Forrest Mcdonald the FAITHFUL and the CRISIS of FAITH

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Forrest Mcdonald the FAITHFUL and the CRISIS of FAITH NO Forrest McDonald THE FAITHFUL AND THE CRISIS OF FAITH By most objective criteria, the Americans of 1800 had abundant cause to be proud, confident, even smug .... And yet a sense of decadence had plagued the land for five years and more. From the pulpit rang c~ies of despair and doom; dishonesty as well as panic had invaded the marketplace; liars and libelers made a travesty of freedom of the press; violence, hysteria, and paranoia infested the public councils. Those Americans who called themselves Federalists felt betrayed by an ungrateful people for whom they had labored long and well, and feared that the horrors of Jacobinism and anarchy were hourly imminent. Those who called themselves Republicans felt betrayed by the twin evils of money and monarchy, and feared that/iberty was about to breathe its last. Many who embraced neither political sect, whether from apathy or disgust, nonetheless shared the general feeling that the nation was in an advanced state of moral rot. What the Federalists thought was actually of little consequence, for they were soon to expire, in what Thomas Jefferson called the Revolution of 1800. Almost miraculously, with their demise--though not because of it--despalr suddenly gave way to euphoria. The new optimism, like the pervasive gloom and the defeat of Federalism that preceded it, stemmed from an interplay of social, religious, ideological, and economic forces and institutions, and from certain ingrained American characteristics. If one would understand the Jeffersonian revolution--how it happened and how it affected the nation’s destiny--one must seek first to understand those forces, institutions, and characteristics. One of the tenets of Republicanism in America was that, contrary to the teachings of Montesqnieu and other theorists, republican government was best adapted to large territories, since in an area as vast as the United States the very diversity of the people would prevent an accumulation of power inimical to liberty. If the principle, was sound, the Americans were truly blessed, for their culture was nothing if not plural. At first blush that 1976). Copyright © 1976 by the University Press of Kansas. Reprinted by perraission, 172 NO Forrest McDonald ! 173 neralization might appear strong, or g~ous views, to the extent that they were indeed entirely unfounded. Overwhelm- fully known, were if anything a political : ingly, Americans were farmers or traders handicap. Rather, it was the compati- of British extraction and the Protestant bility of outlooks that made it possible faith; and’even in politics, as Jefferson for southern and western revivalists si- isaid in his inaugural address, "we are all multaneously to embrace evangelical republicans, we are all federalists." But Arminianism in religion and Republican the mother country itself was scarcely ideology in politics. homogeneous, despite the amalgamation that financial and governmental power Anglo-Americans, like the English them- had brought to Great Britain in the eigh- selves, were by and large nonideological teenth century; it comprised a host of people, but in 18~ the country was di- different Celtic peoples--the Irish, the vided into two fiercely antagonistic ideo- Welsh, the Cornish, and three distinct logical camps. In a loose, general sort of varieties of Scots--as well as Englishmen way and with allowance for a number of ~vho differed from one another from exceptions, it can t~ said that the revival north to south and east to west. Ameri- ideologies derived from contrasting views cans had proved slow to cast off the of the nature of man. The first view, that cultural baggage that they or their ances- associated with the Hamiltonian Federal- tors had brought with them; and a genera- ists, was premised upon the belief that tion of independence, though building man, while capable of noble and even some sense of nationhood, had erased altruistic behavior, could never entirely neither their original ethnic traits nor the escape the influence of his inborn baser intense localism that complemented and ~assions--especially ambition and ava- nourished those traits. As to differences rice, the love of power and the love of in political principles, Jefferson was right mone3a The second, that espoused by the in regarding them as largely superficial; Jeffersonian Republicans, held that man yet they were substantive enough to lead was born with a tabula rasa, with vir- many men to fight, and some to kill, one tually boundless capacity for becoming another .... good or evil, depending upon the whole- It should not be surprising that those someness of the environment in which who were saved through revivalism were he grew, From the premise of the first it also supporters of Jeffersonian Republi- followed that government should recog- canism, for the theology of the one was nize the evil drives of men as individuals, psychologically akin to the ideology of but check them and even harness them the other. In part, to be sure, religious in such a way that they would work for dissenters supported Jefferson because the general good of society as a whole. of his well-known championship of the From the premise of the second it fol- cause of religious liberty. New England lowed that government should work to Baptists, for instance, having fought long rid society of as many evils as possible-- and vainly for disestablishment, virtually including, to a very large extent, the idolized Jefferson. South and west of worst of evils, government itself. The one New England, however, establishment was positive, the other negative; the one had long shnce ceased to be a llve issue, sought to do go~od, the other to eradicate and in much of that area Jefferson’s reli- evil. 174 ! 8. DID PRESIDENT ]~FFERSON OUTFEDERALIZE THE FEDERALISTS? But the ideological division was moreas to dictate another policy. In domestic specifically focused than that. The High affairs, a wide range of implications of FederaliSts believed iv[ and had fash- his system was equally inescapable. ioned a governmental system modeled The Jeffersonian Republicans regarded upon the one that began to emerge in this scheme of things as utterly wicked, England after the Glorious Revolution of even as the English opposition had re- 1688 and was brought to maturity under garded Walpole’s system. Indeed, though the leadership of Sir Robert Walpole dur- the Jeffersonians borrowed some of their ing the 1720s and 1730s. In part the sys- ideas from James Harrington and other tem worked on the basis of what has seventeenth-century writers and some often, simple-wdndedly, been regarded from John Locke, their ideology was bor- as the essence of Hamiltonianism: tying rowed in toto from such Oppositionists the interests of the wealthy to those of as Charles Davenant, John Tr~nchard, the national government, or more accu- Thomas Gordon, James Burgh, ~nd most ratel~ inducing people of all ranks to act espedally Henry St. John, First Viscount in the general interest by making it prof- Bolingbroke. As a well-rounded system, itable for them to do so. But the genius of it is all to be found in the pages of the Hamilton’s system ran much deeper. He Craftsman, an Oppositionist journal that erected a complex set of interrelated in- Bolingbroke published from 1726 to 1737. stitutions, based upon the monetization The Republicans adjusted the ideology of the public debt, which made it vir- to fit the circumstances, to fit the United tually impossible for anyone to pursue States Constitution and the "ministry" power and wealth successfully except of Alexander Hamilton rather than the through the framework of those institu- British constitution and the ministry of tions, and which simultaneously de- Robert Walpole; but that was all, and limited and dictated the possible courses astonishingly little adjustment was nec- of government activity, so that govern- essary: ment had no choice but to function in the The Bolingbroke-Oppositionist cum public interest as Hamilton saw it. For Jeffersonian Republican ideology ran as instance, servicing the public debt, on follows. Corruption was everywhere, it which the whole superstructure rested, was true; but given a proper environ- required a regular source of revenue that ment, that need not be the way of things. was necessarily derived largely from du- Mankind could be rejuvenated through ties on imports from Great Britain. For education and self-discipline, but that that reason the United States could not was possible only in the context of a life go to war with Britain except at the risk style that exalted living on, owning, and of national bankruptc3~ but could figh~ working the land. Only the land could Revolutionary France or France’s ally give people the independence and un- Spain, which were owners of territories hurried existence that were prerequisite that the United States avidly desired. to self-improvement. ’ Hamilton regarded this as the proper In some Edenic past, "the people"-- American foreign polic3~ at least for a which both Bolingbroke dnd Jefferson time; and should circumstances change, understood to mean the gentry and the he was perfectly capable of redefining solid yeomanry, and not to include aris- the rules and rerigging the institutions so tocrats, money jobbers, priests, or the NO Forrest McDonald I 175 scum in the cities--had enjoyed the for gambling, stock-jobbing, and paper proper atmosphere, and therefore had shuffling permeated the highest councils been happy. Relationships were based of state and spread among the people upon agriculture and its "handmaiden" themselves. Maniy virtue gave way to commerce/ upon ownership of land, effeminacy and vice; public spirit suc- honest labor in the earth, craftsmanship cumbed to extravagance, venality and in the cities, and free trade between indi- corruption. viduals. All men revered God, respected Jefferson never tired of telling a story their fellows, deferred to their betters, which, to him, epitomized what had gone and knew their place.
Recommended publications
  • Not Another Constitutional Law Course: a Proposal to Teach a Course on the Constitution
    Florida International University College of Law eCollections Faculty Publications Faculty Scholarship 1991 Not Another Constitutional Law Course: A Proposal to Teach a Course on the Constitution Thomas E. Baker Florida International University College of Law Follow this and additional works at: https://ecollections.law.fiu.edu/faculty_publications Part of the Constitutional Law Commons, and the Legal Education Commons Recommended Citation Thomas E. Baker, Not Another Constitutional Law Course: A Proposal to Teach a Course on the Constitution , 76 Iowa L. Rev. 739 (1991). Available at: https://ecollections.law.fiu.edu/faculty_publications/173 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Faculty Scholarship at eCollections. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Publications by an authorized administrator of eCollections. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Not Another Constitutional Law Course: A Proposal to Teach a Course on the Constitutiont Thomas E. Baker* and James E. Viator** Justice Douglas once railed against law review writing in which "the views presented are those of special pleaders who fail to disclose that they are not scholars but rather people with axes to grind."l Not so here. Authors ofcourse materials, even casebook authors, package their biases in subtle but effective ways, through their selection, organization, and empha­ sis of materials. By this essay, which is based on the preface to our multilithed course materials, we mean to disclose our own biases to our students and readers. This is the basic question we consider at the outset: How is a course on the.Constitution different from a'course on constitutional law? Our course, "The Framers' Constitution," is about the history and theory of the t ©1991 Thomas E.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Commander-In-Chief Power
    Georgetown University Law Center Scholarship @ GEORGETOWN LAW 2008 On the Commander-In-Chief Power David Luban Georgetown University Law Center, [email protected] Georgetown Public Law and Legal Theory Research Paper No. 1026302 This paper can be downloaded free of charge from: https://scholarship.law.georgetown.edu/facpub/598 http://ssrn.com/abstract=1026302 81 S. Cal. L. Rev. 477-571 (2008) This open-access article is brought to you by the Georgetown Law Library. Posted with permission of the author. Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.georgetown.edu/facpub Part of the Constitutional Law Commons ON THE COMMANDER IN CHIEF POWER ∗ DAVID LUBAN BRADBURY: Obviously, the Hamdan decision, Senator, does implicitly recognize that we’re in a war, that the President’s war powers were triggered by the attacks on the country, and that [the] law of war paradigm applies. That’s what the whole case was about. LEAHY: Was the President right or was he wrong? BRADBURY: It’s under the law of war that we . LEAHY: Was the President right or was he wrong? BRADBURY: . hold the President is always right, Senator. —exchange between a U.S. Senator and a Justice Department 1 lawyer ∗ University Professor and Professor of Law and Philosophy, Georgetown University. I owe thanks to John Partridge and Sebastian Kaplan-Sears for excellent research assistance; to Greg Reichberg, Bill Mengel, and Tim Sellers for clarifying several points of American, Roman, and military history; to Marty Lederman for innumerable helpful and critical conversations; and to Vicki Jackson, Paul Kahn, Larry Solum, and Amy Sepinwall for helpful comments on an earlier draft.
    [Show full text]
  • Charles Beard Versus the Founding
    W7 l91 6 CHARLES BEARD VERSUS THE FOUNDING FATHERS: PROPERTY CONCEPTS IN THE EIGHTEENTH CENTURY THESIS Presented to the Graduate Council of the University of North Texas in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements For the Degree of MASTER OF ARTS By Rhonda J. Breaux, B.A. Denton, Texas May, 1992 Breaux, Rhonda J., Charles Beard versus the Founding Fathers: Property Concepts in the Eighteenth Centuy Master of Arts (History), August, 1992, 134 pp., 36 titles. This thesis deals with the role of property in the formation of the American Constitution and government. Charles Beard's views on property are compared with writings from the eighteenth century. Beard's writings on property and his critics are examined in the first two chapters. Then, the thesis's two historical contexts are evaluated. Concentrating on the Enclosure Acts, the fourth chapter looks at the importance of land to the former Englishmen. The eighteenth century view of property is the focus of the fifth section. The last chapter contrasts the two different views of property. Beard believed that the Constitution was a conservative document that protected the property of the few over the many. The Founding Fathers actually included liberal protections for property in the eighteenth century. TABLE OF CONTENTS Page Chapter I. CHARLES BEARD'S VIEWS ON PROPERTY: REALTY VERSUS PERSONALTY ........................ 1 II. CRITICS OF CHARLES BEARD: ROBERT E. BROWN, FORREST MCDONALD, AND RICHARD HOFSTADTER....---------- ................ 23 III. THE TWO HISTORICAL CONTEXTS..... ................. 33 IV. THE IMPORTANCE OF LAND: AN ANALYSIS OF THE ENGLISH ENCLOSURE ACTS.--................54 V. EIGHTEENTH CENTURY VIEWS OF PROPERTY..............76 VI.
    [Show full text]
  • William Robertson Coe Professor of History and American Studies Professor of Political Science and (By Courtesy) of Law Stanford University Stanford CA 94305-2024
    JACK N. RAKOVE William Robertson Coe Professor of History and American Studies Professor of Political Science and (by courtesy) of Law Stanford University Stanford CA 94305-2024 Office: Lane History Corner 117 (650) 723-4514, fax 725-0597 [email protected] EDUCATION: 1969-75 Harvard University; Ph.D. in History 1966-67 University of Edinburgh, Scotland 1964-68 Haverford College; A.B. with Honors in History EMPLOYMENT: 1980- Department of History, Stanford University; Assistant Professor 1980-82; Associate Professor 1982-90; Professor, 1990; William Robertson Coe Professor of History and American Studies, 1996-; Professor of Political Science 1996- ; Professor of Law (by courtesy), spring 1999, spring 2003, 2005- 1975-82 Department of History, Colgate University; Instructor, 1975-76; Assistant Professor 1976-80; Associate Professor with tenure 1980-82 (on leave) fall 2003 Visiting Professor, New York University School of Law spring 2011 Visiting Professor, Tel Aviv University School of Law AWARDS AND FELLOWSHIPS: Member, American Philosophical Society, 2007 Fellow, Center for Advanced Study in the Behavioral Sciences, 2006-2007 Doctor of Humane Letters, Barat College, 2002 President, Society for the History of the Early American Republic, 2002-2003 Member, American Antiquarian Society, 2000 Member, American Academy of Arts and Sciences, 1999 Society of the Cincinnati Book Prize, 1998 Pulitzer Prize in History, 1997 Fraunces Tavern Museum Book Award, 1997 Stanford Humanities Center, Faculty Fellowship, 1988-89, 2000-2001 National Endowment for the Humanities, Constitutional Fellowship, 1984-85 National Endowment for the Humanities, Summer Seminar Instructor, 1984 (College Teachers), 1987 (Law Professors) Project '87, research fellowship, 1982 National Endowment for the Humanities, Summer Stipend, 1977 Delancey K.
    [Show full text]
  • Russell Kirk and the Rhetoric of Order Eric Grabowsky
    Duquesne University Duquesne Scholarship Collection Electronic Theses and Dissertations Summer 2010 Russell Kirk and the Rhetoric of Order Eric Grabowsky Follow this and additional works at: https://dsc.duq.edu/etd Recommended Citation Grabowsky, E. (2010). Russell Kirk and the Rhetoric of Order (Doctoral dissertation, Duquesne University). Retrieved from https://dsc.duq.edu/etd/595 This Immediate Access is brought to you for free and open access by Duquesne Scholarship Collection. It has been accepted for inclusion in Electronic Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Duquesne Scholarship Collection. For more information, please contact [email protected]. RUSSELL KIRK AND THE RHETORIC OF ORDER A Dissertation Submitted to the McAnulty College and Graduate School of Liberal Arts Duquesne University In partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy By Eric Grabowsky August 2010 Copyright by Eric Grabowsky 2010 RUSSELL KIRK AND THE RHETORIC OF ORDER By Eric Grabowsky Approved July 9, 2010 ________________________________ ________________________________ Dr. Janie M. Harden Fritz Dr. Calvin Troup Associate Professor, Department of Associate Professor, Department of Communication & Rhetorical Studies Communication & Rhetorical Studies (Dissertation Director) (First Reader) ________________________________ ________________________________ Dr. Richard Thames Dr. Ronald C. Arnett, Chair Associate Professor, Department of Department of Communication & Communication & Rhetorical Studies Rhetorical Studies (Second Reader) ________________________________ Dr. Christopher M. Duncan, Dean McAnulty College and Graduate School of Liberal Arts iii ABSTRACT RUSSELL KIRK AND THE RHETORIC OF ORDER By Eric Grabowsky August 2010 Dissertation supervised by Dr. Janie M. Harden Fritz The corpus of historically-minded “man of letters” and twentieth century leader among conservatives, Russell Amos Kirk, prompts one to reflect upon a realist rhetoric of order for conservative discourse in particular and public argumentation in general.
    [Show full text]
  • RIP FORREST Mcdonald
    H-Law R.I.P. FORREST McDONALD (1927-2016) Discussion published by R. B. Bernstein on Monday, January 25, 2016 The prolific and controversial constitutional historian Forrest McDonald died of heart failure on 18 January 2016 in Tuscaloosa, Ala. He was 89. Born on 7 January 1927 in Orange, Texas, he was educated at the University of Texas, where he received his doctorate in 1955. Having taught at Brown (1959-1967) and Wayne State (1967-1976) Universities, he was best known as a faculty member at the University of Alabama, where he taught from 1976 until his retirement in 2002. His first book was his dissertation, LET THERE BE LIGHT: THE ELECTRIC UTILITY INDUSTRY IN WISCONSIN (Madison: American History Research Center, 1957). He followed that book with a biography of the controversial business magnate Samuel Insull (University of Chicago Press, 1962). But his second book, WE THE PEOPLE: THE ECONOMIC ORIGINS OF THE CONSTITUTION (University of Chicago Press, 1958), signaled a major shift in his research interests and scholarly priorities away from business and economic history. In that book, which became the first of a trilogy, he re-examined the findings of Charles A. Beard’s landmark 1913 study, AN ECONOMIC INTERPRETATION OF THE CONSTITUTION OF THE UNITED STATES, and refuted Beard’s thesis that holders of personalty influenced the making of the Constitution to protect their financial interests in that property; at the same time, McDonald showed the effects of three dozen kinds of financial interests on the making of the document. McDonald followed up WE THE PEOPLE with his 1965 study E PLURIBUS UNUM: THE FORMATION OF THE AMERICAN REPUBLIC (new edition, 1979, Liberty Fund), a narrative history that focused on the sectional and other political forces that shaped the creation of the Cosntitution and the government it authorized.
    [Show full text]
  • Download Download
    Book Reviews 91 Political Ideas of the American Revolution: Britannic-American Con- tributions to the Problem of Imperial Organization, 1765-1775. Third edition. By Randolph G. Adams. Commentary by Merrill Jensen. (New York: Barnes & Noble, Inc., 1958. Pp. vii, 216. Frontispiece, bibliographical notes, index. Paperbound, $1.60.) According to the late Randolph G. Adams, from 1763 to 1775 the American colonies contested British policy with constitutional arguments which, despite their diversity, were essentially a demand for definition of colonial status vis-h-vis Great Britain. Behind the verbal fencing of shifting American arguments was a consistent plea for self-government, but self-government within the Empire. England’s failure to solve the imperial problem raised by colonial opposition ended in the loss of her American colonies. By presenting the major contentions of representative thinkers such as John Adams, James Wilson, and Thomas Paine, the author endeavors to show that during pre-Revolutionary debate there began to emerge the concept of government as an instrument of society answerable to law as well as the concept of divided authority or federalism. These principles, Adams believes, are America’s contribu- tion to political thought, which form the basis of the American system of government and which also provide the root ideas for both the League of Nations and the British Commonwealth. Adams has acutely analyzed the constitutional controversy prior to the Revolution, but as S. E. Morison has noted (English Historical Review, XXXVIII [January, 19231, 115), he does not place political theory as sharply in its framework of historical fact as he might have.
    [Show full text]
  • Wed., May 6, 1987 Full Text May Not Be Reprinted Without the Author's Permission
    EMBARGOED: For release after 8:00 p.m. (EDT), Wed., May 6, 1987 Full text may not be reprinted without the author's permission. 16th Jefferson Lecture in the Humanities THE INTELLECTUAL WORLD OF THE FOUNDING FATHERS by Forrest McDonald It has been suggested by various intellectuals that the best thing Americans could do to commemorate the 200th anniversary of our Constitution would be to rewrite it to reflect the realities of the twentieth century. It has been suggested by various jurists that the Supreme Court is, and should be, doing just that. The assumption underlying both notions is that our pool of knowledge and understanding about human nature and political institutions is far more sophisticated than any that could have been available in the simple frontier society of eighteenth-century America. That assumption is as presumptuous as it is uninformed. To put it bluntly, it would be impossible in America today to assemble a group of people with anything near the combined experience, learning, and wisdom that the fifty-five authors of the Constitution took with them to Philadelphia in the summer of 1787. As an appetizer, I offer a couple of corroborative tidbits. Thirty-five of the delegates had attended college. Just to enter college during the eighteenth century — which students normally did at the age of fourteen or fifteen — it was necessary, among other things, to be able to read and translate from the original Latin into English (I quote from the requirements at King's College — now Columbia — which were typical) "the first three
    [Show full text]
  • A Republic, Madam, If You Can Keep It Forrest Mcdonald
    Notre Dame Journal of Law, Ethics & Public Policy Volume 4 Article 3 Issue 1 Symposium on Civic Virtue 1-1-2012 A Republic, Madam, If You Can Keep It Forrest McDonald Ellen Shapiro McDonald Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarship.law.nd.edu/ndjlepp Recommended Citation Forrest McDonald & E. Shapiro McDonald, A Republic, Madam, If You Can Keep It, 4 Notre Dame J.L. Ethics & Pub. Pol'y 7 (1990). Available at: http://scholarship.law.nd.edu/ndjlepp/vol4/iss1/3 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Notre Dame Journal of Law, Ethics & Public Policy at NDLScholarship. It has been accepted for inclusion in Notre Dame Journal of Law, Ethics & Public Policy by an authorized administrator of NDLScholarship. For more information, please contact [email protected]. ARTICLES A REPUBLIC, MADAM, IF YOU CAN KEEP IT FORREST MCDONALD* ELLEN SHAPIRO MCDONALD** At the close of the Constitutional Convention of 1787, a Mrs. Powell of Philadelphia inquired of Benjamin Franklin, "Well, Doctor, what have we got, a republic or a monarchy?" "A republic," Franklin replied, "if you can keep it."' As was common with Franklin, the observation was more enigmatic than it would at first appear, for Franklin was well aware that there were several varieties of republicanism in America, each of which posited different means of "keeping it." To understand that observation, one must move back in time from 1787 to the eve of independence. The drive for independence had been spearheaded by what would seem to be an unlikely coalition of leaders in New England and the tobacco-growing regions of the upper South.
    [Show full text]
  • The Articles of Confederation and the Constitution
    An Analysis of Two Federal Structures: The Articles of Confederation and the Constitution DOUGLAS G. SMITH" TABLE OF CONTENTS I. IN1RODUCTION • • • . • • • . • • • • . • • • . • • • . • • • • . • • . • • . • 250 JI. EARLY MODELS OF POLITICAL UNION • • . • . • • • . • • • • • . • . • • • 258 A. Montesquieu~ Model: A "Confederate Republic" . • . 260 B. Valle/~ Model: Mutual Defense and Commercial Union . 261 C. Pufendoif~ Model: A "Perpetual Treaty" . • . • . • . 264 Ill. TEX1UAL ANALYSIS: COMPARISON OF TilE CoNSTITUTION AND TilE ARTICLES OF CONFEDERATION • • • • • • . • • • • • . • . • • • • • 268 A. Structural Similarities . • . • . • . • . 270 J. Formation ofa Union . • • . • . • • . • • • . 270 ,2. Reciprocity Among the States . • . • . • . • . 212 3. A General Government of Enumerated Powers . 278 4. Residual Powers Retained by the States . • . • • . • • . • 281 5. Constitutional Protection for the States as Entities . • • . 283 6. Supremacy • . • . • • . • . • . • . • . • • . 284 B. Structural Differences . • . • • . • . • . • . • • • • . • • • . • 285 1. Scope ofEnumerated Powers . • • . • . • • . 285 2. The Sweeping Clause • • . • . • . 288 3. Source of Political Authority . • . • • • • • • . • . • . 291 4. The Guarantee Clause . • . • • • . • . 294 • Associate, Kirkland & Bilis, Chicago, JI. J.D., Northwestern University School of Law; B.S./B.A., State University of New York at Buffalo. I am grateful for comments on previous drafts of this Article from Stephen Gardbaum and Thomas Merrill. 249 5. Amendment • . • . • . • . • 299
    [Show full text]
  • Book Review: Forrest Mcdonald's States' Rights and the Union
    North Alabama Historical Review Volume 1 North Alabama Historical Review, Volume 1, 2011 Article 18 2011 Book Review: Forrest McDonald's States' Rights and the Union John Griffin Follow this and additional works at: https://ir.una.edu/nahr Part of the Public History Commons, and the United States History Commons Recommended Citation Griffin, J. (2011). Book view:Re Forrest McDonald's States' Rights and the Union. North Alabama Historical Review, 1 (1). Retrieved from https://ir.una.edu/nahr/vol1/iss1/18 This Book Review is brought to you for free and open access by UNA Scholarly Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in North Alabama Historical Review by an authorized editor of UNA Scholarly Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Book Reviews 191 Forrest McDonald. States’ Rights and the Union: Imperium in Imperio (Lawrence: University Press of Kansas, 2000). Forrest McDonald, professor emeritus of history at the University of Alabama, writes “Of all the problems that beset the United States of America during the century from the Declaration of Independence to the end of Reconstruction, the most pervasive concerned disagreements about the nature of the Union and the line to be drawn between the authority of the general government and that of the several states,” (vii). Despite the importance of this issue, McDonald knows of no comprehensive survey on this subject, which he hopes to rectify with this work. The key to McDonald’s argument can be found in his subtitle. Roughly translated, imperium in imperio means “sovereignty within sovereignty.” To better understand the battle between state and federal government, McDonald believes one must understand this view of divided sovereignty.
    [Show full text]
  • Alexander Hamilton's Philosophy of Government and Administration Author(S): John C
    Alexander Hamilton's Philosophy of Government and Administration Author(s): John C. Koritansky Source: Publius, Vol. 9, No. 2, Republicanism, Representation, and Consent: Views of the Founding Era, (Spring, 1979), pp. 99-122 Published by: Oxford University Press Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/3329736 Accessed: 01/07/2008 14:51 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=oup. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit organization founded in 1995 to build trusted digital archives for scholarship. We work with the scholarly community to preserve their work and the materials they rely upon, and to build a common research platform that promotes the discovery and use of these resources. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. http://www.jstor.org Alexander Hamilton's Philosophy of Government and Administration John C. Koritansky Hiram College When Thomas Jefferson called Alexander Hamilton the "col- losus of the Federalists"' he was recognizing the fact that Hamilton was the member of his party who articulated the com- prehensive vision of republican national government and com- mercial society that the Federalists labored to establish.
    [Show full text]