The Morality Behind Lipkin Gorman V. Karpnale Etaf Almutawa*

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Morality Behind Lipkin Gorman V. Karpnale Etaf Almutawa* Title Issues of Unjust Enrichment in English Law: The Morality Behind Lipkin Gorman v. Karpnale Etaf Almutawa* Abstract Since the decision in Lipkin Gorman v Karpnale [1991], unjust enrichment scholars have engaged in significant debate about the role that title plays, if any, in an unjust enrichment claim. Shortly after the decision was handed down, Peter Birks attacked the Court’s proprietary analysis and proposed ‘ignorance’ as an alternative unjust factor. Following Birks, a lively debate ensued, which revolved wholly around the impact of title retention by the claimant. The debate has continued to the present day: most recently, Robert Stevens argued against the proprietary analysis in Lipkin Gorman and suggested that the unjust factor should be ‘unauthorised payment of partnership assets’. What is clear is that, despite the longevity of this debate, a number of questions remain unanswered. This paper will argue that looking at the problem through the lens of title retention is causing more confusion. Under this approach, we are not yet able to even answer some simple questions, such as whether a finder or thief can be claimed against in unjust enrichment. The paper takes a fresh look at the proprietary analysis that was doing the work in the decision. It will argue that Lipkin Gorman was not necessarily about title retention or the passing of title. Rather, reference to the solicitors’ property seems to be an expression of the moral idea of ‘belonging’ that had to be explained by proprietary terminologies and common law of tracing. The idea of ‘belonging’ is broader than whether title passed to the defendant. The fact that the solicitors in Lipkin Gorman recovered the money in spite of the Court’s view that title had actually passed to the defendant supports the analysis based on ‘belonging’ which this paper advances. Table of Contents 1. Introduction 2 2. Setting the Scene 2 3. Lipkin Gorman v. Karpnale revisited 5 4. The aftermath 12 5. A general intuitive approach? 17 6. Conclusion 20 1. Introduction Two years before Lord Goff delivered the main speech in Lipkin Gorman v. Karpnale Ltd1 in the House of Lords, when unjust enrichment was recognised as an independent cause of action, he was invited to write a short comment about the future of the law of restitution.2 He said: “In truth, we are still in the position where we are asking ourselves the most fundamental questions about the subject – not only about its constituent principles, and about its form, but also about its relationship with other branches of the law, notably the law of contract and the law of property.”3 Lord Goff sought to answer some fundamental questions about the relationship between unjust enrichment and property in Lipkin Gorman. Although the reasoning in the case has faced a great deal of criticism,4 the case is extremely important: it inspires investigation of the meaning of ownership and title and their location in an unjust enrichment claim. This paper contributes towards this investigation. It will explore two aspects of the relationship between property and unjust enrichment. Firstly, the extent to which ownership may be a basis for unjust enrichment liability. Secondly, the form of ownership that is sufficient to be a basis for unjust enrichment liability. The paper has four sections. Section one will explain the core issue surrounding the relationship between unjust enrichment and property. Section two will revisit the facts and context of Lipkin Gorman. Section three will explore how commentators have read the judgement in Lipkin Gorman. Finally, section four will provide an alternative analysis of Lipkin Gorman. 2. Setting the Scene Suppose I find your property and take it. If you opted to bring a claim against me in conversion, no problem would arise. It is uncontroversial that you can sue the finder of your property in conversion.5 However, whether you could bring a claim against me in unjust enrichment, or, more generally, whether ownership may be a basis for unjust enrichment liability, is unclear for many reasons. Let me discuss the reasons. One general reason for this ambiguity was discussed by Niall Whitty. English law “accidentally overlooked its law of unjust enrichment for several centuries and has just rediscovered it. English lawyers are now busy exploring and developing it.”6 This is true. Judges and scholars only began defining the parameters of unjust enrichment in English law relatively * I am grateful to Robin Hickey and Samantha Magor for their comments. 1 [1991] 2 AC 548. 2 Lord Goff of Chieveley, ‘The Future of the Law of Restitution’ (1989) 12 The Sydney Law Review 1. 3 Ibid, 3. When Lord Goff wrote this comment, Lipkin Gorman had already been through the Court of Appeal. 4 Many commentators have criticised the reasoning in Lipkin Gorman, and particularly the arguments of Lord Goff. For some views see, Peter Birks, ‘The English recognition of unjust enrichment’ (1991) Lloyd’s Maritime and Commercial Law Quarterly 743; Lionel Smith, ‘Simplifying Claims to Traceable Proceeds’ (2009) 125 Law Quarterly Review 338; and Robert Stevens, ‘The unjust enrichment disaster’ (2018) 134 Law Quarterly Review 547. 5 Robin Hickey, Property and The Law of Finders (Hart Publishing 2010) 97. In the same way, the finder can sue any subsequent converter on the basis of the finder’s possession. 6 Niall Whitty, ‘Rationality, nationality and the taxonomy of unjustified enrichment’ in David Johnston and Reinhard Zimmermann (eds), Unjustified Enrichment: Key Issues in Comparative Perspective (CUP 2004) 658. 2 recently. This process began with the publication of The Law of Restitution by Goff and Jones.7 Then in 1985, Peter Birks published his book on the law of restitution.8 But it was only in 1991 that unjust enrichment was unequivocally recognised as an independent body of law in Lipkin Gorman v. Karpnale.9 But what we view today as an independent body of law has a longer history.10 Commentators,11 as well as cases,12 have shaped modern English law of unjust enrichment. And because the law is still developing, we are still investigating its scope and borderlines. For example, we are still considering what role, if any, a claimant’s ownership plays in an unjust enrichment claim, and whether unjust enrichment has one unified cause of action or whether its causes of actions are separate.13 The second reason why there is doubt about whether ownership can be a basis for unjust enrichment liability is that cases supporting this are rare.14 Though it is beyond the scope of this paper, this rarity is worth investigating. Anyone who suggests that this is because conversion is the orthodox claim should explain why that is. Is it a matter of historical custom or logic? Indeed, it is not just that cases supporting this view are rare. It is also controversial whether these cases should be interpreted as early unjust enrichment cases at all. One reason is that English law deals with rights and causes of actions, but this is a relatively recent phenomenon. Between the 13th and 19th centuries English law was arranged around forms of action.15 They were abolished in the 19th century.16 To see why this is a problem, we must first understand what forms of action are: “Let it be granted that one man has been wronged by another; the first thing that he or his advisers have to consider is what form of action he shall bring. It is not enough that in some way or another he should compel his adversary to appear in court and should then state in the words that naturally occur to him the facts on which he relies and the remedy to which he thinks himself entitled. No, English law knows a certain number of forms of action, each with its own uncouth name, a writ of right, an assize of 7 Robert Goff and Gareth Jones, The Law of Restitution (Sweet & Maxwell 1966). 8 Peter Birks, An Introduction to the Law of Restitution (OUP 1985). 9 [1991] 2 AC 548. 10 See, generally, John Baker, Introduction to English Legal History (5th edn, OUP 2019). 11 See William Evans, Essays on the Action for Money Had and Received, on the Law of Insurances, and on the Law of Bills of Exchange (Merritt & Wright 1802); James Ames, ‘The History of Assumpsit’ (1888) 2 Harvard Law Review 1; William Holdsworth, ‘Unjustifiable Enrichment’ (1939) 55 Law Quarterly Review 37; Wolfgang Friedmann, ‘The Principle of Unjust Enrichment in English Law’ (1938) 16 Canadian Var Review 243; and Harold Guttridge and René David, ‘The Doctrine of Unjustified Enrichment’ (1934) 5 The Cambridge Law Journal 204. 12 See particularly Lord Mansfield’s speeches in Moses v. MacFarlane (1760) 97 ER 676 and Clarke v. Shee and Johnson (1774) 98 ER 1041. 13 See Lionel Smith, ‘Restitution: A New Start?’ in Peter Devonshire and Rohan Havelock (eds), The Impact of Equity and Restitution in Commerce (Hart Publishing 2018). Smith’s approach is to divide the causes of actions of unjust enrichment into “big” and “small”. The interference with pre-property rights fall within the former category which Smith does not seem to support. For a reply to Lionel’s new approach, see Andrew Burrows, ‘In Defence of Unjust Enrichment’ (2019) 78 Cambridge University Press 521. 14 Arguably, these cases include Clarke v. Shee and Johnson (1774) 98 ER 1041; Bristow v. Eastman (1794) 170 ER 317; Holiday v. Sigil (1862) 172 ER 81 and Moffat v. Kazana [1969] 2 QB 152. 15 Baker (n 10) Ch. 4. 16 Common Law Procedure Act 1852. 3 novel disseisin or of mort d'ancestor, a writ of entry sur disseisin in the per and cui, a writ of besaiel, of quare impedit, an action of covenant, debt, detinue, replevin, trespass, assumpsit, ejectment, case.
Recommended publications
  • PDF Print Version
    HOUSE OF LORDS SESSION 2006–07 [2007] UKHL 34 on appeal from: [2005] EWCA Civ 389 OPINIONS OF THE LORDS OF APPEAL FOR JUDGMENT IN THE CAUSE Sempra Metals Limited (formerly Metallgesellschaft Limited) (Respondents) v. Her Majesty’s Commissioners of Inland Revenue and another (Appellants) Appellate Committee Lord Hope of Craighead Lord Nicholls of Birkenhead Lord Scott of Foscote Lord Walker of Gestingthorpe Lord Mance Counsel Appellants: Respondents: Ian Glick QC Laurence Rabinowitz QC Rupert Baldry Francis Fitzpatrick Gerry Facenna Steven Elliott (Instructed by Solicitor’s Office, HM Revenue and (Instructed by Slaughter & May) Customs ) Hearing dates: 1 and 2 November 2006 Further heard: 16 May 2007 ON WEDNESDAY 18 JULY 2007 HOUSE OF LORDS OPINIONS OF THE LORDS OF APPEAL FOR JUDGMENT IN THE CAUSE Sempra Metals Limited (formerly Metallgesellschaft Limited) (Respondents) v. Her Majesty’s Commissioners of Inland Revenue and another (Appellants) [2007] UKHL 34 LORD HOPE OF CRAIGHEAD My Lords, 1. This is a case about the award of interest. Questions about interest usually arise where the claim is presented as ancillary to a claim for a principal sum for which the court is asked to give judgment for the recovery of a debt or as damages. Less usually they can arise where interest is sought on a principal sum which has been paid before judgment. But in this case interest is the measure of the principal sum itself. 2. The question is how that sum should be measured. It is agreed that the calculation of interest should be the method of measurement for the sum that is to be awarded.
    [Show full text]
  • Knowing Receipt and the Law of Restitution
    467 Recovery of Misappropriated Trust Money From Third Parties: Knowing Receipt and the Law of Restitution S R Scott* Introduction A strength of the law of restitution is that it provides a means to reconsider existing rights and remedies. One area that restitution lawyers are turning their attention to, is the recovery of one's money from a third party. Two claims in particular - the commonlaw claim of'money had and received' and the equitable claim of 'knowing receipt', are attracting their attention. Assume that I steal your money and give it to another - the 'third party'. Through the medium of money had and received you may be able to recover the value of the money from the third party. The knowing receipt claim also facilitates the recovery of money from a third party, but in slightly different circumstances. This is when the'thief' is a trustee, the money is misappropriated trust money, and the plaintiff is the beneficial owner. Notwithstanding this general similarity, these claims operate in different ways. The focus of money had and received is on the third party's receipt of the plaintiff's money. The third party's knowledge is relevant only for determining the availability of defences, such as change of position. Subject to defences, a successful claim culminates in an order that the third party repay the value of the plaintiff's money actually received. Turning to the knowing receipt claim, while there is disagreement as to the state of knowledge that a third party must have, the orthodox view is that knowledge is a prerequisite.
    [Show full text]
  • Tracing in the Age of Restitution 377
    2003 Tracing in the Age of Restitution 377 TRACING IN THE AGE OF RESTITUTION MARGARET STONE∗ AND ALISTAIR MCKEOUGH∗∗ Restitution is a remedy by which a plaintiff may recover a benefit, enrichment or value that the defendant has obtained at the expense of the plaintiff. Although variously described as a right, a remedy and a mechanism, tracing is generally accepted as being more in the nature of a process1 and is a precursor to the assertion of a personal or a proprietary claim either at common law or in equity.2 Described in general terms, it is a process for identifying value that the defendant has received, whether or not in the form of specific assets, and establishing a link between that value and the plaintiff. Essentially, tracing and restitution are directed to the same issue.3 Expressed at a level of generality sufficient to comprehend both doctrines, the issue is the position of a person at whose expense another person has been benefited in circumstances where, for one or other reason, it is unjust that the beneficiary should retain the benefit. Both doctrines are directed to vesting that benefit, in some form or other, in the person at whose expense it was obtained and are limited to that benefit or to its equivalent value.4 The value of the benefit (be it property or otherwise) may be greater or less than the loss suffered or the expense occasioned and thus they differ from compensatory remedies which are directed to restoring the person’s former position irrespective of whether any benefit was received by the party obliged to make compensation or the value of any such benefit.5 ∗ Judge, Federal Court of Australia.
    [Show full text]
  • Law 680 Unjust Enrichment Mcinnes
    Law 680 Unjust Enrichment McInnes 1 Part I – Introduction A. The Nature of the Subject UNJUST ENRICHMENT IN A NUTSHELL THREE SEMINAL CASES Moses v Macferlan A third party named Jacob issued promissory notes to the plaintiff. The plaintiff in turn endorsed the notes to the defendant, but only on the latter’s undertaking to not seek recovery on the notes from the former on the basis of his endorsements. Contrary to the promise, the defendant successfully brought an action against the plaintiff for the amounts represented by the notes. The plaintiff then brought an action seeking recovery of the payments. The defendant resisted, arguing, inter alia, that liability can lie only if an express or implied promise to do so can be established. Lord Mansfield recognized that in the circumstances of the case, such a promise was implausible; a recipient of money obtained by way of adverse suit does not promise repayment. Nevertheless, he allowed recovery on the basis of a promise implied (or imposed) law: “If the defendant be under an obligation, from the ties of natural justice, to refund; the law implies a debt, and gives this action, founded in the equity of the plaintiff’s case, as it were upon a contract (‘quasi ex contractu’ as the Roman law expresses it). ... This kind of equitable action, to recover back money, which ought not in justice to be kept, is very beneficial, and therefore much encouraged. It lies only for money which, ex a quo et bono, the defendant ought to refund. ...In one word, the gist of this kind of action is, that the defendant, upon the circumstances of the case, is obliged by the ties of natural justice and equity to refund the money.” Analysis: transfer from Moses enriched Macferlan.
    [Show full text]
  • Tracing and Common Law Claims to Substitute Assets: Separating Myth from Reality
    Tracing and Common Law Claims to Substitute Assets: Separating Myth From Reality Jonathan Silver Submitted in accordance with the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy De Montfort University Faculty of Business and Law, United Kingdom Supervisors Mr Tim Hillier Dr Tatiana Cutts March 2018 I confirm that the work submitted is my own. I further confirm that appropriate credit has been given within the thesis where reference has been made to the work of others. 1 Abstract Tracing is a process by which a claimant shows that an asset represents a substitute for an original asset for the purposes of making a claim in respect of that substitute. Orthodox tracing theory says that this process involves the following of the value inherent in the original into the substitute. Orthodox theory also states that tracing is a neutral process, unconnected to any claims that may be made in the substitute. The effect of accepting this orthodoxy has been that the true nature of the tracing process has become obscured. In particular the failure of orthodox theorists to correctly identify tracing as being an exercise that can only be justified within the context of a fiduciary relationship has led to the widespread belief that it is possible to trace at common law. It will be argued in this thesis that this cannot be the case because the common law allows no claims with respect to substitute assets, and this makes the tracing exercise redundant. The notion that it is possible to trace at common law is contrary to properly understood authority and has no normative foundations.
    [Show full text]
  • Imagereal Capture
    TRACING AT COMMON LAW-MYTH OR REALITY? It is clear that there is a right to trace property in equity. It is a right in rem, and it enables a plaintiff to take priority over the ordinary creditors where the defendant is insolvent. This equitable proprietary remedy is available where, as a result of what has gone before, some equitable proprietary interest has been created and attaches to the property in the hands of the defendant.l In other words, this remedy would seem to be available only where there is a trust or a fiduciary relationship between the plaintiff and the defendant, or between the plaintiff and someone through whom the money has passed to the defendant.2 Although this limitation has been criticised? the scope of the remedy is tolerably well defined. But what of the right to trace property at common law? Is there such a right? What is its scope? A discussion of these questions is of more than academic interest, for if a legal proprietary remedy exists its scope would not depend upon the requirement of a fiduciary relationship, and this would be of enormous importance in the development of an adequate and unified law of restitution. Indeed, of such importance that it is thought to warrant one more attempt to explain the position at law. THE PROBLEM It is submitted that the crux of the matter is this: can a proprietary- - remedy for the recovery of money be enforced by an action for money had and received? Or does a plaintiff in such an action have to prove as an ordinary creditor where the defendant is insolvent? In other words, is an action for money had and received a strictly personal action, or does it fall into two distinct categories-the normal quasi- contractual action and a strictly proprietary one? It would seem that there is considerable academic support for the view that a proprietary remedy can be enforced by an action for 1 Re Diplock, [I9481 1 Ch.
    [Show full text]
  • Australian Challenges for the Law of Unjust Enrichment"
    SPEECH TO THE UNIVERSITY OF WESTERN AUSTRALIA SUMMER SCHOOL, 24 FEBRUARY 2012 "AUSTRALIAN CHALLENGES FOR THE LAW OF UNJUST ENRICHMENT" James Edelman• Introduction....................................................................................................................1 An historical account of unjust enrichment ...................................................................3 Enrichment and the law of trusts: the issue of principle..............................................10 Enrichment and the law of trusts: the issue of authority..............................................11 Authority recognising a trust as a response to unjust enrichment ...........................11 Authority recognising a trust in instances where a defendant obtains rights as a result of an unjust factor ..........................................................................................12 (1) Transfer of rights from a plaintiff without the plaintiff's knowledge.............12 (2) Transfer of rights from a plaintiff as a result of a misrepresentation or mistake ..............................................................................................................................14 (3) Transfer of rights from a plaintiff as a result of failure of consideration.......16 (4) Transfers of rights from a plaintiff as a result of undue influence.................18 The nature of the trust imposed ...............................................................................19 Conclusions: future development of unjust enrichment and the law
    [Show full text]
  • Unjust Enrichment in the Canadian Com- Mon Law and in Quebec Law Frustration of Contract
    Unjust Enrichment in the Canadian Com- mon Law and in Quebec Law Frustration of Contract IAN F. G. BAXTER* Toronto Unjust Enrichment That the law should provide relief in suitable cases, where one man has received an unfair benefit at the expense of another, derives from ancient concepts of justice. Justitia est constans et perpetua voluntas jus suum culque tribuere. l Some modern writers create the impression that unjust enrichment is rather a new discovery. No doubt there is some novelty in the manner and emphasis of modern development, but the fundamental principles of unjust enrichment have for centuries lain close to the hearts of true lawyers. The origins appear distinctly in Roman law, although it is doubtful if the Roman positive law contained a general principle of unjust enrichment .2 The Romans adopted the distinction of the Greek philosophers between idios nomos and koinos nomos and cequitas characterized an attitude of mind rather than a substantive concept for practical application.' But aquitas was a guiding in- *Ian F. G Baxter, M.A., LL.B. (Aberdeen), A.A.C.C.A., of Lincoln's Inn and of osgoode Hall, Barrister-at-Law ; full-time member of the staff of osgoode Hall Law School . The essay that follows, in a slightly altered form, was awarded the second prize in the fifth Canadian Bar Association Essay Competition . 1 Institute, I, 1, 1. 2 Paton, A Text Book of Jurisprudence (2nd ed , 1951) p 388 . There is a fragment without context from a treatise of Pompomus, "lure natures xquum est nemmem cum alterius detrimento et injuria fieri locupletiorem", D.
    [Show full text]
  • Imagereal Capture
    Volume 14(2) Equity, Restitution and the Proprietary Recovery ofValue 247 EQUITY, RESTITUTION AND THE PROPRIETARY RECOVERY OF VALUE JOHN GLOVER* I. INTRODUCTION The language of property in the private law is increasingly used to phrase remedies for the recovery of value. Where value is the subject of a claim and the courts express judgement property terms, they are enabled to confer the increased measures of recovery which proprietary remedies allow. But it may be at the expense of authenticity in the traditional concept of property. Can the old rules for the granting of proprietary relief expand to accommodate the new sense of property? Or must resort be had to some result-driven rationale to justify what is now occurring, such as unjust enrichment? Perhaps it ought be acknowledged that in determining the proprietary consequences of an entitlement to value, the courts are really exercising a discretion. Proprietary recovery of value refers to a certain measure of recovery of non­ specific interests in property, usually money. It does not refer to the recovery of any property in specie and is not the enforcement of title to, or rights over, any particular thing or monetary denomination. In all cases it is obtained through the exercise of equitable rather than common law rights. * BA (Hons), LLB (Hons) (Melb), BCL (Oxon), Lecturer, Monash University, Faculty of Law. 248 UNSW Law Journal 1991 Chase Manhattan Bank NA v Israel-British Bank (London) Ltd1 is an example of the proprietary recovery of value. The plaintiff was a New York Bank which mistakenly paid some $US 2 million to a second bank in New York, for the credit of the defendant bank, which carried on business in London.
    [Show full text]