Alexander Hamilton: Constitutional Realist

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Alexander Hamilton: Constitutional Realist Michael P. Federici. The Political Philosophy of Alexander Hamilton. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 2012. viii + 291 pp. $24.95, paper, ISBN 978-1-4214-0539-1. Reviewed by John G. McCurdy Published on H-Law (June, 2013) Commissioned by Christopher R. Waldrep (San Francisco State University) Since the dawn of the Republic, Alexander Founders series, this book should serve as an ex‐ Hamilton has held a precarious position in the cellent introduction to the complicated and some‐ pantheon of “The Founders.” For more than two times contradictory mind of the founder. In clear hundred years, politicians and scholars have prose that is accessible to students, scholars, and picked over Hamilton’s voluminous corpus both educated readers alike, Federici accomplishes the to praise and to bury the frst secretary of the unenviable task of unpacking the political philos‐ treasury. Simultaneously denounced as a monar‐ ophy of a man who never authored a work of sys‐ chist and praised as a republican, Hamilton has tematic thought. In part, this was because Hamil‐ routinely been marshaled into action both to at‐ ton’s life was tragically cut short at the age of tack and defend the growth of the federal govern‐ forty-nine and thus he never had a chance to re‐ ment, laissez-faire economics, and judicial ac‐ flect back on his life the way that John Adams and tivism. Any idea that Hamilton’s politics are the Thomas Jefferson did. stuff of esoteric arguments locked in the ivory Yet even had Hamilton’s life been spared by tower were put to rest nearly a decade ago when Aaron Burr, it is uncertain that he ever would the New York Historical Society’s exhibit “Alexan‐ have produced such a tome. In fact, this is where der Hamilton: The Man Who Made Modern Amer‐ Federici begins his analysis, arguing that Hamil‐ ica” elicited wide criticism for having a conserva‐ ton was a moral realist who believed that the tive tilt.[1] lessons of history were far more valuable to con‐ To make sense of Alexander Hamilton’s ideas structing a government than any abstract philoso‐ and their legacy, Michael Federici has authored phy. Accordingly, Federici is forced to read the The Political Philosophy of Alexander Hamilton. largely public writings of Hamilton (such as The An entry in the Johns Hopkins University Press’s Federalist and other newspaper columns) in or‐ The Political Philosophy of the American der to construct his own framework of Hamilton’s H-Net Reviews political philosophy. The result is appropriately 35). Most importantly, Federici argues that Hamil‐ quite Hamiltonian as Federici draws on what his ton was “an ethical dualist” who believed that hu‐ subject called the “accumulated experience of mankind could not be made perfect (p. 39). This ages” to make his case (p. 50). Federici also draws put Hamilton at considerable odds with Jefferson on the considerable secondary literature on and Thomas Paine, whose idealism preached that Hamilton--most notably biographies by Forrest the popular will was infallible and thus should be McDonald and Ron Chernow--as well as writings unshackled from the tyranny of government. by contemporaries such as Thomas Jefferson.[2] Hamilton believed that government was neces‐ The result is largely satisfying. Attempting to sary to protect people from their own selfsh ends, “provide a balanced, nuanced view of Hamilton, a stance that Federici observes brought Hamil‐ one that may be messy but is more true to his po‐ ton’s political philosophy closer to that of Edmund litical ideas than any ideologically driven view,” Burke than that of Jean-Jacques Rousseau. Federici succeeds in placing Hamilton in his late- From the personal, Federici moves to Hamil‐ eighteenth-century context, often going to great ton’s philosophical anthropology and theoretical lengths to explain why present-day labels such as foundations of constitutionalism. In two substan‐ “nationalist” are ill fitted to his subject (p. 23). tial chapters, he expands on the nature of Hamil‐ The book is organized functionally, beginning ton’s “ethical dualism” and how this influenced with the man and his political philosophy writ his role in the shaping of the U.S. Constitution. Ac‐ large, before moving to the specific application of cording to Federici, Hamilton has long suffered Hamilton’s ideas and ending with a contrast of unfairly for a “pessimistic, dark, or cynical” view Hamiltonian and Jeffersonian philosophies. This of human nature (p. 63). However, Hamilton’s organization means that several points and exam‐ prescriptions for government followed neither ples reappear two and even three times, although Thomas Hobbes’s amoral realism nor Niccolò this may make the book more accessible as read‐ Machiavelli’s evil efficiency. Instead, Hamilton’s ers and teachers who want to sample a single sober realism was balanced by a refreshing opti‐ chapter can do so and still grasp the totality of mism. He opposed African American slavery as Federici’s argument. unjust and believed that some individuals could rise above their baser instincts and put communi‐ Following an effective introduction, Federici ty before self-interest. Such a hopeful view of hu‐ begins his exploration of his subject with a brief manity was critical to Hamilton’s faith that a “nat‐ biography of Alexander Hamilton. Federici essen‐ ural aristocracy” would emerge to guide the re‐ tially recaps a familiar story of Hamilton the bas‐ public (p. 54). tard son of broken West Indian family who made his way to New York City on the eve of the Ameri‐ In addition to challenging the view of Hamil‐ can Revolution. Hitching his wagon to George ton as a pessimist, Federici also works effectively Washington’s star, the ambitious Hamilton rose in to dismiss the old canard that Hamilton was a the ranks of the Continental Army and the Wash‐ monarchist. He demonstrates Hamilton’s consis‐ ington administration before leaving to devote tent allegiance to republicanism before examin‐ himself to the organization of the Federalist Party ing the sources historians have cited as “proof” of and the promotion of its policies, only to be Hamilton’s monarchism, effectively explaining gunned down in an unfortunate duel with vice away each one as misconstrued or ill informed. president Aaron Burr. Federici illuminates Hamil‐ Nevertheless Hamilton’s ethical dualism meant ton’s “impatient enthusiasm” which made him a that he distrusted the masses to always make the busy author and attracted powerful enemies (p. right decision on their own. In particular, he 2 H-Net Reviews feared that “a momentary lower passion” might the security of the nation demanded otherwise. As “overwhelm the dictates of reason and virtue” (p. a result, Hamilton the treasury secretary appears 76). Hamilton thus opposed direct democracy and far more moderate that many have assumed. For sought to interject elements of “permanence” into example, we learn here that Hamilton supported the Constitution such as an unelected judiciary assuming state debts after the Revolutionary War, and senators for life (p. 130). Such is not to say but railed against inflated national fnancial obli‐ that Hamilton did not trust the people; in fact, he gations. Federici also pushes back against the idea demanded broad suffrage for the House of Repre‐ that Hamilton sought to make law by judicial fat, sentatives. Rather, Hamilton desired a mixed con‐ contending that “his judicial theory has little in stitution that was as balanced as his view of hu‐ common with modern judicial activism, because man nature. it remained largely inconsistent with the original Having established Hamilton’s views writ meaning of the Constitution” (p. 218). large, Federici focuses in on a few debates and, in All told, The Political Philosophy of Alexander the process, clears up a number of popular mis‐ Hamilton is an effective investigation of an ex‐ conceptions about Hamilton. Although a propo‐ tremely consequential man and his ideas. Highly nent of a strong and energetic national govern‐ accessible, this volume should prove useful to ment, Hamilton did not seek to abolish the states those who seek a general introduction to Hamil‐ or even to make them dependent upon the nation. ton’s politics as well as decided scholars who have Instead, Hamilton believed that power had to be traced the conflicting historiography of this properly divided between the nation and the founder. states so as to prevent future tyrannies. For this If there is something missing here, it is that in reason, Federici dismisses the label “nationalist” seeking to place Hamilton solidly in the eigh‐ for Hamilton. Arguing that “the rise of totalitari‐ teenth century, Federici runs the risk of anachro‐ anism, fascism, certain types of authoritarianism, nism. Federici is correct that Hamilton did not and imperial democracy” has so radically support the modern welfare state, judicial ac‐ changed the meaning of nationalism, he suggests tivism, or twentieth-century forms of nationalism. that by the modern definition of nationalism, However, because these ideas did not exist when Hamilton may actually have been “one of the frst Hamilton died in 1804, the relevance of arguing antinationalists, because he recognized that na‐ for their absence in Hamilton’s writings is some‐ tions are not the ultimate measure of goodness or what dubious. Conversely, if Federici is arguing justice” (pp. 182-183). Hamilton did seek to knit that Hamilton’s logic cannot be extended to en‐ the states together into a tighter union--which did compass these ideas, this oddly assumes that necessarily require that they relinquish some of Hamilton’s philosophy would not have changed their power--but localities were essential to a bal‐ over time in accordance with circumstances. In ance of power. this, it is unfortunate that Federici does not ex‐ By the same logic, Federici also rejects efforts plain how Hamilton’s reasoned and thoughtful to make Hamilton a hero of either laissez-faire advocacy of an active (and uniquely American) capitalism or the modern welfare state, arguing federal government was adopted and expanded that “his view of human nature would not have on by the likes of Henry Clay, Abraham Lincoln, allowed either the faith in economic anarchy sug‐ and Franklin Roosevelt.
Recommended publications
  • Not Another Constitutional Law Course: a Proposal to Teach a Course on the Constitution
    Florida International University College of Law eCollections Faculty Publications Faculty Scholarship 1991 Not Another Constitutional Law Course: A Proposal to Teach a Course on the Constitution Thomas E. Baker Florida International University College of Law Follow this and additional works at: https://ecollections.law.fiu.edu/faculty_publications Part of the Constitutional Law Commons, and the Legal Education Commons Recommended Citation Thomas E. Baker, Not Another Constitutional Law Course: A Proposal to Teach a Course on the Constitution , 76 Iowa L. Rev. 739 (1991). Available at: https://ecollections.law.fiu.edu/faculty_publications/173 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Faculty Scholarship at eCollections. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Publications by an authorized administrator of eCollections. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Not Another Constitutional Law Course: A Proposal to Teach a Course on the Constitutiont Thomas E. Baker* and James E. Viator** Justice Douglas once railed against law review writing in which "the views presented are those of special pleaders who fail to disclose that they are not scholars but rather people with axes to grind."l Not so here. Authors ofcourse materials, even casebook authors, package their biases in subtle but effective ways, through their selection, organization, and empha­ sis of materials. By this essay, which is based on the preface to our multilithed course materials, we mean to disclose our own biases to our students and readers. This is the basic question we consider at the outset: How is a course on the.Constitution different from a'course on constitutional law? Our course, "The Framers' Constitution," is about the history and theory of the t ©1991 Thomas E.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Commander-In-Chief Power
    Georgetown University Law Center Scholarship @ GEORGETOWN LAW 2008 On the Commander-In-Chief Power David Luban Georgetown University Law Center, [email protected] Georgetown Public Law and Legal Theory Research Paper No. 1026302 This paper can be downloaded free of charge from: https://scholarship.law.georgetown.edu/facpub/598 http://ssrn.com/abstract=1026302 81 S. Cal. L. Rev. 477-571 (2008) This open-access article is brought to you by the Georgetown Law Library. Posted with permission of the author. Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.georgetown.edu/facpub Part of the Constitutional Law Commons ON THE COMMANDER IN CHIEF POWER ∗ DAVID LUBAN BRADBURY: Obviously, the Hamdan decision, Senator, does implicitly recognize that we’re in a war, that the President’s war powers were triggered by the attacks on the country, and that [the] law of war paradigm applies. That’s what the whole case was about. LEAHY: Was the President right or was he wrong? BRADBURY: It’s under the law of war that we . LEAHY: Was the President right or was he wrong? BRADBURY: . hold the President is always right, Senator. —exchange between a U.S. Senator and a Justice Department 1 lawyer ∗ University Professor and Professor of Law and Philosophy, Georgetown University. I owe thanks to John Partridge and Sebastian Kaplan-Sears for excellent research assistance; to Greg Reichberg, Bill Mengel, and Tim Sellers for clarifying several points of American, Roman, and military history; to Marty Lederman for innumerable helpful and critical conversations; and to Vicki Jackson, Paul Kahn, Larry Solum, and Amy Sepinwall for helpful comments on an earlier draft.
    [Show full text]
  • Charles Beard Versus the Founding
    W7 l91 6 CHARLES BEARD VERSUS THE FOUNDING FATHERS: PROPERTY CONCEPTS IN THE EIGHTEENTH CENTURY THESIS Presented to the Graduate Council of the University of North Texas in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements For the Degree of MASTER OF ARTS By Rhonda J. Breaux, B.A. Denton, Texas May, 1992 Breaux, Rhonda J., Charles Beard versus the Founding Fathers: Property Concepts in the Eighteenth Centuy Master of Arts (History), August, 1992, 134 pp., 36 titles. This thesis deals with the role of property in the formation of the American Constitution and government. Charles Beard's views on property are compared with writings from the eighteenth century. Beard's writings on property and his critics are examined in the first two chapters. Then, the thesis's two historical contexts are evaluated. Concentrating on the Enclosure Acts, the fourth chapter looks at the importance of land to the former Englishmen. The eighteenth century view of property is the focus of the fifth section. The last chapter contrasts the two different views of property. Beard believed that the Constitution was a conservative document that protected the property of the few over the many. The Founding Fathers actually included liberal protections for property in the eighteenth century. TABLE OF CONTENTS Page Chapter I. CHARLES BEARD'S VIEWS ON PROPERTY: REALTY VERSUS PERSONALTY ........................ 1 II. CRITICS OF CHARLES BEARD: ROBERT E. BROWN, FORREST MCDONALD, AND RICHARD HOFSTADTER....---------- ................ 23 III. THE TWO HISTORICAL CONTEXTS..... ................. 33 IV. THE IMPORTANCE OF LAND: AN ANALYSIS OF THE ENGLISH ENCLOSURE ACTS.--................54 V. EIGHTEENTH CENTURY VIEWS OF PROPERTY..............76 VI.
    [Show full text]
  • William Robertson Coe Professor of History and American Studies Professor of Political Science and (By Courtesy) of Law Stanford University Stanford CA 94305-2024
    JACK N. RAKOVE William Robertson Coe Professor of History and American Studies Professor of Political Science and (by courtesy) of Law Stanford University Stanford CA 94305-2024 Office: Lane History Corner 117 (650) 723-4514, fax 725-0597 [email protected] EDUCATION: 1969-75 Harvard University; Ph.D. in History 1966-67 University of Edinburgh, Scotland 1964-68 Haverford College; A.B. with Honors in History EMPLOYMENT: 1980- Department of History, Stanford University; Assistant Professor 1980-82; Associate Professor 1982-90; Professor, 1990; William Robertson Coe Professor of History and American Studies, 1996-; Professor of Political Science 1996- ; Professor of Law (by courtesy), spring 1999, spring 2003, 2005- 1975-82 Department of History, Colgate University; Instructor, 1975-76; Assistant Professor 1976-80; Associate Professor with tenure 1980-82 (on leave) fall 2003 Visiting Professor, New York University School of Law spring 2011 Visiting Professor, Tel Aviv University School of Law AWARDS AND FELLOWSHIPS: Member, American Philosophical Society, 2007 Fellow, Center for Advanced Study in the Behavioral Sciences, 2006-2007 Doctor of Humane Letters, Barat College, 2002 President, Society for the History of the Early American Republic, 2002-2003 Member, American Antiquarian Society, 2000 Member, American Academy of Arts and Sciences, 1999 Society of the Cincinnati Book Prize, 1998 Pulitzer Prize in History, 1997 Fraunces Tavern Museum Book Award, 1997 Stanford Humanities Center, Faculty Fellowship, 1988-89, 2000-2001 National Endowment for the Humanities, Constitutional Fellowship, 1984-85 National Endowment for the Humanities, Summer Seminar Instructor, 1984 (College Teachers), 1987 (Law Professors) Project '87, research fellowship, 1982 National Endowment for the Humanities, Summer Stipend, 1977 Delancey K.
    [Show full text]
  • Russell Kirk and the Rhetoric of Order Eric Grabowsky
    Duquesne University Duquesne Scholarship Collection Electronic Theses and Dissertations Summer 2010 Russell Kirk and the Rhetoric of Order Eric Grabowsky Follow this and additional works at: https://dsc.duq.edu/etd Recommended Citation Grabowsky, E. (2010). Russell Kirk and the Rhetoric of Order (Doctoral dissertation, Duquesne University). Retrieved from https://dsc.duq.edu/etd/595 This Immediate Access is brought to you for free and open access by Duquesne Scholarship Collection. It has been accepted for inclusion in Electronic Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Duquesne Scholarship Collection. For more information, please contact [email protected]. RUSSELL KIRK AND THE RHETORIC OF ORDER A Dissertation Submitted to the McAnulty College and Graduate School of Liberal Arts Duquesne University In partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy By Eric Grabowsky August 2010 Copyright by Eric Grabowsky 2010 RUSSELL KIRK AND THE RHETORIC OF ORDER By Eric Grabowsky Approved July 9, 2010 ________________________________ ________________________________ Dr. Janie M. Harden Fritz Dr. Calvin Troup Associate Professor, Department of Associate Professor, Department of Communication & Rhetorical Studies Communication & Rhetorical Studies (Dissertation Director) (First Reader) ________________________________ ________________________________ Dr. Richard Thames Dr. Ronald C. Arnett, Chair Associate Professor, Department of Department of Communication & Communication & Rhetorical Studies Rhetorical Studies (Second Reader) ________________________________ Dr. Christopher M. Duncan, Dean McAnulty College and Graduate School of Liberal Arts iii ABSTRACT RUSSELL KIRK AND THE RHETORIC OF ORDER By Eric Grabowsky August 2010 Dissertation supervised by Dr. Janie M. Harden Fritz The corpus of historically-minded “man of letters” and twentieth century leader among conservatives, Russell Amos Kirk, prompts one to reflect upon a realist rhetoric of order for conservative discourse in particular and public argumentation in general.
    [Show full text]
  • RIP FORREST Mcdonald
    H-Law R.I.P. FORREST McDONALD (1927-2016) Discussion published by R. B. Bernstein on Monday, January 25, 2016 The prolific and controversial constitutional historian Forrest McDonald died of heart failure on 18 January 2016 in Tuscaloosa, Ala. He was 89. Born on 7 January 1927 in Orange, Texas, he was educated at the University of Texas, where he received his doctorate in 1955. Having taught at Brown (1959-1967) and Wayne State (1967-1976) Universities, he was best known as a faculty member at the University of Alabama, where he taught from 1976 until his retirement in 2002. His first book was his dissertation, LET THERE BE LIGHT: THE ELECTRIC UTILITY INDUSTRY IN WISCONSIN (Madison: American History Research Center, 1957). He followed that book with a biography of the controversial business magnate Samuel Insull (University of Chicago Press, 1962). But his second book, WE THE PEOPLE: THE ECONOMIC ORIGINS OF THE CONSTITUTION (University of Chicago Press, 1958), signaled a major shift in his research interests and scholarly priorities away from business and economic history. In that book, which became the first of a trilogy, he re-examined the findings of Charles A. Beard’s landmark 1913 study, AN ECONOMIC INTERPRETATION OF THE CONSTITUTION OF THE UNITED STATES, and refuted Beard’s thesis that holders of personalty influenced the making of the Constitution to protect their financial interests in that property; at the same time, McDonald showed the effects of three dozen kinds of financial interests on the making of the document. McDonald followed up WE THE PEOPLE with his 1965 study E PLURIBUS UNUM: THE FORMATION OF THE AMERICAN REPUBLIC (new edition, 1979, Liberty Fund), a narrative history that focused on the sectional and other political forces that shaped the creation of the Cosntitution and the government it authorized.
    [Show full text]
  • Download Download
    Book Reviews 91 Political Ideas of the American Revolution: Britannic-American Con- tributions to the Problem of Imperial Organization, 1765-1775. Third edition. By Randolph G. Adams. Commentary by Merrill Jensen. (New York: Barnes & Noble, Inc., 1958. Pp. vii, 216. Frontispiece, bibliographical notes, index. Paperbound, $1.60.) According to the late Randolph G. Adams, from 1763 to 1775 the American colonies contested British policy with constitutional arguments which, despite their diversity, were essentially a demand for definition of colonial status vis-h-vis Great Britain. Behind the verbal fencing of shifting American arguments was a consistent plea for self-government, but self-government within the Empire. England’s failure to solve the imperial problem raised by colonial opposition ended in the loss of her American colonies. By presenting the major contentions of representative thinkers such as John Adams, James Wilson, and Thomas Paine, the author endeavors to show that during pre-Revolutionary debate there began to emerge the concept of government as an instrument of society answerable to law as well as the concept of divided authority or federalism. These principles, Adams believes, are America’s contribu- tion to political thought, which form the basis of the American system of government and which also provide the root ideas for both the League of Nations and the British Commonwealth. Adams has acutely analyzed the constitutional controversy prior to the Revolution, but as S. E. Morison has noted (English Historical Review, XXXVIII [January, 19231, 115), he does not place political theory as sharply in its framework of historical fact as he might have.
    [Show full text]
  • Forrest Mcdonald the FAITHFUL and the CRISIS of FAITH
    NO Forrest McDonald THE FAITHFUL AND THE CRISIS OF FAITH By most objective criteria, the Americans of 1800 had abundant cause to be proud, confident, even smug .... And yet a sense of decadence had plagued the land for five years and more. From the pulpit rang c~ies of despair and doom; dishonesty as well as panic had invaded the marketplace; liars and libelers made a travesty of freedom of the press; violence, hysteria, and paranoia infested the public councils. Those Americans who called themselves Federalists felt betrayed by an ungrateful people for whom they had labored long and well, and feared that the horrors of Jacobinism and anarchy were hourly imminent. Those who called themselves Republicans felt betrayed by the twin evils of money and monarchy, and feared that/iberty was about to breathe its last. Many who embraced neither political sect, whether from apathy or disgust, nonetheless shared the general feeling that the nation was in an advanced state of moral rot. What the Federalists thought was actually of little consequence, for they were soon to expire, in what Thomas Jefferson called the Revolution of 1800. Almost miraculously, with their demise--though not because of it--despalr suddenly gave way to euphoria. The new optimism, like the pervasive gloom and the defeat of Federalism that preceded it, stemmed from an interplay of social, religious, ideological, and economic forces and institutions, and from certain ingrained American characteristics. If one would understand the Jeffersonian revolution--how it happened and how it affected the nation’s destiny--one must seek first to understand those forces, institutions, and characteristics.
    [Show full text]
  • Wed., May 6, 1987 Full Text May Not Be Reprinted Without the Author's Permission
    EMBARGOED: For release after 8:00 p.m. (EDT), Wed., May 6, 1987 Full text may not be reprinted without the author's permission. 16th Jefferson Lecture in the Humanities THE INTELLECTUAL WORLD OF THE FOUNDING FATHERS by Forrest McDonald It has been suggested by various intellectuals that the best thing Americans could do to commemorate the 200th anniversary of our Constitution would be to rewrite it to reflect the realities of the twentieth century. It has been suggested by various jurists that the Supreme Court is, and should be, doing just that. The assumption underlying both notions is that our pool of knowledge and understanding about human nature and political institutions is far more sophisticated than any that could have been available in the simple frontier society of eighteenth-century America. That assumption is as presumptuous as it is uninformed. To put it bluntly, it would be impossible in America today to assemble a group of people with anything near the combined experience, learning, and wisdom that the fifty-five authors of the Constitution took with them to Philadelphia in the summer of 1787. As an appetizer, I offer a couple of corroborative tidbits. Thirty-five of the delegates had attended college. Just to enter college during the eighteenth century — which students normally did at the age of fourteen or fifteen — it was necessary, among other things, to be able to read and translate from the original Latin into English (I quote from the requirements at King's College — now Columbia — which were typical) "the first three
    [Show full text]
  • A Republic, Madam, If You Can Keep It Forrest Mcdonald
    Notre Dame Journal of Law, Ethics & Public Policy Volume 4 Article 3 Issue 1 Symposium on Civic Virtue 1-1-2012 A Republic, Madam, If You Can Keep It Forrest McDonald Ellen Shapiro McDonald Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarship.law.nd.edu/ndjlepp Recommended Citation Forrest McDonald & E. Shapiro McDonald, A Republic, Madam, If You Can Keep It, 4 Notre Dame J.L. Ethics & Pub. Pol'y 7 (1990). Available at: http://scholarship.law.nd.edu/ndjlepp/vol4/iss1/3 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Notre Dame Journal of Law, Ethics & Public Policy at NDLScholarship. It has been accepted for inclusion in Notre Dame Journal of Law, Ethics & Public Policy by an authorized administrator of NDLScholarship. For more information, please contact [email protected]. ARTICLES A REPUBLIC, MADAM, IF YOU CAN KEEP IT FORREST MCDONALD* ELLEN SHAPIRO MCDONALD** At the close of the Constitutional Convention of 1787, a Mrs. Powell of Philadelphia inquired of Benjamin Franklin, "Well, Doctor, what have we got, a republic or a monarchy?" "A republic," Franklin replied, "if you can keep it."' As was common with Franklin, the observation was more enigmatic than it would at first appear, for Franklin was well aware that there were several varieties of republicanism in America, each of which posited different means of "keeping it." To understand that observation, one must move back in time from 1787 to the eve of independence. The drive for independence had been spearheaded by what would seem to be an unlikely coalition of leaders in New England and the tobacco-growing regions of the upper South.
    [Show full text]
  • The Articles of Confederation and the Constitution
    An Analysis of Two Federal Structures: The Articles of Confederation and the Constitution DOUGLAS G. SMITH" TABLE OF CONTENTS I. IN1RODUCTION • • • . • • • . • • • • . • • • . • • • . • • • • . • • . • • . • 250 JI. EARLY MODELS OF POLITICAL UNION • • . • . • • • . • • • • • . • . • • • 258 A. Montesquieu~ Model: A "Confederate Republic" . • . 260 B. Valle/~ Model: Mutual Defense and Commercial Union . 261 C. Pufendoif~ Model: A "Perpetual Treaty" . • . • . • . 264 Ill. TEX1UAL ANALYSIS: COMPARISON OF TilE CoNSTITUTION AND TilE ARTICLES OF CONFEDERATION • • • • • • . • • • • • . • . • • • • • 268 A. Structural Similarities . • . • . • . • . 270 J. Formation ofa Union . • • . • . • • . • • • . 270 ,2. Reciprocity Among the States . • . • . • . • . 212 3. A General Government of Enumerated Powers . 278 4. Residual Powers Retained by the States . • . • • . • • . • 281 5. Constitutional Protection for the States as Entities . • • . 283 6. Supremacy • . • . • • . • . • . • . • . • • . 284 B. Structural Differences . • . • • . • . • . • . • • • • . • • • . • 285 1. Scope ofEnumerated Powers . • • . • . • • . 285 2. The Sweeping Clause • • . • . • . 288 3. Source of Political Authority . • . • • • • • • . • . • . 291 4. The Guarantee Clause . • . • • • . • . 294 • Associate, Kirkland & Bilis, Chicago, JI. J.D., Northwestern University School of Law; B.S./B.A., State University of New York at Buffalo. I am grateful for comments on previous drafts of this Article from Stephen Gardbaum and Thomas Merrill. 249 5. Amendment • . • . • . • . • 299
    [Show full text]
  • Book Review: Forrest Mcdonald's States' Rights and the Union
    North Alabama Historical Review Volume 1 North Alabama Historical Review, Volume 1, 2011 Article 18 2011 Book Review: Forrest McDonald's States' Rights and the Union John Griffin Follow this and additional works at: https://ir.una.edu/nahr Part of the Public History Commons, and the United States History Commons Recommended Citation Griffin, J. (2011). Book view:Re Forrest McDonald's States' Rights and the Union. North Alabama Historical Review, 1 (1). Retrieved from https://ir.una.edu/nahr/vol1/iss1/18 This Book Review is brought to you for free and open access by UNA Scholarly Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in North Alabama Historical Review by an authorized editor of UNA Scholarly Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Book Reviews 191 Forrest McDonald. States’ Rights and the Union: Imperium in Imperio (Lawrence: University Press of Kansas, 2000). Forrest McDonald, professor emeritus of history at the University of Alabama, writes “Of all the problems that beset the United States of America during the century from the Declaration of Independence to the end of Reconstruction, the most pervasive concerned disagreements about the nature of the Union and the line to be drawn between the authority of the general government and that of the several states,” (vii). Despite the importance of this issue, McDonald knows of no comprehensive survey on this subject, which he hopes to rectify with this work. The key to McDonald’s argument can be found in his subtitle. Roughly translated, imperium in imperio means “sovereignty within sovereignty.” To better understand the battle between state and federal government, McDonald believes one must understand this view of divided sovereignty.
    [Show full text]