Sui Generis-Ness, Parsimony and Innocence the (Meta)2Physics of Parthood

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Sui Generis-Ness, Parsimony and Innocence the (Meta)2Physics of Parthood Sui Generis-ness, Parsimony and Innocence The (Meta)2physics of Parthood Fabio Ceravolo Submitted in accordance with the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy The University of Leeds School of Philosophy, Religion and the History of Science July, 2018 i The candidate confirms that the work submitted is his own and that appropriate credit has been given where reference has been made to the work of others. This copy has been supplied on the understanding that it is copyright material and that no quotation from the thesis may be published without proper acknowledgement. The right of Fabio Ceravolo to be identified as Author of this work has been asserted by him in accordance with the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988. ©2018 The University of Leeds and Fabio Ceravolo ii Acknowledgements No matter how valuable, none of what follows would have been remotely conceivable without the enduring support of Steven French and J. Robert G. Williams, who found me an enthusiastic neophyte and turned me into a (more) careful arguer. As the outcome of innumerable and unquantifiably fruitful discussions, this dissertation owes to them any substantial claim it manages to establish. For trivialities and outright mistakes, on the contrary, I deem myself entirely responsible. Very special thanks deserve also my examiners, Darren Bradley and Katherine Hawley, for being among the first readers of the final manuscript. It goes without saying that this work will only have a chance at making broader impact thanks to Darren’s and Katherine’s challenging feedback. Further, having kept in touch with them from an early stage of writing contributed greatly to shape my ideas. Darren organised frequent workshops on the topic of theory choice in metaphysics, which kept me updated on the forthcoming literature and provided chances to discuss it with some of the most influential writers in the field. Katherine supported my application for a four-months visiting scholarship at St. Andrews’ Arché centre – one of the most formative experiences of my academic life – and even after I returned to Leeds she was always happy to spend time discussing my latest writings. This possibility of frequent interaction was especially motivating for two reasons. First, as the reader will notice, my strategy in the second part of the thesis (Chapters 6 – 10) owes much to “Ontological Innocence”, a paper Katherine published in 2014 shortly before I begun studying for my PhD. Second, I am indebted to ideas Katherine presented in a panel discussion at the Ninth International Conference of the German Society for Analytic Philosophy (GAP 9) in 2015. This time the subject is the relationship between metaphysics and science and particularly how to approach metaphysical questions with methods constrained and informed by reputable scientific knowledge. The question I approach asks about the structure of part-whole relations (in a sense we will have time to clarify) and an early, guiding idea I iii found in Katherine’s talk was that answering this question requires a detour through meta-metaphysical topics. We need to ask, for example, whether relations retrieved in advanced science, whose properties seem to reveal surprising new features of the way a part relates to its whole, count as relations of part-whole in a literal and non-metaphoric sense (Chapters 2, 3). These meta-metaphysical preliminaries to using science in theorising about the part- whole relations are so important as to informing my thesis’ title, which reveals that what follows is a work in (Meta)2physics. An exponent follows ‘Meta’ to indicate our aim of invoking science to uncover surprising features of part- whole relations, which metaphysics alone cannot discover. Moreover, the second power of (Meta) is ‘metameta-‘, which indicates the importance of the meta-metaphysical route for pursuing the former aim. To continue, I am indebted to a number of exceptional philosophers, whose comments greatly enhanced the outlook of this work. To my eyes, these figures boldly lead the discipline “where no one has gone before” or most certainly will in the very near future. Thanks, therefore, to Kenneth Aizawa, Claudio Calosi, Christina ‘Squared Cee’ Conroy, Javier Cumpa, Ilaria Canavotto, Jonathan Diettrich, Robert DiSalle, John Divers, Mauro Dorato, Joaquim Giannotti, Carl Gillett, Brigitte Falkenburg, Kit Fine, Suki Finn, Akiko Frischhut, Micheal Huemer, Naoaki Kitamura, James Ladyman, Joseph Melia, D. Hugh Mellor, Kohei Morita, Alyssa Ney, Andrea Raimondi, Juha Saatsi, Thomas Sattig, Theodore Sider, Jonathan Schaffer, Jeroen Smid, Alistair Wilson and Jessica Wilson. To a similar extent I am grateful to the entire graduate community at Leeds and St. Andrews, with a honourable mention to my most frequent philosophical interlocutors: Callum Duguid, Douglas Earl, Jade Fletcher, James Fraser, Will Gamester, Lewis Hickley, Alice Murphy, Simon Newey, Robert Pezet, Nahuel Sznajderhaus and Nick Tusker. For its financial support through three of my four years at Leeds, my highest gratitude goes to The University of Leeds, whose 110th Anniversary Scholarship I was awarded in 2014. I am also thankful, more specifically, to the iv University’s School of Philosophy, Religion and the History of Science for a number of travel grants, which I could avail myself of to attend exceptionally formative events in the UK, USA, Europe and Canada. A final set of acknowledgements relates less to my daily academic surroundings but is by no means less important. I am grateful to The University of Leeds’ Japanese Society and the European Network of Japanese Philosophy for quenching my thirst for symbols with more symbols. To them I say, vowing perpetual friendship: 私たちは誰でも他者との一体感を切望する何かをう ちに秘めている (deep within us lies a will for oneness with others). As it happens, example sentences from online dictionaries can conceal great wisdom1. I owe much professionally and as a person to my friends at EF - Education First: Martina Argine, Rob Arnsmar, Karlie Bertram, Kat Insull, Nora Johnsson, Bryan and Mickey Lao, Lea Le Nabec, Laura Salonen, Joshua Webster, Alice Zentilomo and many others. They all taught me to ‘sparkle’ and not to compromise on my personality in return for monetary rewards. This is the same lesson I learned from some brilliant pieces of song writing, particularly by my friend Ichiko Aoba and The Jezabels. Despite seven years spent away from my hometown, my closest friends never failed to support me. For this I wish to thank you, members of the Oἶδα Council of Milan, who luckily came into existence at closeby places and times: Pietro Barbini, Guido Beduschi, Dario and Bianca Bonetti, Arianna Cardella, Vincenzo Cirillo, Alessandro De Cia, Lorenzo Foletto, Bianca Giacobone, Gianluca Meneghel, Elia Nigris, Alesia Preite and Ayurzana Purevdorj. Last, far from the kind of acknowledgement that demands justification, I would like to dedicate this thesis to Francesca and Enzo, whose parental patience exceeds the limits of pure reason, and to Yuqing, who clears away the darkness like moonlight from the skies. 1 “他者” (tasha), In: JapanDict (© 2016), available at: https://www.japandict.com/他者. v Abstract A metaphysical naturalist could find the following combination of claims attractive. First, part-whole and composition in physics are sui generis and lack some of the ‘core’ features we ascribe to these concepts and their worldly satisfiers in first-order metaphysics. Second, having agreed that some physical objects of interest satisfy sui generis concepts and/or relate by sui generis relations, none among these objects satisfies a classical concept or relate by a classical part-whole relation (e.g. the concept or relation of mereological part). The first claim I read as one of ‘appropriation’: the structural relations between physical objects of interest are sui generis and yet they pertain to the mereological kind. The second I read as one of ‘elimination’: metaphysically abstracted part-whole (or composition) has no instances in well- regarded physical domains. The dissertation argues for appropriation and against elimination. For appropriation, because current physics sanctions relata of part-whole relations (or at least satisfiers of part-whole concepts) that clash with intuitive, seemingly analytic principles for part-whole, e.g. the Antisymmetry postulate (x and y are mutual parts only if identical). Against elimination, because whether these objects of interest to physics also relate by ‘canonical’ part-whole (with the intuitive principles) is largely a question of parsimony. One removes instances of the canonical relations because these are not needed to account for the composition of objects that already relate by the non-canonical ones. But some of these relations at least (such as mereological part-whole) resist the pressure from parsimony, for they come at no cost once the objects already relate non-canonically (e.g. in opposition to the Antisymmetry postulate). The latter we can argue for in (at least) two ways: 1. canonical and non-canonical part-whole are members of a single kind, 2. canonical part-whole is of a kind with identity. Given either view and a preference for theories with minimal kinds, instances of the canonical relation do not increase a theory’s profligacy, because their kind is already instanced in a theory of objects that relate non-canonically. My preference is for the latter view. vi Table of Contents Introduction 1 1. General Composition Question and core principles 7 1.1 Composition and Part-whole 7 1.2 General composition and part-whole questions 8 1.3 Partial and full answers 9 1.4 The conceptual and empirical tasks 11 1.5 The conceptual and the empirical I: 15 undeserving satisfiers 1.6 The conceptual and the empirical II: 16 unfamiliar features 1.6.1 The target concepts 17 1.6.2 Core principles 20 1.7 Alternative core-periphery distinctions 21 1.8 Do we need naturalistic evidence against the 26 core? 1.8.1 Antisymmetry and Idempotence 26 1.8.2 Weak Supplementation (a primer) 28 1.9 Conclusion 31 2.
Recommended publications
  • Comments on Sider's Four Dimensionalism
    Sally Haslanger MIT Department of Linguistics and Philosophy [email protected] 12/30/03 Comments on Sider I. Introduction Congratulations to Ted on the APA Prize. Ted’s book Four Dimensionalism is an impressive piece of work, and it is an honor to be included in this session. The book is a paradigm of systematic work in analytic metaphysics. It demonstrates a comprehensive understanding of a variety of debates over time, persistence, material constitution, as well as a sensitivity to background issues concerning methodology in metaphysics. It is a significant accomplishment. I’ll start by giving a very brief summary of Sider’s position and will identify some points on which my own position differs from his. I’ll then raise four issues, viz., how to articulate the 3-dimensionalist view, the trade-offs between Ted’s stage view of persistence and endurance with respect to intrinsic properties, the endurantist’s response to the argument from vagueness, and finally more general questions about what’s at stake in the debate. I don’t believe that anything I say raises insurmountable problems for Sider’s view; and in fact, I’m sure he’s in a better position to defend his view more convincingly than I’m able to defend mine. However, there is plenty worth discussing further. Sider defends what he calls “four dimensionalism,” but we should start by being clear how he understands this position.1 He defines “four dimensionalism” as “an ontology of the material world according to which objects have temporal as well as spatial parts.” (xiii) So the thesis of four-dimensionalism Sider is interested in is a thesis about objects and their parts.
    [Show full text]
  • David Lewis on Persistence1 Katherine Hawley University of St Andrews
    David Lewis on Persistence1 Katherine Hawley University of St Andrews David Lewis takes a clear stance on persistence: Next, persistence through time. I take the view that nothing endures identically through time. (Except universals, if such there be; their loci would coincide with relations of qualitative match, would indeed constitute these relations, so they would commit no violations of Humean Supervenience.) Persisting particulars consist of temporal parts, united by various kinds of continuity. To the extent that the continuity is spatiotemporal and qualitative, of course it supervenes upon the arrangement of qualities. But the continuity that often matters most is causal continuity: the thing stays more or less the same because of the way its later temporal parts depend causally for their existence and character on the ones just before. So the spatiotemporal boundaries of persisting things, for example people, can supervene on the arrangement of qualities, provided that causation does. (Lewis, 1986b, xiii) To persist is to exist at more than one time, to transcend the momentary. How do things achieve this? We might answer with talk of thermodynamic stability, molecular bonds, photosynthesis, the porcupine’s spines, German manufacturing standards, legal protection of ancient monuments, or the uncanny ability of children to extract care from their parents. In Lewis’s terms, such answers explain the existence of spatiotemporal and qualitative continuities over time in causal terms, by reference either to the causal mechanisms which directly underpin such continuities, or to their preconditions and external circumstances. Explanations may differ according to the kind of object in question: German washing machines and yew trees are both long- lasting, relative to other types of appliance or tree respectively, but the reasons for their longevity are quite different.
    [Show full text]
  • Katherine Hawley [email protected]; +44 1334 462469; University of St Andrews, St Andrews, KY16 9AJ, UK (Full Version, Last Updated June 2015)
    CV – Katherine Hawley [email protected]; +44 1334 462469; University of St Andrews, St Andrews, KY16 9AJ, UK (Full version, last updated June 2015) 2008-present Professor of Philosophy, University of St Andrews. 1999-2008 Lecturer, then Senior Lecturer, University of St Andrews. (Spring 2003 Gillespie (Associate) Professor, College of Wooster, Ohio.) 1997-1999 Sidgwick Research Fellow, Newnham College Cambridge. 1994-1997 Ph.D., University of Cambridge (graduated June 1998). 1993-1994 M.Phil., History and Philosophy of Science, University of Cambridge. 1989-1992 B.A. Hons., Physics and Philosophy, University of Oxford. Major Responsibilities 2014 Deputy Chair of Philosophy REF panel 2009-2014 Head of School of Philosophical, Anthropological and Film Studies, University of St Andrews 2005-2010 Editorial Chair, Philosophical Quarterly 2008 Member of Philosophy RAE panel (For other editorial work, committee service and responsibilities, see below.) Grants and Prizes Leverhulme Major Research Fellowship, 2014-16 (£94,445) Local PI for Marie Curie Initial Training Network 2009-2013 (value to St Andrews around £153K). AHRB Research Leave award 2004 (£13,153). Philip Leverhulme Prize 2003 (Research prize of £50,000) British Academy Joint Activities grant (£4,500 to fund collaboration with philosophers at the University of Western Washington during 2003-5). Authored Books Trust: A Very Short Introduction, Oxford: Oxford University Press (2012) (121 pp.) How Things Persist, Oxford: Oxford University Press (2001) (xi + 221 pp.) Selections reprinted in Haslanger and Fay (eds.) Persistence, MIT Press (2004). Co-Edited Books The Admissible Contents of Perception, edited with Fiona MacPherson, Oxford: Wiley- Blackwell (2011). Re-issue of Philosophical Quarterly special issue 59.236, with a new introduction sole-authored by FM.
    [Show full text]
  • Michael Traynor Phd Thesis
    MODAL ARGUMENTS, POSSIBLE EVIDENCE AND CONTINGENT METAPHYSICS Michael Thomas Traynor A Thesis Submitted for the Degree of PhD at the University of St Andrews 2017 Full metadata for this item is available in St Andrews Research Repository at: http://research-repository.st-andrews.ac.uk/ Please use this identifier to cite or link to this item: http://hdl.handle.net/10023/15595 This item is protected by original copyright Modal Arguments, Possible Evidence and Contingent Metaphysics. Michael Thomas Traynor This thesis is submitted in partial fulfilment for the degree of PhD at the University of St Andrews Date of submission: 23/09/2016 1 Abstract. The present work explores various ways in which contingent evidence can impact metaphysics, while advocating that, just as a scientific realist allows for ampliative inferences to the unobservable, ampliative inferences from possible evidence can warrant possibility claims that lie beyond the reach of sensorial imagination. In slogan form: possible evidence is a guide to possibility. Drawing on Shoemaker’s (1969) argument for the possibility of time without change, I advocate the following principle: If there is a possible world at which the observable facts make it objectively reasonable to conclude that p, then we should conclude that p is possibly true. This provides a route to contingentism in metaphysics, for, if one considers that there are worlds in which the observable facts make it objectively reasonable to conclude that p, and worlds in which the observable facts make it objectively reasonable to conclude that not-p, then my principle tells us that we should conclude that possibly-p and possibly not-p, i.e.
    [Show full text]
  • CV – Katherine Hawley
    CV – Katherine Hawley (Full version, last updated March 2019) [email protected]; +44 1334 462469; Department of Philosophy, University of St Andrews, St Andrews, KY16 9AJ, UK 2008-present Professor of Philosophy, University of St Andrews. 1999-2008 Lecturer, then Senior Lecturer, University of St Andrews. (Spring 2003 Gillespie (Associate) Professor, College of Wooster, Ohio.) 1997-1999 Sidgwick Research Fellow, Newnham College Cambridge. 1994-1997 Ph.D., University of Cambridge (graduated June 1998). 1993-1994 M.Phil., History and Philosophy of Science, University of Cambridge. 1989-1992 B.A. Hons., Physics and Philosophy, University of Oxford. Major Responsibilities 2014 Deputy Chair of Philosophy REF panel 2009-2014 Head of School of Philosophical, Anthropological and Film Studies, University of St Andrews 2005-2010 Editorial Chair, Philosophical Quarterly 2008 Member of Philosophy RAE panel (For other editorial work, committee service and responsibilities, see below.) Grants, Prizes, Honours Royal Society of Edinburgh workshop grant 2018-19 for ‘Exoplanet Ethics’ (£8000). St Leonards scholarship, full funding for interdisciplinary Ph.D. on privacy, 2018-21. SGSAH Applied Research Collaborative scholarship, full funding for Ph.D. collaboration with Audit Scotland, 2017-20. Grant from Philosophy and Science of Self-Control project, 2016-17 (US$67,716). Elected Fellow of the Royal Society of Edinburgh, 2016. Leverhulme Major Research Fellowship, 2014-16 (£94,445) Local PI for Marie Curie Initial Training Network 2009-2013 (value to St Andrews around £153K). AHRB Research Leave award 2004 (£13,153). Philip Leverhulme Prize 2003 (Research prize of £50,000) British Academy Joint Activities grant (£4,500 to fund collaboration with philosophers at the University of Western Washington during 2003-5).
    [Show full text]
  • International Studies in the Philosophy of Science the Structure of Objects
    This article was downloaded by: [University of Colorado, Boulder campus] On: 26 January 2011 Access details: Access Details: [subscription number 785022307] Publisher Routledge Informa Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registered office: Mortimer House, 37- 41 Mortimer Street, London W1T 3JH, UK International Studies in the Philosophy of Science Publication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information: http://www.informaworld.com/smpp/title~content=t713427740 The Structure of Objects Katherine Hawleya a Departments of Philosophy, University of St Andrews, Online publication date: 06 January 2011 To cite this Article Hawley, Katherine(2010) 'The Structure of Objects', International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 24: 3, 336 — 339 To link to this Article: DOI: 10.1080/02698595.2010.522418 URL: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/02698595.2010.522418 PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE Full terms and conditions of use: http://www.informaworld.com/terms-and-conditions-of-access.pdf This article may be used for research, teaching and private study purposes. Any substantial or systematic reproduction, re-distribution, re-selling, loan or sub-licensing, systematic supply or distribution in any form to anyone is expressly forbidden. The publisher does not give any warranty express or implied or make any representation that the contents will be complete or accurate or up to date. The accuracy of any instructions, formulae and drug doses should be independently verified with primary sources. The publisher shall not be liable for any loss, actions, claims, proceedings, demand or costs or damages whatsoever or howsoever caused arising directly or indirectly in connection with or arising out of the use of this material.
    [Show full text]
  • Testimony and Knowing How
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 41 (2010) 397–404 Contents lists available at ScienceDirect Studies in History and Philosophy of Science journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/shpsa Testimony and knowing how Katherine Hawley Department of Philosophy, University of St Andrews, Fife KY16 9AL Scotland, UK article info abstract Keywords: Much of what we learn from talking and listening does not qualify as testimonial knowledge: we can Knowledge how learn a great deal from other people without simply accepting what they say as being true. In this article, Practical knowledge I examine the ways in which we acquire skills or knowledge how from our interactions with other people, Tacit knowledge and I discuss whether there is a useful notion of testimonial knowledge how. Testimony Skills Ó 2010 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved. Assertion When citing this paper, please use the full journal title Studies in History and Philosophy of Science ‘‘Another topic in the epistemology of testimony that particu- 1. What is testimonial knowledge? larly interests us concerns the acquisition of non-propositional knowledge, skill or know-how. How does this form of learning dif- Epistemologists care about testimony because it can be a source fer from the standard cases considered in the literature on testi- of knowledge. In the paradigmatic case a speaker who knows some mony?” (Kusch and Lipton, 2002, p. 211). proposition p tells a listener that p, and the listener thereby ac- Sometimes you can figure out for yourself how to do something, quires testimonial knowledge that p. Some epistemologists think but sometimes you rely upon the kindness of others.
    [Show full text]
  • Stewart Shapiro's Complete Publication List
    PUBLICATIONS Books: Vagueness in context, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2006; reissued in paperback, March, 2008. Thinking about mathematics: The philosophy of mathematics, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2000. Philosophy of mathematics: Structure and ontology, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1997; reissued in paperback, Autumn 2000. Foundations without foundationalism: A case for second-order logic, Oxford Logic Guides 17, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1991, reissued in paperback, Summer 2000. Editorships: Oxford handbook of the philosophy of logic and mathematics, Oxford University Press, 2005. Special issue of History and Philosophy of Logic 20 (2000), a Festschrift for John Corcoran (edited with Michael Scanlan). Special issue of Philosophia Mathematica (3) 8 (2000), devoted to abstraction and neo-logicism. Two special issues of Philosophia Mathematica (3) 7 (1999), 9 (2001), devoted to the proceedings of a conference in memory of George Boolos, held at Notre Dame, during the April of 1998. The limits of logic: Second-order logic and the Skolem paradox, The international research library of philosophy, Dartmouth Publishing Company, 1996. Special issue of Philosophia Mathematica (3) 4 (1996), devoted to structuralism. Contributors: P. Benacerraf, G. Hellman, B. Hale, C. Parsons, M. Resnik, S. Shapiro. Intensional Mathematics, Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics 113, Amsterdam, North Holland Publishing Company, 1985, Contributors: S. Shapiro, J. Myhill, N. D. Goodman, A. Scedrov, V. Lifschitz, R. Flagg, R. Smullyan. Articles: “Towards a point-free account of the continuous” (with Geoffrey Hellman), Iyyun 61, 2012, 263- 287. “Revising logic in light of paradox”, in Insolubles and consequences: essays in honor of Stephen Read, Tributes 18, edited by Catarina Dutilh and Ole Hjortland, College Publications, 2012, 213-237.
    [Show full text]
  • Metaphysics (PHIL10155) Course Guide 2020/21
    Metaphysics (PHIL10155) Course Guide 2021/22 Course Organiser: Dr. Alasdair Richmond, [email protected] Dugald Stewart Building, room 6.11, 0131 650 3656 Timetable, Office hours, etc.: It’s August 16th 2021 as I write this and at present, this course is set to be delivered through a mixture of pre-recorded lectures (all on LEARN) and on- campus, in-person tutorials. (Details of which are linked to the DRPS page for this course.) I hope to be offering on-campus office hours but, like many another thing, they will all obviously be contingent on how the re-opening of University proceeds in the wake of Covid-19. In 2020-21, I found it useful to offer drop- in hours via Blackboard Collaborate so I will very probably do that again, even if campus re-opens. So look out for further announcements but chats via (e.g.) Collaborate, Skype or Teams will be possible regardless. Course Secretary: Ms. Ann Marie Cowe, [email protected] Undergraduate Teaching Office, Dugald Stewart Building, room G.06, 0131 650 3961 Department of Philosophy School of Philosophy, Psychology and Language Sciences University of Edinburgh Course Aims and Objectives In keeping with the course remit of offering a detailed introduction to one perennially interesting, central, topic in metaphysics, this year Metaphysics (PHIL10155) will consist, a sit has for a few years now, of detailed seminars and accompanying tutorials on key philosophical issues in the philosophy of time. Coverage is largely with an analytical slant but including some classic historical issues too. Students should end this course conversant with a range of significant metaphysical (and other) issues surrounding time.
    [Show full text]
  • Macpherson CV January 2021 Copy
    Fiona Macpherson January 2021 Curriculum Vitae Department of Philosophy University of Glasgow Glasgow G12 8QQ United Kingdom Phone: +44 (0)7837 059 652 Email: [email protected] URL: www.gla.ac.uk/people/fionamacpherson Present Position Professor of Philosophy 2011 – present; Senior Lecturer 2008 – 2011; Lecturer 2004 – 2008 Director of the Centre for the Study of Perceptual Experience 2004 – present University of Glasgow Visiting Positions Visiting Professor Institut Jean-Nicod École des Hautes Études en Sciences Sociales, Paris 15 March – 15 April 2019 Visiting Professor Department of Philosophy University of Kentucky September 2017 and 2018 Visiting Faculty National Endowment for the Humanities Summer Institute on Presupposition and Perception, Cornell University, USA June 2016 Visiting Professor Trnava University, Slovakia October 2015 Visiting Professor Institute of Philosophy, School of Advanced Studies, University of London, UK January –April 2013 Visiting Professor Umeå University, Sweden October 2011 Previous Positions Research Fellow Centre for Consciousness, Philosophy Program Research School of Social Sciences, Australian National University (paid position – took unpaid leave from Glasgow to take up this position) September 2005 – September 2006, February – May 2008 & February – May 2009 Rosamund Chambers Research Fellow in Philosophy Girton College, University of Cambridge 2002 – 2004 (curtailed by one year to take up the position at Glasgow) Teaching Fellow Department of Logic and Metaphysics, University of St. Andrews 2000 – 2002 (curtailed by one year to take up the position at Cambridge) Research Assistant Consciousness in the Natural World Project, University of Stirling 1997 – 1998 & 1999 – 2000 (part-time) Education PhD in Philosophy University of Stirling, 2000 Visiting Fellow Harvard University, 1998 – 1999 MLitt in Philosophy with Distinction in the Dissertation University of St.
    [Show full text]
  • Social Science As a Guide to Social Metaphysics?
    J Gen Philos Sci https://doi.org/10.1007/s10838-017-9389-5 ARTICLE Social Science as a Guide to Social Metaphysics? Katherine Hawley1 Ó The Author(s) 2018. This article is an open access publication Abstract If we are sympathetic to the project of naturalising metaphysics, how should we approach the metaphysics of the social world? What role can the social sciences play in metaphysical investigation? In the light of these questions, this paper examines three possible approaches to social metaphysics: inference to the best explanation from current social science, conceptual analysis, and Haslanger-inspired ameliorative projects. Keywords Social science Á Social ontology Á Social metaphysics Á Scientific realism Á Conceptual analysis Á Ameliorative 1 Introduction Philosophical debates about the epistemic relationship between science and metaphysics typically focus upon the natural sciences, especially fundamental physics. Naturalisers argue that discussions of the metaphysics of space, time, causation, composition and identity are fruitless, incomplete, or naı¨ve unless they are closely guided by contemporary scientific opinion. And the scientific opinions which matter are primarily those of physi- cists. This quest for scientifically determined—or at least scientifically informed—meta- physics has both positive and negative motivations. Positive: physics can be pictured as moving from one success to another, bringing technological revolutions in its wake, and opening up realms of the tiny, the enormous, and the spatio-temporally distant to previ- ously unimaginable empirical investigation. Negative: given this onward march to the broad, sunlit uplands, it becomes more and more difficult to understand how a priori, conceptual, or armchair strategies could possibly rival physics in helping us grasp the deep & Katherine Hawley [email protected] 1 Department of Philosophy, University of St Andrews, Edgecliffe 212, The Scores, St Andrews, Fife KY16 9AL, UK 123 K.
    [Show full text]
  • Publications All Papers Are Listed Below with Links To
    Alexander Bird – Publications All papers are listed below with links to publishers’ websites or to pdfs. For details of citations see: http://scholar.google.com/citations?user=8PytVRIAAAAJ Books • Knowing Science Oxford: Oxford University Press (forthcoming). • Nature’s Metaphysics: Laws and Properties Oxford: Oxford University Press (2007) (231pp). Reviewed by Helen Beebee Times Literary Supplement 5511 (14 November 2008) http://eis.bris.ac.uk/~plajb/research/reviews/Beebee_review_TLS.pdf John Carroll Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews http://ndpr.nd.edu/review.cfm?id=13333 Anjan Chakravartty Metascience 18 (2009) http://eis.bris.ac.uk/~plajb/research/reviews/Chakravartty_Metascience.pdf Stefan Storrie Review of Metaphysics 63 (2009) http://eis.bris.ac.uk/~plajb/research/reviews/Storrie_Review_of_Metaphysics.pdf Marc Lange Philosophical Review 119 (2010) http://eis.bris.ac.uk/~plajb/research/reviews/Lange_Phil_Review.pdf Simon Bostock Philosophy 85 (2010) http://eis.bris.ac.uk/~plajb/research/reviews/Bostock_Philosophy.pdf Barbara Vetter Philosophiegeschichte und Logische Analyse 12 (2009) http://eis.bris.ac.uk/~plajb/research/reviews/Vetter_Logical_Analysis.pdf Peter Menzies (Critical Notice) Analysis Reviews 69 (2009) http://eis.bris.ac.uk/~plajb/research/reviews/Menzies_Analysis.pdf Max Kistler Mind 119 (2010) http://eis.bris.ac.uk/~plajb/research/reviews/Kistler_Mind.pdf Gerhard Schurz Erkenntnis 74 (2011) http://eis.bris.ac.uk/~plajb/research/reviews/Schurz_Erkenntnis.pdf Lauren Ashwell Protosociology (2012) http://eis.bris.ac.uk/~plajb/research/reviews/Ashwell_ProtoSociology.pdf • Thomas Kuhn Chesham: Acumen Press; Princeton: Princeton University Press (2000) (308pp). (Spanish edition Thomas Kuhn Madrid: Tecnos (2002) trans. Carmen Garcia Trevijano.) Reviewed by Francis Remedios Philosophy in Review 22 (2001) http://eis.bris.ac.uk/~plajb/research/reviews/Remedios_Phil-in-Review.pdf Edward Rothstein New York Times (21 July 2001) and La Nacion (25 August 2001) http://eis.bris.ac.uk/~plajb/research/reviews/Rothstein_NYTimes.html James Robert Brown Brit.
    [Show full text]