The Language of Causation

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Language of Causation The language of causation Ari Beller*, Erin Bennett* & Tobias Gerstenberg fabeller, erindb, [email protected] Department of Psychology, Stanford University 450 Jane Stanford Way, Stanford, CA, USA, 94305 * equal contribution Abstract these accounts so far have in common is that they construe causal relationships in terms of some notion of probabilistic, People use varied language to express their causal understand- ing of the world. But how does that language map onto peo- counterfactual, or logical dependence. ple’s underlying representations, and how do people choose Wolff (2007) developed a different framework for think- between competing ways to best describe what happened? In this paper we develop a model that integrates computational ing about causal expressions such as “cause”, “enable”, “de- tools for causal judgment and pragmatic inference to address spite”, and “prevent” that is based on Talmy’s (1988) theory these questions. The model has three components: a causal of force dynamics (see also Wolff, Barbey, & Hausknecht, inference component which computes counterfactual simula- tions that capture whether and how a candidate cause made 2010). According to the force dynamics model, causal ex- a difference to the outcome, a literal semantics that maps pressions map onto configurations of force vectors (Figure 1). the outcome of these counterfactual simulations onto different For example, the causal construction “A caused P to reach E” causal expressions (such as “caused”, “enabled”, “affected”, or “made no difference”), and a pragmatics component that maps onto a configuration in which P’s initial force didn’t considers how informative each causal expression would be point toward the endstate E, and A’s force combined with for figuring out what happened. We test our model in an ex- P’s such that the resulting force R led P to reach the end- periment that asks participants to select which expression best describes what happened in video clips depicting physical in- state. In contrast, the construction “A enabled P to reach E” teractions. implies that P’s force vector already pointed toward the end- Keywords: causality; language; counterfactuals; pragmatics; state, and A’s force combined with P’s such that it reached the intuitive physics. endstate. The force dynamics model accurately predicts par- ticipants’ modal selection of which expression best captures Introduction what happened in a variety of different video clips (Wolff, The words we use to describe what happened matter. Hearing 2007). However, the force dynamics model also has some that “Tom killed Bill” elicits a different mental model of what limitations. For example, it doesn’t yield quantitative pre- happened than hearing that “Tom caused Bill to die” does dictions about how well a particular expression captures what (Freitas, DeScioli, Nemirow, Massenkoff, & Pinker, 2017; happened, but instead relies on a qualitative mapping between Niemi, Hartshorne, Gerstenberg, Stanley, & Young, 2020; situations and causal expressions. Rather than a distribution Thomson, 1976). The question of how we express our knowl- over response options, it predicts a single response. Also, edge of what happened in words, and how we infer what hap- as we will see below, when people are provided with other pened based on the words we hear, has a long and deep tradi- alternative expressions (such as “affected”, or “made no dif- tion in philosophy, linguistics, and cognitive science (Pinker, ference”) they don’t choose “enabled” for the predicted force 2007). configuration. In cognitive science, most work on causal cognition has fo- In this paper, we propose a new model of the meaning and cused on building models that capture the notions of “cause” use of causal expressions. Our model builds on the counter- and “prevent” (Waldmann, 2017). However, some attempts factual simulation model (CSM) of causal judgment devel- have also been made to uncover the differences between oped by Gerstenberg, Goodman, Lagnado, and Tenenbaum causal verbs such as “cause” and “enable”. For example, (2015, 2020). Gerstenberg et al. tested their model on dy- Cheng and Novick (1991) argue that these verbs map onto namic physical interactions similar to the diagrams shown at different patterns of co-variation. Sloman, Barbey, and Ho- the top of Figure 2. In their experiment, participants judged taling (2009), in contrast, propose that their meanings are CAUSE ENABLE PREVENT DESPITE best understood as mapping onto qualitatively different causal A models. Whereas “A causes B” means that there is a causal R E P A R E P E A R P E link from A to B, “A enables B” means that A is necessary for B to happen, and that there exists an alternative cause to P R A B. Goldvarg and Johnson-Laird (2001) develop an account based on mental model theory in which “cause” and “al- Figure 1: Analysis of different causal expressions in terms of low” map onto different possible cause-effect pairs (see also configurations of forces. P = patient force, A = agent force, Khemlani, Wasylyshyn, Briggs, & Bello, 2018). What all R = resulting force, E = endstate. 3134 ©2020 The Author(s). This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License (CC BY). to what extent balls A and B were responsible for ball E’s Table 1: Model derivation for clips 1–4 shown in Figure 2. going through (or missing) the gate. The CSM predicts that a) Aspect Values people’s causal judgments are sensitive to different aspects of Clip 1 2 3 4 causation that capture the extent to which the cause made a Whether 1.00 1.00 0.00 0.00 difference to how and whether the outcome happened. These How 1.00 0.00 1.00 0.00 aspects of causation are defined in terms of counterfactual Sufficient 1.00 1.00 0.00 0.00 contrasts operating over an intuitive understanding of the b) Semantic Values physical domain. People use their intuitive understanding of Clip 1 2 3 4 physics to mentally simulate how things could have turned out differently (cf. Gerstenberg & Tenenbaum, 2017; Ull- No Difference 0.00 0.00 0.80 1.00 Affected 1.00 0.00 1.00 0.00 man, Spelke, Battaglia, & Tenenbaum, 2017), and the result Enabled 1.00 1.00 0.00 0.00 of these counterfactual simulations informs their causal judg- Caused 1.00 0.00 0.00 0.00 ments (Gerstenberg, Peterson, Goodman, Lagnado, & Tenen- baum, 2017). c) Literal Listener Distributions The model we develop here predicts people’s use of Clip 1 2 3 4 the causal expressions “caused”, “enabled”, “affected”, and No Difference 0.00 0.00 0.44 0.56 Affected 0.50 0.00 0.50 0.00 “made no difference”. The model has three components: a Enabled 0.50 0.50 0.00 0.00 causal inference component that computes the different as- Caused 1.00 0.00 0.00 0.00 pects of causation according to the CSM, a semantics compo- nent that defines a logical mapping from aspects of causation d) Speaker Distributions to causal expressions, and a pragmatics component that takes Clip 1 2 3 4 into account how informative each expression would be about No Difference 0.00 0.00 0.47 1.00 what happened (Goodman & Frank, 2016). Affected 0.25 0.00 0.53 0.00 Enabled 0.25 1.00 0.00 0.00 The paper is organized as follows. We first describe our Caused 0.50 0.00 0.00 0.00 model and its three components by illustrating how it applies to some example cases. We then present an experiment that ball B would have gone through the gate if ball A had been re- tests the model, as well as alternative models, on a challeng- moved. The model captures this uncertainty by running noisy ing set of video clips. We conclude by discussing the model’s counterfactual simulations. In simulating the counterfactual, limitations that suggest important avenues for future research. B’s movements are perturbed from the point at which the col- Model lision with ball A would have happened onward. By record- ing the proportion of cases in which the outcome would have We discuss the three components of our model in turn: causal been different from what actually happened in these noisy inference, model semantics, and pragmatics. samples, the model computes the probability that A was a Causal inference whether-cause of e. Whether-causation captures the extent to which the presence of the candidate cause was necessary The causal inference component of our model builds on for the outcome to come about. the CSM (Gerstenberg et al., 2015, 2020), which postulates how-causation For how-causation H , the model computes that causal judgments are sensitive to different aspects of 0 causation including how-causation, whether-causation, and whether the fine-grained counterfactual outcome De in sce- sufficient-causation. We briefly describe each aspect here us- nario S would have been different from what actually hap- ing clips participants viewed in our experiment (see Figure 2). pened De, if the candidate cause A had been changed. Table 1a shows the aspect values for clips 1–4. H (A ! De) = P(De0 6= DejS;change(A)) whether-causation To test for whether-causation W , the model computes the probability that the counterfactual out- This test captures whether A made a difference to how the come e0 in scenario S would have been different from what outcome came about (cf. Lewis, 2000; Woodward, 2011). actually happened e, if the candidate cause A had been re- The outcome event De is construed at a finer level of gran- moved. ularity, with information about the time and space at which the event happened. The change() operation is implemented W (A ! e) = P(e0 6= ejS;remove(A)) as a small perturbation to ball A’s initial position.
Recommended publications
  • Causality and Determinism: Tension, Or Outright Conflict?
    1 Causality and Determinism: Tension, or Outright Conflict? Carl Hoefer ICREA and Universidad Autònoma de Barcelona Draft October 2004 Abstract: In the philosophical tradition, the notions of determinism and causality are strongly linked: it is assumed that in a world of deterministic laws, causality may be said to reign supreme; and in any world where the causality is strong enough, determinism must hold. I will show that these alleged linkages are based on mistakes, and in fact get things almost completely wrong. In a deterministic world that is anything like ours, there is no room for genuine causation. Though there may be stable enough macro-level regularities to serve the purposes of human agents, the sense of “causality” that can be maintained is one that will at best satisfy Humeans and pragmatists, not causal fundamentalists. Introduction. There has been a strong tendency in the philosophical literature to conflate determinism and causality, or at the very least, to see the former as a particularly strong form of the latter. The tendency persists even today. When the editors of the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy asked me to write the entry on determinism, I found that the title was to be “Causal determinism”.1 I therefore felt obliged to point out in the opening paragraph that determinism actually has little or nothing to do with causation; for the philosophical tradition has it all wrong. What I hope to show in this paper is that, in fact, in a complex world such as the one we inhabit, determinism and genuine causality are probably incompatible with each other.
    [Show full text]
  • Studies on Causal Explanation in Naturalistic Philosophy of Mind
    tn tn+1 s s* r1 r2 r1* r2* Interactions and Exclusions: Studies on Causal Explanation in Naturalistic Philosophy of Mind Tuomas K. Pernu Department of Biosciences Faculty of Biological and Environmental Sciences & Department of Philosophy, History, Culture and Art Studies Faculty of Arts ACADEMIC DISSERTATION To be publicly discussed, by due permission of the Faculty of Arts at the University of Helsinki, in lecture room 5 of the University of Helsinki Main Building, on the 30th of November, 2013, at 12 o’clock noon. © 2013 Tuomas Pernu (cover figure and introductory essay) © 2008 Springer Science+Business Media (article I) © 2011 Walter de Gruyter (article II) © 2013 Springer Science+Business Media (article III) © 2013 Taylor & Francis (article IV) © 2013 Open Society Foundation (article V) Layout and technical assistance by Aleksi Salokannel | SI SIN Cover layout by Anita Tienhaara Author’s address: Department of Biosciences Division of Physiology and Neuroscience P.O. Box 65 FI-00014 UNIVERSITY OF HELSINKI e-mail [email protected] ISBN 978-952-10-9439-2 (paperback) ISBN 978-952-10-9440-8 (PDF) ISSN 1799-7372 Nord Print Helsinki 2013 If it isn’t literally true that my wanting is causally responsible for my reaching, and my itching is causally responsible for my scratching, and my believing is causally responsible for my saying … , if none of that is literally true, then practically everything I believe about anything is false and it’s the end of the world. Jerry Fodor “Making mind matter more” (1989) Supervised by Docent Markus
    [Show full text]
  • Causation As Folk Science
    1. Introduction Each of the individual sciences seeks to comprehend the processes of the natural world in some narrow do- main—chemistry, the chemical processes; biology, living processes; and so on. It is widely held, however, that all the sciences are unified at a deeper level in that natural processes are governed, at least in significant measure, by cause and effect. Their presence is routinely asserted in a law of causa- tion or principle of causality—roughly, that every effect is produced through lawful necessity by a cause—and our ac- counts of the natural world are expected to conform to it.1 My purpose in this paper is to take issue with this view of causation as the underlying principle of all natural processes. Causation I have a negative and a positive thesis. In the negative thesis I urge that the concepts of cause as Folk Science and effect are not the fundamental concepts of our science and that science is not governed by a law or principle of cau- sality. This is not to say that causal talk is meaningless or useless—far from it. Such talk remains a most helpful way of conceiving the world, and I will shortly try to explain how John D. Norton that is possible. What I do deny is that the task of science is to find the particular expressions of some fundamental causal principle in the domain of each of the sciences. My argument will be that centuries of failed attempts to formu- late a principle of causality, robustly true under the introduc- 1Some versions are: Kant (1933, p.218) "All alterations take place in con- formity with the law of the connection of cause and effect"; "Everything that happens, that is, begins to be, presupposes something upon which it follows ac- cording to a rule." Mill (1872, Bk.
    [Show full text]
  • Moritz Schlick and Bas Van Fraassen: Two Different Perspectives on Causality and Quantum Mechanics Richard Dawid1
    Moritz Schlick and Bas van Fraassen: Two Different Perspectives on Causality and Quantum Mechanics Richard Dawid1 Moritz Schlick’s interpretation of the causality principle is based on Schlick’s understanding of quantum mechanics and on his conviction that quantum mechanics strongly supports an empiricist reading of causation in his sense. The present paper compares the empiricist position held by Schlick with Bas van Fraassen’s more recent conception of constructive empiricism. It is pointed out that the development from Schlick’s understanding of logical empiricism to constructive empiricism reflects a difference between the understanding of quantum mechanics endorsed by Schlick and the understanding that had been established at the time of van Fraassen’s writing. 1: Introduction Moritz Schlick’s ideas about causality and quantum mechanics dealt with a topic that was at the forefront of research in physics and philosophy of science at the time. In the present article, I want to discuss the plausibility of Schlick’s ideas within the scientific context of the time and compare it with a view based on a modern understanding of quantum mechanics. Schlick had already written about his understanding of causation in [Schlick 1920] before he set out to develop a new account of causation in “Die Kausalität in der gegenwärtigen Physik” [Schlick 1931]. The very substantial differences between the concepts of causality developed in the two papers are due to important philosophical as well as physical developments. Philosophically, [Schlick 1931] accounts for Schlick’s shift from his earlier position of critical realism towards his endorsement of core tenets of logical empiricism.
    [Show full text]
  • Naturalism, Causality, and Nietzsche's Conception of Science Justin Remhof Old Dominion University, [email protected]
    Old Dominion University ODU Digital Commons Philosophy Faculty Publications Philosophy & Religious Studies 2015 Naturalism, Causality, and Nietzsche's Conception of Science Justin Remhof Old Dominion University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.odu.edu/philosophy_fac_pubs Part of the Continental Philosophy Commons, Metaphysics Commons, and the Philosophy of Science Commons Repository Citation Remhof, Justin, "Naturalism, Causality, and Nietzsche's Conception of Science" (2015). Philosophy Faculty Publications. 48. https://digitalcommons.odu.edu/philosophy_fac_pubs/48 Original Publication Citation Remhof, J. (2015). Naturalism, causality, and Nietzsche's conception of science. The Journal of Nietzsche Studies, 46(1), 110-119. This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Philosophy & Religious Studies at ODU Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Faculty Publications by an authorized administrator of ODU Digital Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Naturalism, Causality, and Nietzsche’s Conception of Science JUSTIN REMHOF ABSTRACT: There is a disagreement over how to understand Nietzsche’s view of science. According to what I call the Negative View, Nietzsche thinks science should be reconceived or superseded by another discourse, such as art, because it is nihilistic. By contrast, what I call the Positive View holds that Nietzsche does not think science is nihilistic, so he denies that it should be reinterpreted or overcome. Interestingly, defenders of each position can appeal to Nietzsche’s understanding of naturalism to support their interpretation. I argue that Nietzsche embraces a social constructivist conception of causality that renders his natu- ralism incompatible with the views of naturalism attributed to him by the two dominant readings.
    [Show full text]
  • Causality, Free Will, and Divine Action Contents
    Organon F, Volume 26, 2019, Issue 1 Special Issue Causality, Free Will, and Divine Action Frederik Herzberg and Daniel von Wachter Guest Editors Contents Daniel von Wachter: Preface ......................................................................... 2 Research Articles Robert A. Larmer: The Many Inadequate Justifications of Methodological Naturalism .......................................................................................... 5 Richard Swinburne: The Implausibility of the Causal Closure of the Physical ............................................................................................. 25 Daniel von Wachter: The Principle of the Causal Openness of the Physical ............................................................................................. 40 Michael Esfeld: Why Determinism in Physics Has No Implications for Free Will ..................................................................................... 62 Ralf B. Bergmann: Does Divine Intervention Violate Laws of Nature? ....... 86 Uwe Meixner: Elements of a Theory of Nonphysical Agents in the Physical World ................................................................................ 104 Ansgar Beckermann: Active Doings and the Principle of the Causal Closure of the Physical World ......................................................... 122 Thomas Pink: Freedom, Power and Causation .......................................... 141 Discussion Notes Michael Esfeld: The Principle of Causal Completeness: Reply to Daniel von Wachter ...................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • A Brief Introduction to Temporality and Causality
    A Brief Introduction to Temporality and Causality Kamran Karimi D-Wave Systems Inc. Burnaby, BC, Canada [email protected] Abstract Causality is a non-obvious concept that is often considered to be related to temporality. In this paper we present a number of past and present approaches to the definition of temporality and causality from philosophical, physical, and computational points of view. We note that time is an important ingredient in many relationships and phenomena. The topic is then divided into the two main areas of temporal discovery, which is concerned with finding relations that are stretched over time, and causal discovery, where a claim is made as to the causal influence of certain events on others. We present a number of computational tools used for attempting to automatically discover temporal and causal relations in data. 1. Introduction Time and causality are sources of mystery and sometimes treated as philosophical curiosities. However, there is much benefit in being able to automatically extract temporal and causal relations in practical fields such as Artificial Intelligence or Data Mining. Doing so requires a rigorous treatment of temporality and causality. In this paper we present causality from very different view points and list a number of methods for automatic extraction of temporal and causal relations. The arrow of time is a unidirectional part of the space-time continuum, as verified subjectively by the observation that we can remember the past, but not the future. In this regard time is very different from the spatial dimensions, because one can obviously move back and forth spatially.
    [Show full text]
  • Causality Causality Refers to the Relationship
    Causality Causality refers to the relationship between events where one set of events (the effects) is a direct consequence of another set of events (the causes). Causal inference is the process by which one can use data to make claims about causal relationships. Since inferring causal relationships is one of the central tasks of science, it is a topic that has been heavily debated in philosophy, statistics, and the scientific disciplines. In this article, we review the models of causation and tools for causal inference most prominent in the social sciences, including regularity approaches, associated with David Hume, and counterfactual models, associated with Jerzy Neyman, Donald Rubin, and David Lewis, among many others. One of the most notable developments in the study of causation is the increasing unification of disparate methods around a common conceptual and mathematical language that treats causality in counterfactual terms---i.e., the Neyman- Rubin model. We discuss how counterfactual models highlight the deep challenges involved in making the move from correlation to causation, particularly in the social sciences where controlled experiments are relatively rare. Regularity Models of Causation Until the advent of counterfactual models, causation was primarily defined in terms of observable phenomena. It was philosopher David Hume in the eighteenth century who began the modern tradition of regularity models of causation by defining causation in terms of repeated “conjunctions” of events. In An Enquiry into Human Understanding (1751), Hume argued that the labeling of two particular events as being causally related rested on an untestable metaphysical assumption. Consequently, Hume argued that causality could only be adequately defined in terms of empirical regularities involving classes of events.
    [Show full text]
  • The Law of Causality and Its Limits Vienna Circle Collection
    THE LAW OF CAUSALITY AND ITS LIMITS VIENNA CIRCLE COLLECTION lIENK L. MULDER, University ofAmsterdam, Amsterdam, The Netherlands ROBERT S. COHEN, Boston University, Boston, Mass., U.SA. BRIAN MCGUINNESS, University of Siena, Siena, Italy RUDOLF IlALLER, Charles Francis University, Graz, Austria Editorial Advisory Board ALBERT E. BLUMBERG, Rutgers University, New Brunswick, N.J., U.SA. ERWIN N. HIEBERT, Harvard University, Cambridge, Mass., U.SA JAAKKO HiNTIKKA, Boston University, Boston, Mass., U.S.A. A. J. Kox, University ofAmsterdam, Amsterdam, The Netherlands GABRIEL NUCHELMANS, University ofLeyden, Leyden, The Netherlands ANTH:ONY M. QUINTON, All Souls College, Oxford, England J. F. STAAL, University of California, Berkeley, Calif., U.SA. FRIEDRICH STADLER, Institute for Science and Art, Vienna, Austria VOLUME 22 VOLUME EDITOR: ROBERT S. COHEN PHILIPP FRANK PHILIPP FRANK THELAWOF CAUSALITY AND ITS LIMITS Edited by ROBERT s. COHEN Boston University Translated by MARIE NEURATH and ROBERT S. COHEN 1Ii.. ... ,~ SPRINGER SCIENCE+BUSINESS MEDIA, B.V. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication data Frank, Philipp, 1884-1966. [Kausalgesetz und seine Grenzen. Englishl The law of causality and its limits / Philipp Frank; edited by Robert S. Cohen ; translation by Marie Neurath and Robert S. Cohen. p. cm. -- (Vienna Circle collection ; v. 22) Inc I udes index. ISBN 978-94-010-6323-4 ISBN 978-94-011-5516-8 (eBook) DOI 10.1007/978-94-011-5516-8 1. Causation. 2. Science--Phi losophy. I. Cohen, R. S. (Robert Sonne) 11. Title. 111. Series. BD543.F7313
    [Show full text]
  • Kant's Model of Causality: Causal Powers, Laws, and Kant's Reply to Hume
    KANT’ S MODEL OF CAUSALITY 449 Kant’s Model of Causality: Causal Powers, Laws, and Kant’s Reply to Hume ERIC WATKINS* KANT’S VIEWS ON CAUSALITY have received an extraordinary amount of scholarly at- tention, especially in comparison with Hume’s position. For Hume presents pow- erful skeptical arguments concerning causality, yet Kant claims to have an ad- equate response to them. Since it turns out to be far from obvious what even the main lines of Kant’s response are, scholars have felt the need to clarify his posi- tion. Unfortunately, however, no consensus has been reached about how best to understand Kant’s views. To gauge the current state of the debate, consider briefly Hume’s two-fold skeptical attack on causality in his Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding and what strategy Kant is often thought to be pursuing in response in the Critique of Pure Reason.1 1 Hume’s fuller views on causality are naturally more complex than the brief summary provided below indicates. For more comprehensive discussions, see, e.g., Barry Stroud, Hume (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1978), John Wright, The Sceptical Realism of David Hume (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1983), Richard Fogelin, Hume’s Skepticism in the Treatise of Human Nature (Boston: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1985), Galen Strawson, The Secret Connexion: Causation, Realism, and David Hume (New York: Oxford University Press, 1989), Ken Winkler, “The New Hume,” Philosophical Review 100 (1991): 541–79, and Don Garrett “The Representation of Causation and Hume’s Two Defini- tions of ‘Cause’,” Nous 27 (1993): 167–90.
    [Show full text]
  • ⋆ Evidence and Epistemic Causality ⋆
    ? Evidence and Epistemic Causality ? Michael Wilde & Jon Williamson Draft of January 13, 2015 The epistemic theory of causality maintains that causality is an epistemic relation, so that causality is taken to be a feature of the way a subject reasons about the world rather than a non-epistemological feature of the world. In this paper, we take the opportunity to briefly rehearse some arguments in favour of the epistemic theory of causality, and then present a version of the theory developed in Williamson(2005, 2006, 2009, 2011). Lastly, we provide some possible responses to an objection based upon recent work in epistemology. This paper provides a broad overview of the issues, and in a number of places readers are directed towards work which provides the relevant details. §1 Causality and evidence Standardly, there are mechanistic and difference-making theories of causality. On the one hand, mechanistic theories maintain that variables in a domain are causally re- lated if and only if they are connected by an appropriate sort of mechanism. On the other hand, difference-making theories maintain that variables are causally related if and only if one variable makes an appropriate sort of difference to the other. Stated in these terms, there might be a worry that both types of theory will be uninforma- tive or circular, since the appropriate sort of mechanism or the difference-making relationship might be less well understood than the causal relation, or only under- standable in terms of causality. Therefore, a good mechanistic theory should attempt to provide an account of the appropriate sort of mechanism in better-understood and non-causal terms, e.g., the mechanism might be understood in terms of a process that possesses a conserved quantity (Dowe, 2000).
    [Show full text]
  • Causality and Identification
    Mgmt 469 Causality and Identification As you have learned by now, a key issue in empirical research is identifying the direction of causality in the relationship between two variables. This problem often arises when it is unclear in a regression whether X causes Y or Y causes X. An example from my own research experience helps to clarify the problem and its solution. The Problem of Supplier Induced Demand Historically, MDs have controlled the medical process. Analysts have long noted that medical prices are higher in markets that have more MDs per capita. Some have hypothesized that when MDs who face competition “induce demand" so as to maintain their incomes. The theory of demand inducement is almost dogma among health policy analysts, especially in Canada and Europe. The supplier induced demand (SID) hypothesis may be stated as follows: The SID hypothesis: When the supply of physicians increases, the demand for their services increases. That is, increased supply causes increased demand. Early proponents of SID proposed testing it with the following model: Qd = g(Xd, P, Qs) + ε, where Qd = the quantity of physician services provided (e.g., number of surgeries), Xd = one or more demand shifters, P = price Qs = the number of physicians per capita, and ε = the error term. One might want to test this model by gathering the required data and running OLS. A positive, statistically significant coefficient on Qs might be considered evidence of SID. It turns out that this would be a very bad approach. The reason: doubts about causality 1 Consider the following, somewhat related example: There is a positive correlation between construction workers and the number of office buildings under construction.
    [Show full text]