Deliberative Democracy, Overlapping Consensus, and Same-Sex Marriage

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Deliberative Democracy, Overlapping Consensus, and Same-Sex Marriage View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Fordham University School of Law Fordham Law Review Volume 66 Issue 4 Article 18 1998 Deliberative Democracy, Overlapping Consensus, and Same-Sex Marriage Linda C. McClain Follow this and additional works at: https://ir.lawnet.fordham.edu/flr Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Linda C. McClain, Deliberative Democracy, Overlapping Consensus, and Same-Sex Marriage, 66 Fordham L. Rev. 1241 (1998). Available at: https://ir.lawnet.fordham.edu/flr/vol66/iss4/18 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by FLASH: The Fordham Law Archive of Scholarship and History. It has been accepted for inclusion in Fordham Law Review by an authorized editor of FLASH: The Fordham Law Archive of Scholarship and History. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Deliberative Democracy, Overlapping Consensus, and Same-Sex Marriage Cover Page Footnote Professor of Law, Hofstra University School of Law. I presented an earlier version of this essay at "The Relevance of Religion to a Lawyer's Work: An Interfaith Conference," held at Fordham University School of Law, June 1-3, 1997. Thanks to Jim Fleming for helpful comments, and to Hofstra law student Bella Blat and law librarian Connie Lenz for valuable research assistance This article is available in Fordham Law Review: https://ir.lawnet.fordham.edu/flr/vol66/iss4/18 DELIBERATIVE DEMOCRACY, OVERLAPPING CONSENSUS, AND SAME- SEX Linda C. McClain* I. DELIBERATIVE DEMOCRACY AND THE SEARCH FOR A LIMITING PRINCIPLE OF PUBLIC JUSTIFICATION A pressing concern in political and constitutional theory is how to construct a model of justification in law and politics that offers methods for securing agreement and social cooperation in the face of moral pluralism. A common goal of this work is to elaborate the re- quirements of deliberative democracy, that is, a model of democratic self-government that "asks citizens and officials to justify public policy by giving reasons that can be accepted by those who are bound by it."' Two fundamental questions are: (1) are there any limits to the grounds to which citizens may appeal or the reasons that they may proffer to support their positions?; and (2) if so, what are they? One familiar answer to these questions is found in John Rawls's account of political liberalism, which holds that where questions of constitutional essentials (such as basic liberties) and matters of basic justice are at stake, citizens and governmental officials should abide by an idea of public reason and satisfy the criterion of "reciprocity." Public reason requires that citizens not simply appeal to their compre- hensive moral doctrines, or seek the "whole truth" in politics, but ulti- mately appeal to political values or public reasons. They should give reasons that other citizens can understand and that they might reason- ably expect those citizens reasonably to accept. 2 Such work draws the criticism that it unduly constrains the appeal to substantive moral ar- gument and bars a perfectionist goal of "settling law and public policy in accordance with what is true as a matter of justice, human rights, * Professor of Law, Hofstra University School of Law. I presented an earlier version of this essay at "The Relevance of Religion to a Lawyer's Work: An Inter- faith Conference," held at Fordham University School of Law, June 1-3, 1997. Thanks to Jim Fleming for helpful comments, and to Hofstra law student Bella Blat and law librarian Connie Lenz for valuable research assistance. 1. Amy Gutmann & Dennis Thompson, Democracy and Disagreement 52 (1996). 2. See John Rawls, Political Liberalism (1996); John Rawls, The Idea of Public Reason Revisited, 64 U. Chi. L. Rev. 765 (1997) [hereinafter Rawls, Public Reason]. Rawls defines "comprehensive moral doctrine" as a moral conception that "includes conceptions of what is of value in human life, and ideals of personal character, as well as ideals of friendship and of familial and associational relationships, and much else that is to inform our conduct .. " Rawls, Political Liberalism, supra, at 13. Other leading work on deliberative democracy shares Rawls's premise that citizens should not seek to impose or establish their comprehensive moral doctrines in politics, but should abide by an idea of public reason and a duty of reciprocity. See Gutmann & Thompson, supra note 1, at 46-49. 1241 1242 FORDHAM LAW REVIEW [Vol. 66 and political morality generally."3 Moreover, it is said to lead to dis- content with democracy because it asks citizens to put aside their deeply 4held beliefs and moral judgments when they enter into politics. It is helpful to situate Professor Edward B. Foley's ambitious and thought-provoking article, Jurisprudence and Theology,5 within the framework of this debate over deliberative democracy. He too at- tempts to put forth an appropriate limiting principle for justification, pursuant to a principle of reciprocity. He finds that principle in a dis- tinction between the secular and the theological. Contending that it is possible, appropriate, and fair to have an "entirely secular legal sys- tem," he makes two basic claims. First, he argues that a constitutional and legal system can have a commitment to a set of "transcendent human rights" (that is, rights that exist without regard to their enact- ment by a legislature in a text, and that supersede any contrary legisla- tive enactments) without taking a position in the theological debate over the existence of God.6 Instead of resolving the question of whether such rights rest upon a natural law foundation or are the product of human reason through a social contract, both theists and atheists could accept the use of a principle of reciprocity to govern the identification of transcendental human rights. This principle of reci- procity seeks to secure assent on fair terms of social cooperation, whereby persons imagine themselves in each other's position, having to abide by whatever terms were mutually agreeable. Second, Foley contends that it is possible to use such a principle of reciprocity to develop a method of reasoning about transcendental human rights that does not reflect a commitment to either the natural law or social contract view about the origin of such rights. In written opinions, judges need not and should not rely upon theological argu- ment, which Foley defines as "any belief about the ultimate status and character of moral propositions."7 The problem with theological pro- positions is that "theology is different from other matters"-such pro- positions are "inherently unconvincing to someone who is not already a theist."' For the same reason, legislators should not draft their en- actments in "explicitly theological terms" and legislation should never "make reference to theological beliefs."9 3. Robert P. George, Public Reason and Political Conflict: Abortion and Homo- sexuality, 106 Yale L.J. 2475, 2504 (1997). 4. See generally Michael J. Sandel, Democracy's Discontent: America In Search of a Public Philosophy (1996) (attributing the "procedural republic" characteristic of America's public philosophy to, inter alia, Rawls's political liberalism). 5. See Edward B. Foley, Jurisprudenceand Theology, 66 Fordham L. Rev. 1195 (1998). Foley draws upon Gutmann & Thompson, supra note 1; Rawls, Political Lib- eralism, supra note 2; and Rawls, Public Reason, supra note 2. 6. Foley, supra note 5, at 1197. 7. Id. at 1207. 8. Id. at 1204. 9. Id. at 1209-10. 19981 POLITICAL THEORY 1243 But Foley allows at least one point of entry for theological beliefs into his otherwise "entirely secular" legal system. When a transcen- dental legal system confronts a problem that cannot be resolved by recourse to the principle of reciprocity alone, it is permissible for judges, lawyers, and (presumably) legislators, in attempting to justify a proposition of law or an outcome, to invoke the existence of an over- lapping consensus, or agreement upon a proposition of law or a legis- lative enactment arrived at from a variety of theological perspectives. 10 When it is uncertain how reciprocity applies in a par- ticular case, that is, "when secular (that is, public) reasoning can go no further to justify a decision the law must make," judges (and presuma- bly legislators) may appeal to an overlapping consensus of theological positions for one outcome rather than another, even though there may also be an overlapping consensus for the other outcome. 1 In this essay, I use the current debate over whether same-sex mar- riage should be permissible as a practical test case for Foley's strategy for achieving a secular legal system. This debate is a helpful test case because some scholars and many citizens and public officials believe that the issue of the permissibility of same-sex marriage cannot be resolved without recourse to what Foley calls theological arguments or beliefs, and appeals to theological beliefs feature prominently in the opposition to legal recognition of such marriages."2 I suggest that his ban on theological arguments may be unduly restrictive and unrealis- tic, as a comparison with Rawls's idea of public reason will suggest. At the same time, ironically, Foley's stricture upon theology may prove to be insufficiently restrictive because of his allowance of the appeal to an overlapping consensus of theological beliefs-what I will call the "strength in numbers" exception to his general proscription against theological argument. This creates unresolved tension over what his model requires in cases of apparent conflict between the de- mands of transcendental human rights and the existence of an appar- ent overlapping consensus to restrict or deny such rights. In such cases, what, ultimately, does his model require of citizens and legisla- tors engaged in deliberation over questions of basic liberties or rights?' 3 I conclude that Foley should incorporate, into his appeal to an overlapping consensus, a requirement of the evaluation of argu- ments for the legitimacy of state interests in limiting basic liberties or rights by reference to political values and public reasons.
Recommended publications
  • The Fragility of Consensus: Public Reason, Diversity, and Stability
    The Fragility of Consensus: Public Reason, Diversity, and Stability (Forthcoming in The European Journal of Philosophy) John Thrasher and Kevin Vallier Abstract: John Rawls’s transition from A Theory of Justice to Political Liberalism was driven by his rejection of Theory’s account of stability. The key to his later account of stability is the idea of public reason. We see Rawls’s account of stability as an attempt to solve a mutual assurance problem. We maintain that Rawls’s solution fails because his primary assurance mechanism, in the form of public reason, is fragile. His conception of public reason relies on a condition of consensus that we argue is both unrealistic in modern, pluralistic democracies and fragile. Rejecting his conception of public reason as unable to maintain stability, we offer an “indirect alternative” that we believe is much more robust. We offer experimental evidence to back up this claim. John Rawls’s early conception of stability required a substantive ‘congruence’ between the right and the good (1999: 496-505).1 He later rejected this view, however, believing it was untenable in light of the fact of reasonable pluralism. Pervasive disagreement among reasonable members of a well-ordered society will inevitably lead to a breakdown in congruence; destabilizing institutions based on Justice as Fairness.2 In Political Liberalism, Rawls attempted to avoid this problem by developing a conception of stability ‘for the 1 (Rawls 1999) is hereafter TJ. Many readers may be unfamiliar with Rawlsian ‘congruence,’ but the concept is pivotal. See: (Weithman 2010), hereafter WPL? Throughout, we us PL to refer to (Rawls 2005).
    [Show full text]
  • Public Reason1
    charles larmore 10 Public Reason1 For John Rawls, public reason is not one political value among others. It envelops all the different elements that make up the ideal of a constitutional democracy, for it governs “the political relation” in which we ought to stand to one another as citizens (CP,p.574). Public reason involves more than just the idea that the principles of political association should be an object of public knowledge. Its concern is the very basis of our collectively binding decisions. We honor public reason when we bring our own reason into accord with the reason of others, espousing a common point of view for settling the terms of our political life. The conception of justice by which we live is then a conception we endorse, not for the different reasons we may each discover, and not simply for reasons we happen to share, but instead for reasons that count for us because we can affirm them together. This spirit of reciprocity is the foundation of a democratic society. Public reason has emerged as an explicit theme in Rawls’s writings only after A Theory of Justice with his turn to “political liberalism” and the pursuit of a common ground on which people can stand de- spite their deep ethical and religious differences. But the concept itself has always been at the heart of his philosophy. It runs through his first book in the guise of the idea of publicity, playing an in- dispensable part in the theory of justice as fairness. The notion of fairness itself, so central to Rawls’s thought, denotes that mutual acknowledgement of principles which public reason demands and which forms the real import of the language of social contract he has used to articulate his conception of justice.
    [Show full text]
  • The Lukewarm Religions of Rawls' Overlapping Consensus
    Aporia vol. 24 no. 2—2014 The Lukewarm Religions of Rawls’ Overlapping Consensus ALEXANDER SCHAEFER With regard to abortion, I accept my church’s position that life begins at conception. That’s the church’s judgment. I accept it in my personal life. But I refuse to impose it on equally devout Christians and Muslims and Jews and—I just refuse to impose that on others, unlike my friend here, the congressman. I do not believe that we have a right to tell other people that women can’t control their body. It’s a decision between them and their doctor, in my view. —Vice President Joe Biden I. Introduction iden’s statement neatly exemplifies Rawls’ ideal separation of one’s Comprehensive Moral Doctrine (CMD) from the sphere of political Breason. Given what Rawls calls the “burdens of judgment,” it is un- reasonable for any citizen in a democratic society to expect all others to adopt his or her exact same doctrine (54).1 Therefore, it is also unreason- able to use the values and beliefs of one’s particular CMD to form laws that will apply equally to all citizens. Doing so would force those who reasonably disagree with one’s CMD to act in accord with it. If a legitimate and stable 1 Although a CMD can be any system of values that extends beyond the political (containing “nonpolitical values and virtues” (Rawls 175)) this paper will treat only religious CMDs. Whether parts of this critique can be extended to cover other types of CMDs is an open question.
    [Show full text]
  • Fairness, Consensus, and the Justification of the Ideal Liberal Constitution
    Fairness, Consensus, and the Justification of the Ideal Liberal Constitution Philip Cook LSE Law, Society and Economy Working Papers 4/2009 London School of Economics and Political Science Law Department This paper can be downloaded without charge from LSE Law, Society and Economy Working Papers at: www.lse.ac.uk/collections/law/wps/wps.htm and the Social Sciences Research Network electronic library at: http://ssrn.com/abstract=1331374. © Philip Cook. Users may download and/or print one copy to facilitate their private study or for non-commercial research. Users may not engage in further distribution of this material or use it for any profit-making activities or any other form of commercial gain. Electronic copy available at: http://ssrn.com/abstract=1331374 Philip Cook The Justification of the Ideal Liberal Constitution Fairness, Consensus, and the Justification of the Ideal Liberal Constitution Philip Cook * Abstract: In Constitutional Goods Brudner argues that the justification of the ideal liberal constitutional must be based on an alternative conception of public reason from that that presented by Rawls in Political Liberalism. This paper sets out the disagreement between the two notions of justification, and argues that Brudner’s proposed account is problematic on two accounts. Firstly, it seems internally inconsistent. Brudner’s alternative to Rawls’s overlapping consensus, a convergent consensus on an inclusive conception of liberalism, will be impossible given the plural and often contradictory nature of differing liberal doctrines. Secondly, even if such a consensus is possible it will be characterized by modus vivendi rather than a reasonable agreement based on the value of fairness.
    [Show full text]
  • Consensus on What? Convergence for What? Four Models of Political
    Consensus on What? Convergence for What? Four Models of Political Liberalism* Gerald Gaus and Chad Van Schoelandt 1 A PROJECT, NOT AN EDIFICE In an early symposium on A Theory of Justice, John Chapman remarked that “Rawls’s theory has both the simplicity and the complexity of a Gothic cathedral.”1 In his recent important book on Rawls’s political turn, Paul Weithman notes and endorses this characterization. Weithman seeks a unified interpretation of Theory, Rawls’s political turn and its search for stability, overcoming the many partial interpretations that take only “one view of the cathedral.”2 When readers turn to Political Liberalism, the style that comes to mind is not gothic, but baroque.3 If one takes even the 1993 hardback edition of Political Liberalism as a single, unified construction — much less the paperback edition, which includes the important “Reply to Habermas”— it has the tension, movement, complexity and irregularity of the baroque. Nevertheless, at least as far as we can see, the baroque interpretation too fails — after numerous readings, we are unable to construct a reasonably coherent and viable interpretation that accounts for all the *An earlier version of this essay was delivered to the 25th anniversary of conference of Rawls's Political Liberalism, hosted by the Jean Beer Blumenfeld Center for Ethics, Georgia State University, May, 2016. Our thanks for the comments and suggestions of all the participants; subsequent comments by Paul Weithman were especially vaulable, as were discussions with Brian Kogelmann. 1 John W. Chapman, “Rawls’s Theory of Justice,” American Political Science Review, vol.
    [Show full text]
  • Catholics, Muslims, and the Possibility of Overlapping Consensus Elizabeth A
    Florida State University Libraries Electronic Theses, Treatises and Dissertations The Graduate School 2009 Reconciled to Liberty: Catholics, Muslims, and the Possibility of Overlapping Consensus Elizabeth A. Barre Follow this and additional works at the FSU Digital Library. For more information, please contact [email protected] FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY COLLEGE OF ARTS AND SCIENCES RECONCILED TO LIBERTY: CATHOLICS, MUSLIMS, AND THE POSSIBILITY OF OVERLAPPING CONSENSUS By ELIZABETH A. BARRE A Dissertation submitted to the Department of Religion in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Degree Awarded: Summer Semester, 2009 Copyright © 2009 Elizabeth A. Barre All Rights Reserved The members of the committee approve the dissertation of Elizabeth A. Barre defended on July 7, 2009. _______________________________________ John Kelsay Professor Directing Dissertation _______________________________________ M. Victoria Costa Outside Committee Member _______________________________________ Sumner B. Twiss Committee Member _______________________________________ Aline Kalbian Committee Member _______________________________________ Adam Gaiser Committee Member Approved: _____________________________________________ John Corrigan, Chair, Department of Religion The Graduate School has verified and approved the above-named committee members. ii One of the main aims of moral philosophy is to look for possible bases of agreement where none seem to exist. It must attempt to extend the range of some existing consensus and to frame more discriminating moral conceptions for our consideration. Justifying grounds do not lie ready at hand: they need to be discovered and suitably expressed, sometimes by lucky guesses, sometimes by noting the requirements of theory. —John Rawls, A Theory of Justice iii ACKNOWLEDGMENTS A central theme of the pages that follow is that our moral arguments and identities are inextricably linked to and shaped by the communities in which we find ourselves.
    [Show full text]
  • Jack Donnelly Graduate School of International Studies University of Denver
    THE RELATIVE UNIVERSALITY OF HUMAN RIGHTS1 Jack Donnelly Graduate School of International Studies University of Denver [forthcoming, 2007, Human Rights Quarterly] Human rights as an international political project are closely tied to claims of universality. The foundational international legal instrument is the Universal Declaration of Human Rights. The 1993 World Human Rights Conference, in the first operative paragraph of the Vienna Declaration and Programme of Action, asserted that “the universal nature of these rights and freedoms is beyond question.” Attacks on the universality of human rights, however, are also widespread. And some versions of universalism are indeed theoretically indefensible, politically pernicious, or both. This essay explores several different senses of “universal” human rights. I also consider, somewhat more briefly, several senses in which it might be held that human rights are “relative.” I defend what I call functional, international legal, and overlapping consensus universality. But I argue that what I call anthropological and ontological universality are empirically, philosophically, or politically indefensible. I also emphasize that universal human rights, properly understood, leave considerable space for national, regional, cultural particularity and other forms of diversity and relativity. 1 The tone of this essay owes much to a long conversation with Daniel Bell and Joseph Chan in Japan nearly a decade ago. I thank them for the sort of deep engagement of fundamental differences that represents one of the best and most exhilarating features of intellectual life. I also thank audiences at Yonsei University, Ritsumeikan University, and Occidental College, where earlier versions of this paper were presented, and more than two decades of students who have constantly pushed me to clarify, sharpen, and properly modulate my arguments.
    [Show full text]
  • Public Reason and Political Justifications
    Fordham Law Review Volume 72 Issue 5 Article 29 2004 Public Reason and Political Justifications Samuel Freeman Follow this and additional works at: https://ir.lawnet.fordham.edu/flr Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Samuel Freeman, Public Reason and Political Justifications, 72 Fordham L. Rev. 2021 (2004). Available at: https://ir.lawnet.fordham.edu/flr/vol72/iss5/29 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by FLASH: The Fordham Law Archive of Scholarship and History. It has been accepted for inclusion in Fordham Law Review by an authorized editor of FLASH: The Fordham Law Archive of Scholarship and History. For more information, please contact [email protected]. THE IDEA OF PUBLIC REASON REVISITED PUBLIC REASON AND POLITICAL JUSTIFICATIONS Samuel Freeman* INTRODUCTION In a constitutional democracy citizens normally have a sense of the kinds of reasons that are fittingly appealed to, as well as those that are not, in legislative and judicial forums and when arguing about laws and the constitution with people who hold different religious or philosophical views. We see this all the time in arguments in news editorials, for example. But it is very hard to characterize these reasons in any straightforward way. It is not enough to say that, because people have different faiths and their differences are irresolvable, religious considerations ought to be kept out of politics. For people have irresolvably conflicting philosophical and ethical beliefs too. Moreover, sometimes it may be wholly fitting within public political life for members of a faith to declare the religious beliefs that lead them to support or oppose measures involving fundamental questions of justice (Martin Luther King's religious declarations in support of civil rights is one example).
    [Show full text]
  • Rawls, Religion and the Ethics of Citizenship: Toward a Liberal Reconciliation
    University of Tennessee, Knoxville TRACE: Tennessee Research and Creative Exchange Doctoral Dissertations Graduate School 12-2013 Rawls, Religion and the Ethics of Citizenship: Toward a Liberal Reconciliation Jeffrey Michael Cervantez University of Tennessee, Knoxville, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://trace.tennessee.edu/utk_graddiss Part of the Ethics and Political Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Cervantez, Jeffrey Michael, "Rawls, Religion and the Ethics of Citizenship: Toward a Liberal Reconciliation. " PhD diss., University of Tennessee, 2013. https://trace.tennessee.edu/utk_graddiss/2562 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at TRACE: Tennessee Research and Creative Exchange. It has been accepted for inclusion in Doctoral Dissertations by an authorized administrator of TRACE: Tennessee Research and Creative Exchange. For more information, please contact [email protected]. To the Graduate Council: I am submitting herewith a dissertation written by Jeffrey Michael Cervantez entitled "Rawls, Religion and the Ethics of Citizenship: Toward a Liberal Reconciliation." I have examined the final electronic copy of this dissertation for form and content and recommend that it be accepted in partial fulfillment of the equirr ements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy, with a major in Philosophy. David Reidy, Major Professor We have read this dissertation and recommend its acceptance: E.J. Coffman, Adam Cureton, Anthony Nownes Accepted for the Council: Carolyn R. Hodges Vice Provost and Dean of the Graduate School (Original signatures are on file with official studentecor r ds.) Rawls, Religion and the Ethics of Citizenship: Toward a Liberal Reconciliation A Dissertation Presented for the Doctor of Philosophy Degree The University of Tennessee, Knoxville Jeffrey Michael Cervantez December 2013 ii Copyright © 2013 by Jeffrey M.
    [Show full text]
  • Vol. 2, No 1, 2021 Chris O. Abakare JOHN RAWLS
    InternationalVol. 2, No 1, Journal 2021 Social Sciences and Education Chris O. Abakare Volume 2, Number 1, 2021, pa. 30-51 JOHN RAWLS: OVERLAPPING CONSENSUS AND PUBLIC REA Chris O. Abakare Department of Philosophy, Nnamdi Azikiwe University, Ifite Road, 420110, Awka, Anambra State, Nigeria Email; [email protected] Received : 11 Mei 2021 Reviewed: 4-23 Juni 2021 Accepted: 31 Juli 2021 ABSTRACT John Rawls Rawls’s political thought has been chosen for study because he has been very influential and his philosophy can be used in interpreting modern constitution. Rawls’ later works had focused on the question of stability; how a society ordered by the two principles of justice endures? His answer to this question is contained in a collection of lectures titled Political Liberation. In these lectures, Rawls introduced the ‘idea of an overlapping consensus’ – or agreement of justice as fairness between citizens who hold different religious and philosophical views. Political liberalism also introduced the idea of Public reason – the common reason of all citizens. This work attempts to explained and interrogate John Rawls idea of “Overlapping Consensus and Public Reason”. This paper submits that Rawls Political Liberalism is a rich and suggestive account of how to justify a scheme of principles for ordering the basic structure of society. This work further argues that Rawls’s theory leaves us with same pressing problems. One of the problems that Rawls must answer is that of providing a critic and justification. By calling justice as fairness a political conception Rawls has abandoned the attempt to provide such a critical justification. But in doing so, one has to wonder what reasons one would have to ultimately accept the political conception, other than merely pragmatic ones.
    [Show full text]
  • Does Social Justice Ground Democracy in Education Or Does Democracy Ground Social Justice?
    DOES SOCIAL JUSTICE GROUND DEMOCRACY IN EDUCATION OR DOES DEMOCRACY GROUND SOCIAL JUSTICE? Sheron Fraser-Burgess Ball State University In recent theorizations of education’s emerging political economies theorists aim to make sense of the relation between persistent social and economic inequalities in schooling experiences and stringent accountability regimes.1 Salient to these movements are a set of looming demographic transitions. These include the forecasted emergence of a majority-minority society and the cultural flux of primary social institutions such as families, education, and long-standing pillars of religious beliefs and norms. Particularly arresting to philosophers of education is that, as unintended consequences, such developments have the potential further to vacate the promise of public schools as vehicles of equity. How, in the face of revolutionary change, can American education advance a democratic society that treats all equitably? The notion of social justice is one moral lens through which philosophers of education continue to interpret and evaluate the interplay between contemporary sociopolitical conditions in education (e.g., schools, accountability, and public sentiment) and democratic norms. The term social justice has been bandied about in the field of education for much of the last two decades as a particular understanding of the moral framework by which we evaluate social institutions.2 Despite its broad usage, the term remains somewhat unspecified in educational discourse. As Kent den Heyer claims, social justice is considered by some to be an empty signifier because of its multifarious interpretations.3 1 Jean Anyon, Ghetto Schooling: A Political Economy of Urban Educational Reform (New York: Teachers College Press, 1997); Pauline Lipman, The New Political Economy of Urban Education (New York: Routledge, 2011); Lisa Delpit, Multiplication Is for White People (New York: New Press, 2012).
    [Show full text]
  • The Fragility of Consensus: Public Reason, Diversity and Stability
    bs_bs_banner DOI: 10.1111/ejop.12020 The Fragility of Consensus: Public Reason, Diversity and Stability John Thrasher and Kevin Vallier Abstract: John Rawls’s transition from A Theory of Justice to Political Liberalism was driven by his rejection of Theory’s account of stability. The key to his later account of stability is the idea of public reason. We see Rawls’s account of stability as an attempt to solve a mutual assurance problem. We maintain that Rawls’s solution fails because his primary assurance mechanism, in the form of public reason, is fragile. His conception of public reason relies on a condition of consensus that we argue is unrealistic in modern, pluralistic democracies. After rejecting Rawls’s conception of public reason, we offer an ‘indirect alter- native’ that we believe is much more robust. We cite experimental evidence to back up this claim. 1. Introduction John Rawls’s early conception of stability required a substantive ‘congruence’ between the right and the good (Rawls 1999: 496–505).1 He later rejected this view, however, believing it was untenable in light of the fact of reasonable pluralism. Pervasive disagreement among reasonable members of a well-ordered society will inevitably lead to a breakdown in congruence, destabilizing insti- tutions based on Justice as Fairness.2 In Political Liberalism, Rawls attempted to avoid this problem by developing a conception of stability ‘for the right reasons’ that obtains so long as citizens come to affirm a political conception of justice consistent with their distinct reasonable comprehensive doctrines.3 Public reason, on this account, is the critical mechanism that generates stability.
    [Show full text]