTEGRITY ​ ​ ​ Bard College Berlin maintains the staunchest regard for academic integrity and expects good academic practice from students in their studies.
    [Show full text]
  • Art, Clive Bell
    PHI 3240: Philosophy of Art Session 3 September 9th, 2015 Matisse, Henri. (1905) Luxe, Calme, et Volupte. Collingwood & Bell on the Ontology of Art 1 Today we officially begin a unit on the ontology of art, Ø the attempt to answer the question “What is art?” Ø This question is ambiguous. Is it asking: • What is the nature of artworks?, or • What is the nature of the practice of art? Ø We are going to read these authors as if they are answering the question as a claim about artworks. Before discussing Collingwood’s & Bell’s answers, let’s consider a theoretical predecessor. • The earliest views about art we have on record are mimetic, or representational theories: – these say that artworks mimic & depict images/events from the real world. • As Shakespeare’s Hamlet says about plays, artworks were understood to “hold as ‘twere the ‘play within a play’ the mirror up to nature” (Act 3, Scene 2) in Hamlet 2 Representational views were common among the ancient Greeks (e.g. Plato), • and popularized in 18th century Europe (especially by Charles Batteaux, in “The Fine Arts Reduced to a Common Principle” (trans. from French) Why have representational theories of art fallen out of favor? Greek sculpture, Fragonard, Jean-Honoré. nd Ø There are tons of counterexamples 2 -century B.C. (1772) The Reader. to the view, e.g.: – visual artworks which don’t clearly depict any recognizable objects or events (beginning in 1800s), – and purely instrumental music (e.g., symphonies) without lyrics or guiding narratives. • Mozart’s #40 in G Minor (1788): bit.ly/1O2GbSp Turner, Joseph Mallord William.
    [Show full text]
  • The Significance and Insignificance of Clive Bell's Formalism I
    Navorsingsartikels/Research articles The significance and insignificance of Clive Bell’s formalism i Johan Snyman Dept, of Philosophy Rand Afrikaans University JOHANNESBURG Abstract Clive Bell coined the phrase significant form. The way he initially defined the phrase and the way he implemented it were two different matters. In this article Bell's procedure is analysed as a characteristic of late moder­ nist aesthetics, i.e. an attempt to come to terms with the challenge o f the radically new in art. It is suggested that one should bear in mind that formalism in this sense is a theory of artistic material which explains how meaning is communicated and perceived through non-discursive qualities o f the artistic material. That is the relevance o f Susanne K. Longer's re- interpretation o f Bell's phrase. 1. Introduction Clive Bell’s aesthetics does not make for profound reading. Why bother then? The least one can say is that Bell contributed towards the modem aesthetic vocabulary by coining a phrase that has since become a cliché or hackneyed for that matter, viz. significant form. On the other hand, if one reflects from a distance on the Wirkungsgeschichte of Bell’s phrase as well as on the Wirkungs- geschichte of the problem he wanted to solve, significant form has an intriguing logic. Significant form as an aesthetic category has spawned quite a generation of related concepts, from Clive Bell to Susanne K. Langer’s unconsummated symbol, up to Nelson Goodman’s languages of art (Goodman, 1976), Peter A revised version of a paper read at a 2nd International Symposium on Formalism, organized by the Slovenian Society of Aesthetics in Ljubljana, 14-17 May 1992.
    [Show full text]
  • Are We Teaching High Art Or Low Art?
    CHAPTER 7 ARE WE TEACHING HIGH ART OR LOW ART? We are apt to call barbarous whatever departs widely from our own tatse and apprehension; but some find the epithet of reproach retorted on us. (Hume, 1965, p. 3) References to high-art notions span the globe. Centuries of continuous and changing conceptions of high art have involved, for example: ideas about the grand and the common, the technical study of its rhetoric concerns, its indifferent morality or lack of any firm moral basis to it, its notions of beauty, perfectionism, emotion, idealism, formalism, the sublime, taste, academic painting and correctness, can be found in the work of Homer, Aeschylus, Aristophanes, Sophocles, Plato, Aristotle, Longinus, Joshua Reynolds, David Hume and Clive Bell. So consequently, we are sometimes asked in art education whether the art we are teaching is: ‘high art’ rather than ‘low art’, ‘high culture rather than low culture’, ‘high art rather than popular art’, ‘high art rather than student-centered art’. What are all these different distinctions with ‘high’ and ‘low’ in them segregating? What are their contrasts? Can we segregate what we teach in art in these ways and ought we to do so? ‘High art’ is poor art if, as Marcel Proust satirically mocks, we confuse art with ‘high society’, ‘social ambition’ and ‘special friendships in the art world’ (Proust, 2001, p. 59–67). Proust was aware that in the history of art no continent, nation and single group of people have a monopoly over what is ‘high art’. The above terms with ‘high’ and ‘low’ in them certainly imply a clash of ideas about teaching in art, but if so, why should popular teenage music necessarily clash with classical instrumental music, since on the one hand classical music can perform in instrumental ways Beatles songs rather well, and popular music can have instrumental orchestral influences that can benefit its music interest.
    [Show full text]
  • The Mosaic of Aesthetics: the Manifestation of Clive Bell's and Roger Fry's Theories in the Waves
    Criterion: A Journal of Literary Criticism Volume 13 Issue 1 Winter Article 8 4-2020 The Mosaic of Aesthetics: The Manifestation of Clive Bell's and Roger Fry's Theories in The Waves Nina Katarina Štular Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarsarchive.byu.edu/criterion Part of the English Language and Literature Commons BYU ScholarsArchive Citation Štular, Nina Katarina (2020) "The Mosaic of Aesthetics: The Manifestation of Clive Bell's and Roger Fry's Theories in The Waves," Criterion: A Journal of Literary Criticism: Vol. 13 : Iss. 1 , Article 8. Available at: https://scholarsarchive.byu.edu/criterion/vol13/iss1/8 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at BYU ScholarsArchive. It has been accepted for inclusion in Criterion: A Journal of Literary Criticism by an authorized editor of BYU ScholarsArchive. For more information, please contact [email protected], [email protected]. The Mosaic of Aesthetics The Manifestation of Clive Bell’s and Roger Fry’s Aesthetic Theories in The Waves Nina Katarina Štular In Roger Fry’s “An Essay in Aesthetics,” published in 1909, he explores the question of what art truly is. A year after the paper’s publication, Fry met Clive Bell on a train and they struck a conversation about aesthetics that marked the beginning of Fry’s life-long friendship with the Bloomsbury group—a group that gave home to many influential modernist thinkers and writers. The aesthetic theory that Fry explains in “An Essay in Aesthetics” influenced Bell’sArt , published in 1914, which in turn affected Fry’s Vision and Design, published in 1920, in which Fry fully elaborates his aesthetic theory.
    [Show full text]
  • “Art” by Clive Bell Table of Contents Ideas of Interest from Art
    “Art” by Clive Bell Table of Contents Ideas of Interest from Art..............................................................................2 The Reading Selection from Art...................................................................3 Related Ideas............................................................................................... 16 Topics Worth Investigating.......................................................................... 17 Index............................................................................................................ 22 Clive Bell, 1908, adapted from Henry Lamb About the author . Clive Bell (1881-1964) studied history at Trinity College, Cambridge where he and many other undergraduates were influenced by G.E. Moore’s method of analysis exemplified in Principia Ethica. Bell writes that the students who met as a “reading group” in his rooms at Cambridge, together with the artist Vanessa Stephen (later his wife) and her sister, the writer and future Vir- ginia Woolf, initiated the circle of friends known as the “Bloomsberries.” The Bloomsbury Group, as it came to be known, was a literary and cultural circle including, among others, the critic and historian Lytton Strachey, the novelist E. M. Forster, the artist Roger Fry, and the economist John May- nard Keynes. Bell’s shaping of a formalistic æsthetic theory along the lines of Moore’s analysis of good strongly influenced early twentieth century art criticism. Quentin Bell writes that his father’s Art, although “more quoted 1 “Art” by Clive Bell than read . is one of the seminal books of its time.”1 About the work . In Art,2 Bell outlines a formalist theory based on his definition of art as “significant form.” True art, he believes, exhibits combinations of lines and colors which engender intellectual recognition and æsthetic experience in persons of taste. The resultant æsthetic emotion, he believes, is unique, morally transcendent, and independent of other kinds of human emotion.
    [Show full text]
  • Old and New in Modernist Art
    Chapter 2: Old and New in Modernist Art Mr. Thomas T. Baxter presents what appears to be a figure of Christ teaching a dickey-bird to chew worms. This work is labelled "St. Francis" (D‟Asise). I cannot concede his background but the face is remarkable; it is painted with very great skill, and the frenetic modernist who rushes by the picture merely because of the demoded subject-matter will miss one of the best pieces of detail in the exhibition. (Ezra pound, writing as B. H. Dias, in The New Age for January 17, 1918--22.12.235, emphasis added) Among the many kinds of artists, it may be that there are some who are hybrid. Some, that is to say, bore deeper and deeper into the stuff of their own art; others are always making raids into the lands of others. Sickert, it may be, is among the hybrids, the raiders. But . he is probably the best painter now living in England. (Virginia Woolf, writing in 1933, The Captain's Death Bed and Other Essays, 201-202, emphasis added) In 1918, we find Ezra Pound worrying about "the frenetic modernist" who will miss something of great beauty because its subject matter, which Pound himself has mocked, is "demoded." And, as late as 1933, we find Virginia Woolf, reporting on a conversation in "Bloomsbury" about Walter Sickert, in which a consensus is reached that this derivative painter, whose work is often naturalistic in its content, and might well have been associated by Woolf with her despised Edwardians, is the best that England has to offer.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 2 the Phantom Aesthetic State
    Chapter 2 The Phantom Aesthetic State Serious defect in aesthetics is the avoidance of considerations as to value. o It is true that an ill-judged introduction of value considerations usually leads to disaster, as in Tolstoy’s case. Some of experiences to which the arts give rise, are valuable This fact is naturally depending upon the theory of value adopted. The phantom problem of aesthetic mode All modern aesthetics rests upon an assumption which has been strangely little discussed, the assumption that there is a distinct kind of mental activity present in what are called aesthetic experiences. “The first rational word concerning beauty” – spoken by Immanuel Kant. o Kant attempt to define the ‘judgement of taste’ as concerning pleasure which is disinterested, unintellectual. o Thus arise, the phantom problem of the aesthetic mode or aesthetic state, a legacy from the days of abstract investigation into the Good, The Beautiful, and the True. Will, Feeling, and Thought: The temptation - will, feeling, and thought was irresistible. The faculties of capacities are reducible to three. Kant said in Critque of Judgement: o The faculty of Knowledge o The feeling of pleasure or displeasure o The faculty of desire Theses faculties stood understanding, judgement and Reason respectively The faculty of Knowledge Understanding The feeling of pleasure or displeasure Judgement The faculty of desire Reason trb.springline.in | Chapter 2 | Principles of Literary Criticism | 1 ‘Between the faculties of knowledge and desire stands the feeling of pleasure ’ just as judgement is intermediate between understanding and reason’ Kant went on to discuss aesthetics as appertaining to the province of judgement, the middle of these three, the first and last having already occupied him in his two other.
    [Show full text]
  • Anti-Essentialism Tom Leddy, San Jose State University
    San Jose State University From the SelectedWorks of Tom Leddy 2014 Anti-Essentialism Tom Leddy, San Jose State University Available at: https://works.bepress.com/tom_leddy/194/ This is a post-print of Thomas Leddy, “Anti-Essentialism,” The Encyclopedia of Aesthetics, 2nd Ed., ed. Michael Kelly (Oxford U. Press, 2014). If you wish to find correct pagination for a quote you should go to the published version. At SJSU The Encyclopedia of Aesthetics is available for students and faculty electronically in MLK Library. http://catalog.sjlibrary.org/record=b4969786~S1 ESSENTIALISM Anti-Essentialism From the late nineteenth century to the 1950s one of the main foci of aesthetic inquiry was the attempt to develop definitions of art and such related concepts as visual art, music, tragedy, beauty, and metaphor. Clive Bell (1958) [orig. 1914] famously stated that either all works of visual art have some common quality or when we speak of “work of art” we speak nonsense. DeWitt H. Parker (1939) argued more generally that the assumption underlying every philosophy of art is the existence of some common nature present in all the arts. This search for a common quality or nature of art was generally take to be a form of essentialism When analytic philosophers came to aesthetics in the 1950s they saw it as dominated by the essentialism of G.W.F. Hegel and such idealist followers as Benedetto Croce (1922) and Robin George Collingwood (1938). It was in this context that John A. Passmore (1954) attacked aestheticians for pretentiously saying nothing and for trying to retain mystery rather than dispel it.
    [Show full text]
  • Why Has Aesthetic Formalism Fallen on Hard Times? David E.W
    University of North Florida UNF Digital Commons Philosophy Faculty Publications Department of Philosophy Fall 2010 Why Has Aesthetic Formalism Fallen on Hard Times? David E.W. Fenner University of North Florida, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://digitalcommons.unf.edu/aphi_facpub Part of the Esthetics Commons Recommended Citation Fenner, David E.W., "Why Has Aesthetic Formalism Fallen on Hard Times?" (2010). Philosophy Faculty Publications. 2. http://digitalcommons.unf.edu/aphi_facpub/2 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Department of Philosophy at UNF Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Faculty Publications by an authorized administrator of UNF Digital Commons. For more information, please contact Digital Projects. © Fall 2010 All Rights Reserved Why Has Aesthetic Formalism Fallen on Hard Times? David E. W. Fenner University of North Florida 1. Introduction Nick Zangwill has done more than any person recently to resuscitate aesthetic formalism.1 I say ―resuscitate‖ because formalism has not been in favor for several decades. Zangwill writes that ―Aesthetic Formalism has fallen on hard times. At best it receives unsympathetic discussion and swift rejection. At worse it is the object of abuse and derision.‖2 The reasons many today believe aesthetic formalism is not viable have been the subject of discussion since the pendulum swing away from New Criticism, via the work of William Wimsatt, Cleanth Brooks, Clement Greenberg, André Levinson, and Heinrich Wolfflin. Most of these reasons have been discussed thoroughly, and those that I will review here that have been discussed I will spend little time reconsidering.
    [Show full text]
  • Considering the Nature of the Aesthetic Through an Imaginary Letter Exchange
    University of Nebraska - Lincoln DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln Faculty Publications: Department of Teaching, Department of Teaching, Learning and Teacher Learning and Teacher Education Education January 2005 Considering the Nature of the Aesthetic through an Imaginary Letter Exchange Margaret A. Macintyre Latta University of Nebraska-Lincoln, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.unl.edu/teachlearnfacpub Part of the Teacher Education and Professional Development Commons Macintyre Latta, Margaret A., "Considering the Nature of the Aesthetic through an Imaginary Letter Exchange" (2005). Faculty Publications: Department of Teaching, Learning and Teacher Education. 8. https://digitalcommons.unl.edu/teachlearnfacpub/8 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Department of Teaching, Learning and Teacher Education at DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Publications: Department of Teaching, Learning and Teacher Education by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln. JournalofjCurriculum Theorizing, Spring 2005 123 conJiiering tbe Nature of tbe Aeotbetic tdrougb an Imaginary Letter Excvbange Margaret Macintyre Latna University of Nebraska-Lincoln DearReader: I propose to consider the nature of aesthetics through the perspectives of three contemporaries of early 20th century England (Virginia Woolf, 1882-1941, Clive Bell, 1881-1964, and Sylvia Gosse, 1881- 1968), with claim to an intimate understanding of the aesthetic. This is an imaginative journey of my own making. I find imagination makes empathy possible.' Imagination allows me to put aside my definitions and distinctions regarding the aesthetic, and give credence to alternative perspectives. Aesthetics is an elusive entity that is used indiscriminately to capture a felt dimension of lived experience.
    [Show full text]
  • The Significance of Form | Nonsite.Org
    3/22/2017 The Significance of Form | nonsite.org nonsite.org - Feature - Issue #20 THE SIGNIFICANCE OF FORM SAM ROSE There are drawings by Adolph Menzel (1815-1905) in which the black lead of his carpenter’s pencil has been pressed into the paper with tremendous force, far exceeding the demands of the form or the requirements of the shading in that precinct of the image. I said to Kathrin: What we see here is rst-hand evidence of Menzel’s desire—his compulsion—to make the world as real to him, and at the same time to make himself as real to the world, as it was within his power to achieve. At whatever cost to strict delity to appearances, which was of urgent concern to him but only up to a point. As Kafka notes in another connection, “That is the point that must be reached.” —Michael Fried, “In the Kupferstichkabinett” 1 St Andrews Research Repository http://nonsite.org/feature/the­significance­of­form provided by 1/28 View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk CORE brought to you by 3/22/2017 The Significance of Form | nonsite.org Formalism in the visual arts just won’t quite go away. Ever since the full recognition in the early twentieth century that form could ground a distinct theory of art, writers in search of a denition that would differentiate it from their own views have embraced two premises: the idea that adherents of the theory understand contemplation of the form of an artwork to be both necessary and sufcient for its aesthetic evaluation; and the idea that this contemplation is a univocal, pure, or essentially content-less one.
    [Show full text]