How Natural Is Ficino's Natural Magic

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

How Natural Is Ficino's Natural Magic Myth, Cosmology and the Sacred Module 2: Essay 2 – Carole Taylor How 'natural' is Ficino's natural magic? Introduction Of all Ficino's work, the most pertinent to an understanding of what he termed 'natural magic' is De vita libri tres or Three Books on Life 1, particularly book three, De vita coelitus comparanda 2, which Copenhaver describes as the most important work on magic of the early modern period (Copenhaver, 1990, p.267). A number of scholars have noted the presence of theurgic elements in De vita . Kaske and Clark, for instance, stress the theurgic content of Ficono’s Neoplatonic sources (Kaske and Clark, 1989) pp.46-47), Copenhaver cites the impact of the theurgic magic of Iamblichus, Psellos and the Chaldean Oracles (Copenhaver, 1987, p.453), and Voss refers to it as 'a beginner's guide to theurgic ritual under the cloak of a manual on health' (Voss, Ficino's Natural Magic , p.2). The book only narrowly escaped being banned (Campion, 2009, p.89) and Ficino published an Apology just four months later, restating his position on magic, so it is clear that the more orthodox authorities viewed it with suspicion. However, through infusing the spiritual aims of Neoplatonic philosophy into Christianity, he seems to have reframed the idea of 'natural magic' altogether, extending it into a celestial context and emphasising the 'natural' life-giving properties of the celestial bodies. A complete spiritual and cosmological vision emerges, and perhaps a new understanding of the notion of ‘natural magic’. Natural magic At the time De Vita was published in 1489, magic was generally seen as incompatible with scripture (Campion, 2009, p.88); in particular, any practice which involved the invocation of spirits was considered heretical by the Church. Of the latter, there were two types, theurgy (high spiritual magic) and goetia (witchcraft or sorcery), both involving interaction with spiritual entities of one type or another (Copenhaver, 1990, p.273); and it was this interaction which was central to the Church's prohibition (Campion, 2009, p.94). 1 Hereafter referred to as De vita. 2 Hereafter referred to as Dvcc, except in referencing quotes when the full title Three Books on Life III has been used. 1 Myth, Cosmology and the Sacred Module 2: Essay 2 – Carole Taylor Natural magic, by contrast, was acceptable if it contained no demonic or ritual elements but focused itself on harnessing the powers believed to be implanted by God in the natural world for man’s use. Here we see the magician as natural philosopher, gaining advantage over his environment through knowledge of its constituents, in activities such as the making of medicines or prediction of the weather (Thomas, 1971, pp.302-303). We can locate this distinction in the seminal theology of Augustine and Aquinas. Because of the polarisation between incarnate and divine worlds which emerged in Christianity, the idea of a benign intermediary realm largely disappeared, save for the existence of angels and saints – the deities, daemons and spirits of Greek pagan belief became demonised, excluded from the benefic structure of God's universe as depicted in Valedes’ image of the Great Chain of Being , left (Voss, Iamblichus & Theurgy ). For example, the classical notion of calling down a divine presence to inhabit a statue was considered sinful; in addition, Augustine had condemned the idea of theurgic magic in City of God : "Who does not see that all these things are fictions of deceiving demons, unless he be a wretched slave of theirs, and an alien from the grace of the true Liberator? ... For these are the delusive appearances of that spirit who longs to entangle wretched souls in the deceptive worship of many and false gods, and to turn them aside form the true worship of the true God, by whom alone they are cleansed and healed..." (Augustine, City of God, chapter 10). Aquinas similarly warned against any practice which summoned demons or offered worship to pagan deities (Copenhaver, 1990, p.274 and 1984, pp.531-2). He also condemned 'judicial' astrology (the reading of horoscopes with a view to foretelling the future) where this acknowledged the planets as causal agents, denying free will (Campion, 2009, p.156). Theurgic magic Theurgy can be defined literally as 'divine working' or 'divine action'. It describes a ritual practice designed to invoke divine presence and achieve the goal of henosis, unity with the One. As Thomas describes it, "spiritual magic or theurgy was based on the idea that one could reach God in an ascent up the scale of creation made possible by a rigorous course of prayer, fasting and devotional preparation" (Thomas, 1971, p.320). As Proclus tells us: 2 Myth, Cosmology and the Sacred Module 2: Essay 2 – Carole Taylor "(Theurgy is) a power higher than all human wisdom embracing the blessings of divination, the purifying powers of initiation and in a word all the operations of divine possession". (Proclus, Theologia Platonica , 1.26.63, in Dodds, 1951) Theurgy is central to the work of the Neoplatonist Iamblichus, later to have a significant influence on Ficino (Voss, Iamblichus and Theurgy , p.1). Iamblichus taught a form of theurgic practice which he describes in his book De Mysteriis as "ritualised cosmogony" – in other words a re-enactment of, and reconnection to, the divine source (Collins, 2010, p.17). The theurgist worked with sympathetic resonance, beginning with the divine correspondences to be found within matter and moving upwards, tracing the signatures through the levels of being until eventually reaching a point where the soul unites with the One. For Iamblichus, matter contains innate divinity and one must work with it as the beginning of the spiritual journey; through acts of religious ritual, the world becomes ordered as a reflection of its divine counterpart. Iamblichus stresses that the divine cannot be reached through contemplation alone (Voss, Iamblichus and Theurgy , p.1-4; and Shaw, 2003, pp.58-59). "The perfect efficacy of ineffable works, which are divinely performed in a way surpassing all intelligence, and the power of inexplicable symbols, which are known only to the Gods, impart theurgic union..." (Iamblichus, De Mysteriis 96-97, in Taylor, 1821). Further, the gods are not separate from us but are "coexistent with our very essence" (Voss, 'Iamblichus and Theurgy', p.4-5); in other words, the human soul contains the divine spark, and is intrinsic to the hierarchy, being, in the words of Gregory Shaw: "an agent of cosmogenesis through whom the gods express themselves in the soul’s theurgic activity, and the specific faculty of the soul in which these theurgies occur is the phantasikon , the soul’s power of imagination”. (Shaw, 2003, p.69) Iamblichus is clear about the role played by daemons in theurgic work: “By daimons, I mean the generative and creative powers of the gods in the furthest extremity of their emanations and in the last stages of division... One must assign to daimons productive powers that oversee nature and the bond uniting souls to bodies ” (Iamblichus, De mysteriis II.1, in in Taylor, 1821 [my italics]). I highlight the final words in this quote since it is a theme to which we will return – the idea of daimonic intelligence as a force uniting 'soul to body' has a parallel in Ficino's 3 Myth, Cosmology and the Sacred Module 2: Essay 2 – Carole Taylor magic. Iamblichus speaks of echelons of cosmic beings – archons, heroes, daemons, angels, archangels and gods – numbered according to sacred mathematics, able to communicate divine knowledge and accessible through prayers and offerings. Despite this polytheistic aspect, however, it is essentially a monotheistic vision – everything in the cosmos is an emanation of the One (Campion, 2009, p.88). Ficino's magic: the beneficial powers of the heavenly bodies "Using natural objects, natural magic captures the beneficial powers of the heavenly bodies to bring good health. This means of action must surely be conceded to those who use their talents lawfully, just as it is in medicine and farming...One practices agriculture, another mundiculture....Just as the farmer tempers his field to the weather to give sustenance to man, so this wise man, this priest, for the sake of man's safety tempers the lower objects of the cosmos to the higher...[Natural magic] puts natural materials in a correct relationship with natural causes". (Ficino, Three Books on Life III, in Copenhaver, 1990, p.281) Here Ficino speaks in terms of medicine and agriculture. Natural magic, he implies, is like good husbandry – a farmer wouldn't sow his crop in the snow or in poor soil; by the same token, we cannot expect good health if we do not pay attention to the 'natural causes' emanating from the ‘higher objects of the cosmos’. Thus, it is legitimate for the magician to harness this power, as the farmer harnesses the power of the sun or the rain, each at the appropriate time. As Copenhaver states, for Ficino his magic was ‘natural’ because of these innate connections between "terrestrial, celestial and higher entities” – no commerce with demons need be involved. (Copenhaver 1990, p.271). If we are to “draw down favour from the heavens”, we must align our lives to the celestial picture: 'With this in mind, agriculture prepares the field and the seed for celestial gifts and by grafting prolongs the life of the shoot and refashions it into another and better species. The doctor, the natural philosopher, and the surgeon achieve similar effects in our bodies to strengthen our own nature and to obtain more productively the nature of the universe. The philosopher who knows about natural objects and stars, whom we rightly call a Magus, does the very same things: he seasonably introduces the celestial into the earthly by particular lures just as the farmer interested in grafting brings the fresh graft onto the old stock'.
Recommended publications
  • The Chaldean Oracles of Zoroaster
    The Chaldean Oracles of Zoroaster The Chaldean Oracles of Zoroaster v. 12.11, www.philaletheians.co.uk, 29 June 2018 Page 1 of 25 THEOSOPHY AND THEOSOPHISTS SERIES THE CHALDEAN ORACLES OF ZOROASTER Contents A brief note about the Chaldeans. 3 Cause God, Father, Mind, Fire Monad, Duad, Triad. 4 Ideas Intelligibles, Intellectuals, Iynges, Synoches, Teletarchæ, Fountains, Principles, Hecate, and Dæmons. 8 Particular Souls Soul, Life, Man. 13 Matter Matter, the Word, and Nature. 16 Magical and Philosophical Precepts [For would-be disciples] 20 The Chaldean Oracles of Zoroaster v. 12.11, www.philaletheians.co.uk, 29 June 2018 Page 2 of 25 THEOSOPHY AND THEOSOPHISTS SERIES THE CHALDEAN ORACLES OF ZOROASTER A brief note about the Chaldeans. These “mysterious” Akkadians or Chaldeans, whose name both upon classical and biblical authority designates not only a nation but that peculiar priestly caste initiat- ed in and entirely devoted to the Sciences of astrology and magic. Held sacred in all ages, this peculiar learning was concentrated in Babylon and known in the remotest periods of history as a system of religious worship and Science which made the glory of the Chaldean.1 [The Chaldeans] assuredly got their primitive learning from the Brahmans, for H.C. Rawlinson shows an undeniably Vedic influence in the early mythology of Babylon; and Col. Vans Kennedy has long since justly declared that Babylonia was, from her origin, the seat of Sanskrit and Brahman learning.2 . [H]Ea, the God of Wisdom, [is] now identified with the Ōannēs of Berosus, the half-man, half-fish, who taught the Babylonians culture and the art of writing.3 It is maintained that INDIA (not in its present limits, but including its ancient bound- aries) is the only country in the world which still has among her sons adepts, who have the knowledge of all the seven sub-systems and the key to the entire system.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Chaldaean Oracles 565
    Classical Quarterly 56.2 563–581 (2006) Printed in Great Britain 563 doi:10.1017/S0009838806000541 A NEGLECTED TESTIMONIUM ON THECHALDAEAN ORACLESG. BECHTLE A NEGLECTED TESTIMONIUM (FRAGMENT?) ON THE CHALDAEAN ORACLES* INTRODUCTION The Chaldaean Oracles, their Platonic context and their influence on later Platonism have recently received fresh scholarly attention (from, for example, Polymnia Athanassiadi, Carine van Liefferinge and Ruth Majercik).1 But although an important quotation from the Oracles—in indirect speech—can be found in the anonymous Turin Commentary on the Platonic Parmenides (9.1–8), this latter does not seem to have received a great deal of attention in the scholarly literature on the Oracles.2 Thus it seems that the Commentary’s importance with respect to the Oracles is either not fully realized or else undervalued. Probably because the piece of text is a non-literal, that is, non-metric, quotation, editors of the Chaldaean Oracles have rejected the notion that it constitutes an actual fragment, and have viewed it only as a testimonium or a text of reference.3 However, it will be argued that what we actually * I would like to thank the Swiss National Science Foundation for generously supporting my work on this article. I also owe a debt of gratitude to both the anonymous referee and Luc Brisson for their valuable comments. 1 P. Athanassiadi, ‘The Chaldaean Oracles: theology and theurgy’, in P. Athanassiadi and M. Frede (edd.), Pagan Monotheism in Late Antiquity (Oxford, 1999), 149–83. C. van Liefferinge, La Théurgie. Des Oracles Chaldaïques àProclus, Kernos supplément 9 (Liège, 1999). R.
    [Show full text]
  • Iamblichus and Julian''s ''Third Demiurge'': a Proposition
    Iamblichus and Julian”s ”Third Demiurge”: A Proposition Adrien Lecerf To cite this version: Adrien Lecerf. Iamblichus and Julian”s ”Third Demiurge”: A Proposition . Eugene Afonasin; John M. Dillon; John F. Finamore. Iamblichus and the Foundations of Late Platonism, 13, BRILL, p. 177-201, 2012, Ancient Mediterranean and Medieval Texts and Contexts. Studies in Platonism, Neoplatonism, and the Platonic Tradition, 10.1163/9789004230118_012. hal-02931399 HAL Id: hal-02931399 https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-02931399 Submitted on 6 Sep 2020 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. Iamblichus and Julian‟s “Third Demiurge”: A Proposition Adrien Lecerf Ecole Normale Supérieure, Paris, France [email protected] ABSTRACT. In the Emperor Julian's Oration To the Mother of the Gods, a philosophical interpretation of the myth of Cybele and Attis, reference is made to an enigmatic "third Demiurge". Contrary to a common opinion identifying him to the visible Helios (the Sun), or to tempting identifications to Amelius' and Theodorus of Asine's three Demiurges, I suggest that a better idea would be to compare Julian's text to Proclus' system of Demiurges (as exposed and explained in a Jan Opsomer article, "La démiurgie des jeunes dieux selon Proclus", Les Etudes Classiques, 71, 2003, pp.
    [Show full text]
  • Pythagorean Music in Boethius's Consolation of Philosophy
    32 RAMIFY 8.1 (2019) “How Pythagoras Cured by Music”: Pythagorean Music in Boethius’s Consolation of Philosophy KIMBERLY D. HEIL Interpretive schemata for reading Boethius’s Consolation of Philosophy are plentiful. Some of the more popular of those schema read the work along the divided line from Plato’s Republic, taking as programmatic the passage from Book Five in which Boethius discusses the ways in which man comes to know through sensation first, then imagination, then reason, and finally understanding.1 Others read the work as Mneppian Satire because of its prosimetron format. Some scholars study character development in the KIMBERLY D. HEIL is a PhD candidate in Philosophy at the Institute of Philosophic Studies at the University of Dallas; she received a BA in Philosophy from the University of Nebraska at Kearney and an MA in Philosophy from the University of South Florida. She is currently a Wojtyła Graduate Teaching Fellow at the University of Dallas, where she teaches core curriculum philosophy classes. She is writing a dissertation on the relationship between philosophy and Christianity in Augustine of Hippo’s De Beata Vita. The title of this piece is taken from a section subtitle in the work The Life of Pythagoras by the second-century Neopythagorean Iamblichus. 1 See, for instance, McMahon, Understanding the Medieval Meditative Ascent, 215. He references two other similar but competing interpretations using the same methodology. “How Pythagoras Cured by Music” : HEIL 33 work as it echoes Platonic-style dialogues. Still others approach the work as composed of several books, each representing a distinct school of philosophy.2 Furthermore, seeing it as an eclectic mixture of propositions from various schools of philosophy re-purposed and molded to suit Boethius’s own needs, regardless of the literary form and patterns, is commonly agreed upon in the secondary literature.
    [Show full text]
  • A Correspondent of Iamblichus TD Barnes
    A Correspondent of Iamblichus Barnes, T D Greek, Roman and Byzantine Studies; Jan 1, 1978; 19, 1; ProQuest pg. 99 A Correspondent of Iamblichus T. D. Barnes HE CORRESPONDENCE of the emperor Julian, as transmitted in T various manuscripts, includes six letters addressed to the philosopher Iamblichus (Epp. 181, 183-187 Bidez-Cumont).l Since Iamblichus died before Julian was born, it is impossible that the emperor could ever have written to the philosopher. On the other hand, the letters do not read like the productions of a deliberate forger, nor do they simulate an emperor's authorship. On internal criteria, one would naturally interpret them as letters from an absent pupil to his former teacher. Accordingly, Franz Cumont argued that these six letters, together with another two (Epp. 180, 182) and possibly another ten (Epp. 188-197), are genuine letters, which were mistakenly attributed to the emperor Julian because their real author was Julianus of Caesarea, otherwise known as a sophist active in Athens in the early fourth century.2 Joseph Bidez subsequently amplified Cumont's arguments into a study of Iamblichus and his circle which remains, after more than fifty years, the standard account of the philosopher's life. 3 The central thesis of Cumont and Bidez seems as secure as the nature of the case admits, but their deductions from it need some important modifications. First, as Bidez and Cumont later realised, a sophist from Caesarea in Cappadocia (Suda I 435) cannot be supposed to have written these letters,4 for one of the letters to Iamblichus states that writer and recipient share the same fatherland (Ep.
    [Show full text]
  • Proclus and the Chaldean Oracles
    Proclus and the Chaldean Oracles This volume examines the discussion of the Chaldean Oracles in the work of Proclus, as well as offering a translation and commentary of Proclus’ Treatise On Chaldean Philosophy . Spanu assesses whether Proclus’ exegesis of the Chaldean Oracles can be used by modern research to better clarify the content of Chaldean doctrine or must instead be abandoned because it represents a substantial misinterpretation of originary Chaldean teachings.The volume is augmented by Proclus’ Greek text, with English translation and commentary. Proclus and the Chaldean Oracles will be of interest to researchers working on Neoplatonism, Proclus and theurgy in the ancient world. Nicola Spanu wrote a PhD thesis on Plotinus and his Gnostic disciples and took part in a postdoctoral project on Byzantine cosmology and its relation to Neoplatonism. He has worked as an independent researcher on his second academic publication, which has focused on Proclus and the Chaldean Oracles. Routledge Monographs in Classical Studies Titles include : Un-Roman Sex Gender, Sexuality, and Lovemaking in the Roman Provinces and Frontiers Edited by Tatiana Ivleva and Rob Collins Robert E. Sherwood and the Classical Tradition The Muses in America Robert J. Rabel Text and Intertext in Greek Epic and Drama Essays in Honor of Margalit Finkelberg Edited by Jonathan Price and Rachel Zelnick-Abramovitz Animals in Ancient Greek Religion Edited by Julia Kindt Classicising Crisis The Modern Age of Revolutions and the Greco-Roman Repertoire Edited by Barbara Goff and Michael Simpson Epigraphic Culture in the Eastern Mediterranean in Antiquity Edited by Krzysztof Nawotka Proclus and the Chaldean Oracles A Study on Proclean Exegesis , with a Translation and Commentary of Proclus’ Treatise On Chaldean Philosophy Nicola Spanu Greek and Roman Military Manuals Genre and History Edited by James T.
    [Show full text]
  • Iamblichus' Exegesis of Parmenides'
    IAMBLICHUS’ EXEGESIS OF PARMENIDES’ HYPOTHESES AND HIS DOCTRINE OF DIVINE HENADS Svetlana Mesyats 1. Henads and the Problem of the Transcendent First Principle The question about the First Principle is one of the central problems of Neoplatonism as well as that of every monistic system of philosophy, that considers the world as a creation of a single divine Cause. The problem here is the following: the absolutely transcendent and self-su cient Principle does not need to cause anything outside itself, because to be transcendent means to be entirely independent from all the rest. But a principle, which is entirely independent from its own efects, cannot be a cause, since causality presupposes some relationship between the causative principle and its efects. Consequently we are faced with a dilemma: either to de ne some principle as a cause, so that it depends by nature on its own efects and is no longer transcendent; or to de ne it as transcendent, so that it cannot be a cause. In the history of Platonic philosophy there were many eforts to solve this dilemma. In one of his treatises Plotinus described the One as a “productive power of all things” (δύναµις τῶν πάντων)1 and so to some extent introduced into the Absolute all the plurality of its efects, at least in the mode of potency, power. Plotinus’ pupil Porphyry abandoned the idea of the transcendent Principle and identi ed the supreme One with Being.2 Iamblichus after him proposed the theory of “two” Ones, rst of which he thought to be completely inefable and inexpressible, whereas the second one he understood as a cause in the true sense of the word in so far as it 1 Plotinus, Enneads III, 8, 10, 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Analysis of Justice in St. Augustine's Political Philosophy and Nigerian
    International Journal of Education and Human Developments, Vol. 6 No 2; July 2020 ISSN 2415-1270 (Online), ISSN 2415-1424 (Print) Published by Center for Global Research Development Analysis of Justice in St. Augustine’s Political Philosophy and Nigerian Political System ONUCHE, Joseph PhD. Department of Philosophy Kogi State University Anyigba, Kogi State Nigeria Abstract St Augustine of Hippo (354-430CE) is the most influential Christian philosopher in western Christianity after Paul the Apostle. This paper analyses justice in Augustine‟s political philosophy as contained in His „City of God‟. It will be argued that, we could learn from his answers to bad politicking which resulted in destruction of State. His answers on various theological and philosophical issues have continued to be relevant in modern theological and philosophical debate. A lot can still be learnt from him even in the area of Church‟s response to bad governance. Augustine‟s argument is that Kingdoms (Countries, nations) without justice are robberies, as Kings (Governors) of such are robbers. This supposition is illustrated with three historical allusions namely: the encounter of Alexander the Great with a Pirate, the establishment of Roman Empire by Romulus, and the establishment of Assyrian Empire by Ninus. Contextually, Nigeria as it is today falls into this category of robberies as the British colonial masters forced this unequal union for their personal, self-seeking and self-interest, to satisfy their libido dominandi. An analysis of what Augustine meant by justice will be carried out. Philosophically, Augustine evaluated justice from Neo-Platonic background and theologically from Pauline concept of justice.
    [Show full text]
  • Boethius the Demiurge
    BOETHIUS THE DEMIURGE: TIMAEAN DOUBLE-CIRCLE SPIRAL STRUCTURE IN THE CONSOLATIO by Cristalle N. Watson Submitted in partial fulfilment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts at Dalhousie University Halifax, Nova Scotia April 2020 © Copyright by Cristalle N. Watson, 2020 For my Opa, Karl Heinz Hiob 1926-1999 Vir doctissimus & lover of words, who first introduced me to Latin Ars longa, vita brevis ii TABLE OF CONTENTS LIST OF TABLES..............................................................................................................vi LIST OF FIGURES...........................................................................................................vii ABSTRACT.....................................................................................................................viii ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS................................................................................................ix CHAPTER 1: INTRODUCTION........................................................................................1 CHAPTER 2: POETRY AND THE CIRCLE IN THE CONSOLATIO: AN OVERVIEW….............................................................................................................3 2.1 A "MULTIFACETED" CONSOLATIO AND AUTHOR.............................................3 2.2 THE METERS OF THE CONSOLATIO: A NEGLECTED STUDY............................11 2.3 IIIM9: CENTRAL PIVOT, TIMAEAN PARAPHRASE, PRAYER...........................17 2.4 THE CIRCLE IN THE CONSOLATIO AND IN IIIM9.............................................22
    [Show full text]
  • Pseudo-Dionysius and CG Jung
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Goldsmiths Research Online ! ∀# ∀ ∃%% &∀∋ (∀ ! % )∗+)% ! ∀# ∀ ∃%% &∀∋ % , % − . ! % / ! !00 %∋%%∀102++20 ∋ ∋ , % ∀∀/ ∀ ∋ / ∀% ∀∋ ∀ / / ∃∋ / 3% ∋ ∋ ∀ ∋ 4 5 / # / 3 ∀ 0 6∀ / ∀/ 3∀ 3 ∀% # 7∀ # / / ∋ ∀ ∋ ∀∋ 3 ∀ ∋ ∋ 3 13 ∋ ∀ ∋ % 8 ∀ 6∀ ∀ ∀ / ∀∋ ∋ ∋ % ∀ / 4 5 / ∋ ∀ ∋ ∀ ∃ 7 / ∀ / ∀ ∀ ∀ ∀ ∀ % (∀ ∀ / ∀ % / 3 3 % / ∀ ∀ ∋ ∋ 6∀ / ∀/ 3∀ 13 ∋ % !00 #∋%∋ %%∀1 ∃ ! /# 9∋%%∀1 Apophatic Elements in the Theory and Practice of Psychoanalysis: Pseudo-Dionysius and C.G. Jung by David Henderson Goldsmiths, University of London Submitted for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy ! ∀! I declare that the work in this thesis is my own. David Henderson Date: ! #! Acknowledgements I am grateful for the help I have received from my supervisors over the time I have been working on this project: Robert Burns believed in the value of the original proposal and accompanied me in my exploration of the work of Dionysius and neoplatonism. Brendan Callaghan supported me when I was in the doldrums and was wondering whether I would reach port. Roderick Main gave me encouragement to finish. He read my work intelligently and sympathetically. I regret
    [Show full text]
  • Pattison, Kirsty Laura (2020) Ideas of Spiritual Ascent and Theurgy from the Ancients to Ficino and Pico. Mth(R) Thesis
    Pattison, Kirsty Laura (2020) Ideas of spiritual ascent and theurgy from the ancients to Ficino and Pico. MTh(R) thesis. http://theses.gla.ac.uk/81873/ Copyright and moral rights for this work are retained by the author A copy can be downloaded for personal non-commercial research or study, without prior permission or charge This work cannot be reproduced or quoted extensively from without first obtaining permission in writing from the author The content must not be changed in any way or sold commercially in any format or medium without the formal permission of the author When referring to this work, full bibliographic details including the author, title, awarding institution and date of the thesis must be given Enlighten: Theses https://theses.gla.ac.uk/ [email protected] Ideas of Spiritual Ascent and Theurgy from the Ancients to Ficino and Pico Kirsty Laura Pattison MA (Hons) Submitted in fulfilment of the requirements for the Degree of MTh (by Research). School of Critical Studies College of Arts University of Glasgow Supervisors Prof Charlotte Methuen Dr Mia Spiro October 2020 Declaration of Originality Form – Research Degrees This form must be completed and signed and submitted with your thesis. Name Kirsty Laura Pattison ............................................................................................................. Student Number ........................................................................................................... Title of degree MTh (by Research) .................................................................................................. Title of thesis Ideas of Spiritual Ascent from the Ancients to Ficino and Pico .................................. The University's degrees and other academic awards are given in recognition of a student's personal achievement. All work submitted for assessment is accepted on the understanding that it is the student's own effort.
    [Show full text]
  • Augustine's Encounter with Neoplatonism* Augustine
    c Peter King, The Modern Schoolman (forthcoming). AUGUSTINE’S ENCOUNTER WITH NEOPLATONISM* UGUSTINE was surely the main conduit whereby late Hellenistic metaphysics, in the version we call ‘neoplatonism,’ A passed into the Latin West and coloured the whole of mediæval philosophy; it is hard to overestimate its influence or to overstate Augus- tine’s role in passing it along.1 Likewise, neoplatonic metaphysics had an immense impact on Augustine himself and on his own philosophical devel- opment. Reading just a few neoplatonic works in the spring of 386, he tells us, rescued him from sceptical despair and Manichaean illusion,2 giving him a metaphysical system that allowed him to recognize truths he had hitherto been unable even to formulate. For all that, scholarship has had a hard time taking Augustine’s philo- sophical encounter with neoplatonism seriously. That is because Augustine himself, despite the momentousness he attributes to the encounter, makes it hard to take seriously. For although he is at pains to emphasize its im- portance, and furthermore situates his report of the experience at the very centre of the Confessions (the midpoint of the middle book),3 his presen- tation of the encounter, some eleven years after the event, undercuts its philosophical significance. Furthermore, it is unlikely that this is acciden- tal; Augustine was far too accomplished a rhetor not to be aware of the effects of his literary devices. But why would he apparently pull the rug out from under the very point he was trying to make? * All translations are mine. This essay is dedicated to Eyj´olfurEmilsson on the occasion of his fiftieth birthday.
    [Show full text]