Recognizing Justice for Citizens with Cognitive Disabilities

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Recognizing Justice for Citizens with Cognitive Disabilities RECOGNIZING JUSTICE FOR CITIZENS WITH COGNITIVE DISABILITIES by KACEY BROOKE WARREN B.A. California State University Sacramento, 2005 M.A. University of Colorado at Boulder, 2008 A thesis submitted to the Faculty of the Graduate School in partial fulfillment of the requirement for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy 2012 This dissertation entitled: Recognizing Justice For Citizens With Cognitive Disabilities written by Kacey Brooke Warren has been approved for the Department of Philosophy ____________________________ Dr. Alison Jaggar (Chair) ____________________________ Dr. Eva Kittay ____________________________ Dr. Celeste Montoya-Kirk ____________________________ Dr. Alastair Norcross ____________________________ Dr. Michael Zimmerman Date___________ The final copy of this thesis has been examined by the signatories, and we find that both the content and the form meet acceptable presentation standards Of scholarly work in the above mentioned discipline. iii Warren, Kacey Brooke (Ph.D., Philosophy, Department of Philosophy) “Recognizing Justice For Citizens With Cognitive Disabilities” A dissertation directed by College Professor of Distinction Alison Jaggar Citizens with cognitive disabilities represent a growing constituency in Western liberal democratic societies and, indeed, within the globe. There are currently millions of citizens with cognitive disabilities living in the United States alone. Most people will experience cognitive disability as some point in their lives, or at least will know and likely care for someone who does. The question of what justice requires for citizens with cognitive disabilities is citizens therefore a topic that any normatively adequate theory of justice must neither to overlook, nor ignore. Central to any liberal theory of justice are the values of political equality and liberty and with these the need to provide justification for all those who are subject to the coercive legal and social institutions that the theory specifies. Although undeniably subject to any political regime and, indeed, to any liberal theory of justice intended to govern one, citizens with cognitive disabilities have frequently and without justification been denied equal justice. This, I suggest, marks a lurking bias in the structure of these theories of justice—the extent of which becomes evident only in light of the plausibility that alternative theories of justice can meet a standard of political equality and liberty for citizens with cognitive disabilities. In light of this I assess four of the most influential contemporary theories of justice: John Rawls’s justice as fairness; Martha Nussbaum’s capabilities approach; Eva Kittay’s connection- iv based approach and Axel Honneth’s theory of differentiated recognition according to these two standards. My analysis clarifies how in the first three, certain of the theorist’s methodological commitments precludes the theory of justice he or she advances from meeting either one or the other or both standards. I conclude that of the four, Axel Honneth’s theory of differentiated recognition is the most promising. I then propose an approach to justification in terms of contextual transparency that complements Honneth’s theory and has potential for upholding a standard of political equality and the liberal standard of justification. v Acknowledgments It is a pleasure for me to thank David Boonin, Amandine Catala, Alison, Jaggar, Audra King, Eva Kittay, Claudia Mills, Celeste Montoya-Kirk, Marlisa Moschella, Alastair Norcross, Giovana Nurena, Edwin Rhine, Kevin and Rhiannon Thompson, Michael Zimmerman, and my parents Gary and Linda Warren, all of whom have made this dissertation possible. I owe my most profound gratitude to Alison Jaggar for her exceptional assistance and dedication as director of my dissertation. I feel extremely fortunate to work under Alison who has served as an inspirational figure in my life, even prior to attending graduate school. It was because of her work, namely in Feminist Politics and Human Nature, that I chose to attend graduate school and that CU Boulder was my top choice. Many years later, it is because of her continued work, most certainly as distinguished professor at CU Boulder and an unparalleled author in feminist philosophy in the United States as well as abroad, but also as an advisor and role-model for female graduate students like myself, that I now have the confidence, knowledge, and privilege to issue forth my own work. I am deeply indebted to Alison for the countless drafts she has read, the precision with which she has criticized them, and the guidance she has offered for restructuring and clarifying the ideas presented in them. I do hope that this dissertation is something that not only I but she too can be proud of. I am also honored to have Alastair Norcross, Michael Zimmerman, Celeste Montoya-Kirk and Eva Kittay as members of my doctoral dissertation committee. It is a special honor for me to work with Eva Kittay who is widely recognized as one of the most distinguished philosophers working on moral issues, including of justice, for citizens with cognitive disabilities in the vi United States. She has extended herself far beyond any commitments she may have at SUNY Stonybrook and graciously offered her assistance as a member of my committee and for this I am both privileged and grateful. I am also grateful for the efforts of Alastair Norcross who has participated not only on this committee but also on my prospectus committee alongside David Boonin and Claudia Mills, whose assistance I appreciate very much too. Finally, I would like to thank Christine Hollister, Giovana Nurena, and Edwin Rhine for their copy-editing assistance, Amandine Catala, Audra King, and Marlisa Moschella for the numerous discussions where I clarified my ideas and for offering substantive commentary on early drafts of the dissertation, and those precious friends and family members (in particular, my parents, Marlisa Moschella, Giovana Nurena, Edwin Rhine, and Kevin and Rhiannon Thompson) who provided me with much needed and appreciated moral support during those times where I questioned my ability to continue. I am deeply thankful for Marlisa’s unwavering confidence and friendship, as well as for our numerous philosophy talks over coffee or over the phone, which so often gave me the nudge I needed to get the ideas out of my head and onto paper. vii Table of Contents 1. What Does Justice Require For Citizens With Cognitive Disabilities? The Need For Moral Analysis 1.1 Disability and Political Philosophy......................................................................................1 1.2 The Challenge Cognitive Disability Poses to Liberalism....................................................5 1.3 Two Necessary Standards of Adequacy For a Liberal Theory of Justice..........................10 1.4 Toward a Liberal Theory of Justice For Citizens With Cognitive Disabilities ........................................................................................................................15 2. Political Equality For Citizens With Cognitive Disabilities 2.1 Liberalism and Presumptive Political Equality..................................................................17 2.2 What is “Disability”: The Social Model of Disability and The American’s With Disabilities Act.......................................................................................18 2.3 Cognitive Disability and Political Equality: Three Important Considerations .................23 2.4 Meeting the Standard of Presumptive Political Equality: Equal Basic Rights and Equal Moral Consideration..........................................................................................................33 3. Liberty and the Liberal Standard of Justification: 3.1 The Liberal Standard of Justification: An Interpretation of Equal Liberty.......................37 3.2. Original Position Reasoning..............................................................................................37 3.3 Wide Reflective Equilibrium.............................................................................................42 3.4 Overlapping Consensus.....................................................................................................46 viii 3.5 Operationalizing the Liberal Standard of Justification For Citizens With Cognitive Disabilities.........................................................................................................................51 4. Can Justice As Fairness Uphold the Values of Political Equality and Liberty For Citizens With Cognitive Disabilities? 4.1 Justice as Fairness and the Exclusion of Citizens with Cognitive Disabilities..................53 4.2 An Overview of Justice as Fairness...................................................................................55 4.3 Can Justice as Fairness Plausibly Address Concerns for the Equal Treatment of Citizens with Cognitive Disabilities Who Have Medical Impairment?...........................................64 4.4 Can Justice as Fairness Plausibly Address Concerns for the Equal Treatment of Citizens with Cognitive Disabilities Who Are Socially and Politically Excluded?........................67 4.5 Can Justice as Fairness Plausibly Address Concerns for the Equal Treatment of Citizens With Cognitive Disabilities Who are Stigmatized?.............................................70 4.6 Is Justice as Fairness Justifiable to Citizens With Cognitive Disabilities via Wide-Reflective Equilibrium?...........................................................................................74
Recommended publications
  • Feminist Perspectives on Dependency Eva Feder Kittay and Ellen K. Feder (Eds.) Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, Lanham, 2002, 336Pp
    Contemporary Political Theory, 2004, 3, (358–360) r 2004 Palgrave Macmillan Ltd 1470-8914/04 $30.00 www.palgrave-journals.com/cpt The Subject of Care: Feminist Perspectives on Dependency Eva Feder Kittay and Ellen K. Feder (eds.) Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, Lanham, 2002, 336pp. ISBN:0742513637. Contemporary Political Theory (2004) 3, 358–360. doi:10.1057/palgrave.cpt.9300147 Before freedom, there is dependency. With dependency comes the need for care. But who exactly does the bulk of life’s caretaking? Why has caretaking work frequently gone unacknowledged as real ‘labor’ (and how have gender, race and class affected its treatment)? Can contemporary political theory effectively displace the ideologically-driven fiction of the citizen as a self- sufficient, independent individual and develop more secure principles and rights to protect dependents and their caretakers? The 16 contributors to this volume raise such questions and insist upon collective attentiveness to the impoverishment and exploitation that often marks the lives of caretakers and their ‘charges’. While tackling many issues from a distinctly feminist perspective, these contributors also provide reflections and proposals that are essential readingfor any political theorist, philosopher or activist currently committed to a substantive vision of freedom and a progressive approach to social justice. Part I provides conceptual analysis and historical insights into the meaning of dependency. Nancy Fraser and Linda Gordon’s notable genealogy explores ‘registers’ of dependency (related to economic, sociological, political and moral-psychological conditions (p. 16)) and how normative claims about those who appear dependent have shifted over time, especially in relation to the dominant discourse of liberal capitalism.
    [Show full text]
  • Cognitive Disability, Capabilities, and Justice Serene Khader Stony Brook University
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by CommonKnowledge Essays in Philosophy Volume 9 Article 11 Issue 1 Philosophy of Disability 1-2008 Cognitive Disability, Capabilities, and Justice Serene Khader Stony Brook University Follow this and additional works at: http://commons.pacificu.edu/eip Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Khader, Serene (2008) "Cognitive Disability, Capabilities, and Justice," Essays in Philosophy: Vol. 9: Iss. 1, Article 11. Essays in Philosophy is a biannual journal published by Pacific nivU ersity Library | ISSN 1526-0569 | http://commons.pacificu.edu/eip/ Essays in Philosophy Essays in Philosophy A Biannual Journal Vol. 9, No. 1, January 2008 Cognitive Disability, Capabilities, and Justice Abstract: I argue that capabilities approaches are useful in formulating a political theory that takes seriously the needs of persons with severe cognitive disabilities (PSCD). I establish three adequacy criteria for theories of justice that take seriously the needs of PSCD: A) understanding PSCD as oppressed, B) positing a single standard of what is owed to PSCD abled individuals, and C) concern with flourishing as well as political liberty. I claim that conceiving valued capabilities as the end of social distribution may help a political theory to meet these criteria. I posit three further adequacy criteria: D) refusing to see PSCD as less than human, E) valuing moral powers other than practical reason, and F) securing space for care and dependency relationships. I show that how well Elizabeth Anderson and Martha Nussbaum’s capabilities approaches meet these criteria depends on their divergent conceptions of what capabilities are for.
    [Show full text]
  • More Than a Municipal Campaign: Speech in Haverhill, Massachusetts (November 27, 1899)
    More Than a Municipal Campaign: Speech in Haverhill, Massachusetts (November 27, 1899) Ladies and Gentlemen, Citizens of Haverhill:— A year ago the name of Haverhill was flashed around the world. On Wednesday next [Dec. 6, 1899] the magnificent victory achieved then will have ben ratified by an increased majority. This is something more than a municipal campaign. There are issues involved that are of vital and commanding interest to every man, woman, and child in Haverhill, in Massachusetts, throughout the length and breadth of the land. The competitive system, with its extreme wealth upon the one hand, its abject and widespread poverty upon the other, its political corruption, its economic servitude, its social demoralization is on trial. What pen or tongue, from primeval man to the dullest intellect, can describe the effect of this struggle upon the great mass of the working people? Multiplied millions of them answer to the description of the embruted peasant in the poem of Edwin Markham, a poem fraught with such significance that it blazed the immortality of the author on wings of lightning around the world: Bowed by the weight of centuries he leans Upon his hoe and gazes on the ground, The emptiness of ages in his face, And on his back the burden of the world. Who made him dead to rapture and despair, A thing that grieves not and that never hopes. Stolid and stunned, a brother to the ox? Who loosened and let down this brutal jaw? Whose was the hand that slanted back this brow? Whose breath blew out the light within this brain? 1 The capitalist system must answer for this appalling indictment at the bar of humanity.
    [Show full text]
  • Autonomy, Relationality, and Feminist Ethics
    Autonomy, Relationality, and Feminist Ethics JEAN KELLER While care ethics has frequently been criticized for lacking an account ofauton- omy, this paper argues that care ethics’ relational model of moral agency provides the basis for criticizing the philosophical tradttion’s model of autonomy and for rethinking autonomy in relational terms. Using Diana Meyers’s account of autonomy compe- tency as a basis, a dialogical model of autonomy is developed that can respond to internal and external critiques of care ethics. Care ethics has frequently been criticized for failing to address how women’s practice of care places women’s autonomy in jeopardy. The question of the implications of care ethics for our conception of autonomy, however, has been asked less frequently.’ This is the question that concerns me here. After first examining the general terrain of the “autonomy-care ethics debate,” focusing on the difficulties that autonomy and care ethics pose for one another,’ I turn to my central concern: laying the groundwork for a relational model of autonomy. Although it is still unclear whether care ethics will survive as the feminist ethic of the future, it would appear that whatever shape feminist ethics ends up taking, it will incorporate a relational model of moral agency. That is, the insight that the moral agent is an “encumbered self,” who is always already embedded in relations with flesh-and-blood others and is partly constituted by these relations, is here to stay. Thus, although my analysis addresses care ethics in particular, to the extent that other feminist approaches to ethics also rely on a relational model of moral agency, the issues raised here will, I hope, be relevant to feminist ethics more generall~.~ Hyptia vol.
    [Show full text]
  • How Campaign Songs Sold the Image of Presidential Candidates
    University of Central Florida STARS Honors Undergraduate Theses UCF Theses and Dissertations 2019 Music and the Presidency: How Campaign Songs Sold the Image of Presidential Candidates Gary M. Bogers University of Central Florida Part of the Music Commons, and the United States History Commons Find similar works at: https://stars.library.ucf.edu/honorstheses University of Central Florida Libraries http://library.ucf.edu This Open Access is brought to you for free and open access by the UCF Theses and Dissertations at STARS. It has been accepted for inclusion in Honors Undergraduate Theses by an authorized administrator of STARS. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Recommended Citation Bogers, Gary M., "Music and the Presidency: How Campaign Songs Sold the Image of Presidential Candidates" (2019). Honors Undergraduate Theses. 511. https://stars.library.ucf.edu/honorstheses/511 MUSIC AND THE PRESIDENCY: HOW CAMPAIGN SONGS SOLD THE IMAGE OF PRESIDENTIAL CANDIDATES by GARY MICHAEL BOGERS JR. A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Honors in the Major Program in Music Performance in the College of Arts and Humanities and in The Burnett Honors College at the University of Central Florida Orlando, Florida Spring Term, 2019 Thesis Chair: Dr. Scott Warfield Co-chairs: Dr. Alexander Burtzos & Dr. Joe Gennaro ©2019 Gary Michael Bogers Jr. ii ABSTRACT In this thesis, I will discuss the importance of campaign songs and how they were used throughout three distinctly different U.S. presidential elections: the 1960 campaign of Senator John Fitzgerald Kennedy against Vice President Richard Milhouse Nixon, the 1984 reelection campaign of President Ronald Wilson Reagan against Vice President Walter Frederick Mondale, and the 2008 campaign of Senator Barack Hussein Obama against Senator John Sidney McCain.
    [Show full text]
  • The Fragility of Consensus: Public Reason, Diversity, and Stability
    The Fragility of Consensus: Public Reason, Diversity, and Stability (Forthcoming in The European Journal of Philosophy) John Thrasher and Kevin Vallier Abstract: John Rawls’s transition from A Theory of Justice to Political Liberalism was driven by his rejection of Theory’s account of stability. The key to his later account of stability is the idea of public reason. We see Rawls’s account of stability as an attempt to solve a mutual assurance problem. We maintain that Rawls’s solution fails because his primary assurance mechanism, in the form of public reason, is fragile. His conception of public reason relies on a condition of consensus that we argue is both unrealistic in modern, pluralistic democracies and fragile. Rejecting his conception of public reason as unable to maintain stability, we offer an “indirect alternative” that we believe is much more robust. We offer experimental evidence to back up this claim. John Rawls’s early conception of stability required a substantive ‘congruence’ between the right and the good (1999: 496-505).1 He later rejected this view, however, believing it was untenable in light of the fact of reasonable pluralism. Pervasive disagreement among reasonable members of a well-ordered society will inevitably lead to a breakdown in congruence; destabilizing institutions based on Justice as Fairness.2 In Political Liberalism, Rawls attempted to avoid this problem by developing a conception of stability ‘for the 1 (Rawls 1999) is hereafter TJ. Many readers may be unfamiliar with Rawlsian ‘congruence,’ but the concept is pivotal. See: (Weithman 2010), hereafter WPL? Throughout, we us PL to refer to (Rawls 2005).
    [Show full text]
  • Public Reason1
    charles larmore 10 Public Reason1 For John Rawls, public reason is not one political value among others. It envelops all the different elements that make up the ideal of a constitutional democracy, for it governs “the political relation” in which we ought to stand to one another as citizens (CP,p.574). Public reason involves more than just the idea that the principles of political association should be an object of public knowledge. Its concern is the very basis of our collectively binding decisions. We honor public reason when we bring our own reason into accord with the reason of others, espousing a common point of view for settling the terms of our political life. The conception of justice by which we live is then a conception we endorse, not for the different reasons we may each discover, and not simply for reasons we happen to share, but instead for reasons that count for us because we can affirm them together. This spirit of reciprocity is the foundation of a democratic society. Public reason has emerged as an explicit theme in Rawls’s writings only after A Theory of Justice with his turn to “political liberalism” and the pursuit of a common ground on which people can stand de- spite their deep ethical and religious differences. But the concept itself has always been at the heart of his philosophy. It runs through his first book in the guise of the idea of publicity, playing an in- dispensable part in the theory of justice as fairness. The notion of fairness itself, so central to Rawls’s thought, denotes that mutual acknowledgement of principles which public reason demands and which forms the real import of the language of social contract he has used to articulate his conception of justice.
    [Show full text]
  • Narrative Ethics and Vulnerability Kristeva and Ricoeur on Interdependence
    Narrative Ethics and Vulnerability Kristeva and Ricoeur on Interdependence Elizabeth Purcell Journal of French and Francophone Philosophy - Revue de la philosophie française et de langue française, Vol XXI, No 1 (2013) pp 43-59 Vol XXI, No 1 (2013) ISSN 1936-6280 (print) ISSN 2155-1162 (online) DOI 10.5195/jffp.2013.575 www.jffp.org This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 3.0 United States License. This journal is operated by the University Library System of the University of Pittsburgh as part of its D-Scribe Digital Publishing Program, and is co-sponsored by the UniversityJournal of Pittsburgh of French and Press Francophone Philosophy | Revue de la philosophie française et de langue française Vol XXI, No 1 (2013) | www.jffp.org | DOI 10.5195/jffp.2013.575 Narrative Ethics and Vulnerability Kristeva and Ricoeur on Interdependence Elizabeth Purcell Boston College Introduction The passage of the Americans with Disabilities Act in 1990 led to the need to define disability and to define the experiences of those with disabilities. Because people with disabilities have been considered to “deviate” from the able-bodied norm and have been systematically oppressed, there came a need to redefine disability in response to the cultural and medical narratives that historically associated disability with defectiveness, insufficiency, and imperfection.1 With the aid of medicine, the goal was to cure the disability and return the body to its original, healthy state. Thus, the body that “has the ‘right’ number of smoothly functional limbs and organs,” does not “drool, spasm, jerk, wheeze, wheel, limp, stutter, piss, or fart uncontrollably either in private or public realms.”2 The power to define and regulate impairment, disorder, malfunction, disfigurement, or dysfunction in either the body or the brain, lay in the hands of medical practitioners.
    [Show full text]
  • The Lukewarm Religions of Rawls' Overlapping Consensus
    Aporia vol. 24 no. 2—2014 The Lukewarm Religions of Rawls’ Overlapping Consensus ALEXANDER SCHAEFER With regard to abortion, I accept my church’s position that life begins at conception. That’s the church’s judgment. I accept it in my personal life. But I refuse to impose it on equally devout Christians and Muslims and Jews and—I just refuse to impose that on others, unlike my friend here, the congressman. I do not believe that we have a right to tell other people that women can’t control their body. It’s a decision between them and their doctor, in my view. —Vice President Joe Biden I. Introduction iden’s statement neatly exemplifies Rawls’ ideal separation of one’s Comprehensive Moral Doctrine (CMD) from the sphere of political Breason. Given what Rawls calls the “burdens of judgment,” it is un- reasonable for any citizen in a democratic society to expect all others to adopt his or her exact same doctrine (54).1 Therefore, it is also unreason- able to use the values and beliefs of one’s particular CMD to form laws that will apply equally to all citizens. Doing so would force those who reasonably disagree with one’s CMD to act in accord with it. If a legitimate and stable 1 Although a CMD can be any system of values that extends beyond the political (containing “nonpolitical values and virtues” (Rawls 175)) this paper will treat only religious CMDs. Whether parts of this critique can be extended to cover other types of CMDs is an open question.
    [Show full text]
  • Fairness, Consensus, and the Justification of the Ideal Liberal Constitution
    Fairness, Consensus, and the Justification of the Ideal Liberal Constitution Philip Cook LSE Law, Society and Economy Working Papers 4/2009 London School of Economics and Political Science Law Department This paper can be downloaded without charge from LSE Law, Society and Economy Working Papers at: www.lse.ac.uk/collections/law/wps/wps.htm and the Social Sciences Research Network electronic library at: http://ssrn.com/abstract=1331374. © Philip Cook. Users may download and/or print one copy to facilitate their private study or for non-commercial research. Users may not engage in further distribution of this material or use it for any profit-making activities or any other form of commercial gain. Electronic copy available at: http://ssrn.com/abstract=1331374 Philip Cook The Justification of the Ideal Liberal Constitution Fairness, Consensus, and the Justification of the Ideal Liberal Constitution Philip Cook * Abstract: In Constitutional Goods Brudner argues that the justification of the ideal liberal constitutional must be based on an alternative conception of public reason from that that presented by Rawls in Political Liberalism. This paper sets out the disagreement between the two notions of justification, and argues that Brudner’s proposed account is problematic on two accounts. Firstly, it seems internally inconsistent. Brudner’s alternative to Rawls’s overlapping consensus, a convergent consensus on an inclusive conception of liberalism, will be impossible given the plural and often contradictory nature of differing liberal doctrines. Secondly, even if such a consensus is possible it will be characterized by modus vivendi rather than a reasonable agreement based on the value of fairness.
    [Show full text]
  • Consensus on What? Convergence for What? Four Models of Political
    Consensus on What? Convergence for What? Four Models of Political Liberalism* Gerald Gaus and Chad Van Schoelandt 1 A PROJECT, NOT AN EDIFICE In an early symposium on A Theory of Justice, John Chapman remarked that “Rawls’s theory has both the simplicity and the complexity of a Gothic cathedral.”1 In his recent important book on Rawls’s political turn, Paul Weithman notes and endorses this characterization. Weithman seeks a unified interpretation of Theory, Rawls’s political turn and its search for stability, overcoming the many partial interpretations that take only “one view of the cathedral.”2 When readers turn to Political Liberalism, the style that comes to mind is not gothic, but baroque.3 If one takes even the 1993 hardback edition of Political Liberalism as a single, unified construction — much less the paperback edition, which includes the important “Reply to Habermas”— it has the tension, movement, complexity and irregularity of the baroque. Nevertheless, at least as far as we can see, the baroque interpretation too fails — after numerous readings, we are unable to construct a reasonably coherent and viable interpretation that accounts for all the *An earlier version of this essay was delivered to the 25th anniversary of conference of Rawls's Political Liberalism, hosted by the Jean Beer Blumenfeld Center for Ethics, Georgia State University, May, 2016. Our thanks for the comments and suggestions of all the participants; subsequent comments by Paul Weithman were especially vaulable, as were discussions with Brian Kogelmann. 1 John W. Chapman, “Rawls’s Theory of Justice,” American Political Science Review, vol.
    [Show full text]
  • Partisan Federal Election Commission (FEC)
    Analysis of H.R. 1 (Part Two) Establishing a Campaign Speech Czar and Enabling Partisan Enforcement: An Altered FEC Structure Poses Risks to First Amendment Speech Rights Bradley A. Smith, Chairman January 2019 Introduction While most of the attention on H.R. 1 has focused on “hot” issues, such as earmarking government subsidies for political campaigns, gerrymandering, and new restrictions on grassroots organizations that engage in public affairs,1 twenty pages of the bill are devoted to the unsexy, yet vitally important, issue of the Federal Election Commission’s (FEC) composition and operating procedures.2 If you’re a Democrat, do you think Donald Trump should be able to appoint a campaign speech czar to determine and en- force the rules on political campaigns? And if you’re a Republican, would you have wanted those rules enforced by a partisan selected by Barack Obama? Of course not. That’s why for over 40 years, Republicans and Democrats have agreed that campaign regulations should be enforced by an independent, bipartisan agency. The Watergate scandal that forced Richard Nixon to resign the presidency showed the dangers of allowing one party to use the power of government against the other.3 As the late Sen. Alan Cranston (D-Ca.) warned during debate on legislation creating the agency, “We must not allow the FEC to become a tool for harassment by future imperial Presidents who may seek to repeat the abuses of Watergate. I un- derstand and share the great concern expressed by some of our colleagues that the FEC has such a potential for abuse in our democratic society that the President should not be given power over the Commission.”4 That concern led to Congressional adoption of the present method of selecting Commission members.
    [Show full text]