The Moral Significance of Empathy
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
Load more
Recommended publications
-
Exploring the Applications of Second-Generation Mindfulness-Based Interventions For
Exploring the Applications of Second-Generation Mindfulness-Based Interventions for Improving Health and Human Functioning: A Mixed-Methods Investigation William Van Gordon, BSc, MSc Psychology Department, Nottingham Trent University, Nottinghamshire, UK, NG1 4BU A thesis submitted in partial fulfilment of the requirements of Nottingham Trent University for the degree of Doctorate of Psychology December 2017 1 © William Van Gordon, 2017 This work is the intellectual property of the author. You may copy up to 5% of this work for private study, or personal non-commercial research. Any re-use of the information contained within this document should be fully referenced, quoting the author, title, university, degree level, and pagination. Queries or requests for any other use, or if a more substantial copy is required, should be directed to the owner of the Intellectual Property Rights. Recommended citation: Van Gordon, W. (2017). Exploring the Applications of Second-Generation Mindfulness-Based Interventions for Improving Health and Human Functioning: A Mixed-Methods Investigation [PhD Thesis]. Nottingham: Nottingham Trent University. Keywords: Mindfulness, Second-Generation Mindfulness-based Interventions, Meditation, Meditation Awareness Training, Buddhist-Derived Interventions, Mindfulness-Based Interventions, Emptiness, Ontological Addiction, Buddhism, Workaholism, Work Addiction, Sex Addiction, Fibromyalgia, Psychopathology, Job Performance, Civic Engagement, Stress, Anxiety, Randomised Controlled Trial Aspects of this doctoral project -
Empathy, Attitudes, and Action
10.1177/014616702237647 PERSONALITY AND SOCIAL PSYCHOLOGY BULLETIN Batson et al. / EMPATHY, ATTITUDES, AND ACTION Empathy, Attitudes, and Action: Can Feeling for a Member of a Stigmatized Group Motivate One to Help the Group? C. Daniel Batson Johee Chang Ryan Orr Jennifer Rowland University of Kansas Research reveals that inducing empathy for a member of a stig- This empathy-attitude effect seems remarkably matized group can improve attitudes toward the group as a robust. Empathy has improved attitudes even when the whole. But do these more positive attitudes translate into action individual for whom empathy was induced was not on behalf of the group? Results of an experiment suggested an prototypical of the group and was not responsible for his affirmative answer to this question. Undergraduates first lis- or her plight (Batson et al., 1997). Extremely negative tened to an interview with a convicted heroin addict and dealer; attitudes have been affected despite apparent attempts they were then given a chance to recommend allocation of Stu- to resist the effect. For example, attitudes toward con- dent Senate funds to an agency to help drug addicts. (The victed murderers serving life without parole were not sig- agency would not help the addict whose interview they heard.) nificantly improved immediately after the empathy Participants induced to feel empathy for the addict allocated induction but were significantly improved several weeks more funds to the agency. Replicating past results, these partici- later when assessed through an unrelated telephone sur- pants also reported more positive attitudes toward people vey (Batson et al., 1997, Experiment 3). -
Buddhism and Non-Violent World: Examining a Buddhist Contribution to Promoting the Principle of Non-Violence and a Culture of Peace
Volume 8 Number 2 (2014): 122-149 http://www.infactispax.org/journal Buddhism and Non-Violent World: Examining a Buddhist Contribution to Promoting the Principle of Non-Violence and a Culture of Peace Juichiro Tanabe Coventry University [email protected] Introduction This paper examines a Buddhist contribution to promoting the principle of non-violence and culture of peace. The opposition to violence has been one of the cardinal principles of Buddhism, which is stated in the Dhamapada1: “All tremble at violence; all fear death. Seeing others as being like yourself, do not kill or cause others to kill. All tremble at violence; life is dear for all. Seeing others as being like yourself, do not kill or cause others to kill.”2 Further, Buddhism since its beginning has developed the analysis of psychologically-oriented suffering including violence by means of eradication of its cause and achievement of internal serenity3 and this paper 1 Dhamapada is a collection of sayings of the Buddha. 2 Fronsdal, G. (2005). The Dhammapada: A New Translation of the Buddhist Classic with Annotations. Boston: Shambala: 35. 3 Burton, D. (2002). Knowledge and Liberation: Philosophical Ruminations on a Buddhist Conundrum. 122 In Factis Pax Volume 8 Number 2 (2014): 122-146 http://www.infactispax.org/journal explores how the Buddhist analysis of human mind deepens the psychological dynamics of violence and unfolds internal dimension of peace for more humane world. To this end, three sections constitute this paper. The first section expounds the Four Noble Truths doctrine that is the core of Buddhist teaching. Based on the analysis, the second section examines a Buddhist view of dynamics of violence. -
How Social an Animal? the Human Capacity for Caring
How Social an Animal? The Human Capacity for Caring C. Daniel Batson University of Kansas I I II I ABSTRACT." We live in a social arena. Yet, in our inter- simply complex objects in our environment--important actions with others do we ever really care about them, or sources of stimulation and gratification, of facilitation and is the real target of our concern always, exclusively our- inhibition--as we each pursue self-interest. We care for selves? For many years psychology, including social psy- them only insofar as their welfare affects ours. chology, has assumed that we are social egoists, caring Perhaps the clearest way to phrase the question I am exclusivelyfor ourselves. Today, the computer analogy that raising is by borrowing Milton Rokeach's (1973) distinc- underlies so much thinking in cognitive and social psy- tion between terminal and instrumental values. Each of chology overlooks the fact that we care altogether. Recent us values at least some other people. But do we value evidence in support of the empathy-altruism hypothesis these others for their own sakeaa terminal value--or for suggests a very different view. It suggests that not only do ours--an instrumental value? This is what it means to we care but also that when we feel empathy for others in ask how social we really are. need, we are capable of caring for them for their sakes and not our own. Limits on the human capacity for al- Psychology's Explicit Response: truistic caring are discussed. Discreet Silence Psychology, especially in recent years, has shied away from directly confronting this rather fundamental question about human nature. -
For Hecuba Or for Hamlet: Rethinking Emotion and Empathy in the Theatre
Spring 2011 71 For Hecuba or for Hamlet: Rethinking Emotion and Empathy in the Theatre Amy Cook It is true that I am a proselytizer for the work being done at the intersection of the cognitive sciences and the humanities; I can be found on college campuses shaking a copy of The Way We Think (2002) or How the Body Shapes the Mind (2006) and spreading the good word about the importance of deploying research from across the cognitive sciences to previously held beliefs about language and bodies onstage. My aims are not small and my opinions are not meek. There are questions about the great impact that language and performance has on an audience to which I still do not have the answer and yet find more exciting given research in the cognitive sciences. This essay, however, will not be a manifesto, nor will it present clear answers or bold claims. Working in an intersection requires a degree of caution. I know better than to let that metaphor go unquestioned: interdisciplinary inquiry need not be work and it need not be perilous. If, instead, I describe my project here as playing on the beachfront of theatre and performance studies, watching how the waves of research from the cognitive sciences come in and alter the shoreline, I may open up the field of play, rather than advancing an argument for a kind of work. This is not to suggest that the scholarship is lazy and noncommittal, rather that what I seek to do here is imagine the kinds of sandcastles that could be made on this beach here and now. -
POSITIVE PSYCHOLOGY MODULE No.27: EMPATHY and ALTRUISM
Web links http://portal.idc.ac.il/en/symposium/herzliyasymposium/documents/dcbatson.pdf http://static.squarespace.com/static/523f28fce4b0f99c83f055f2/t/52821931e4b096cf32d7d70 0/1384257841292/Emotion2008VanLange.pdf http://www.psychologytoday.com/basics/empathy https://www.boundless.com/psychology/social-psychology/positive-and-negative-social- behaviors/altruism-helping/ http://education-portal.com/academy/lesson/altruism-and-prosocial-behavior-definition- predictors.html#lesson http://ericboonesarchi.sourceforge.net/Archive/Empathy-Altruism%20Hypothesis.pdf Suggested Readings Batson, C.D. (2009). "These things called empathy: eight related but distinct phenomena". In J. Decety & W. Ickes (Eds.). The Social Neuroscience of Empathy (pp. 3–15). Cambridge: MIT press. Batson, C.D. Empathy Induced Altruistic Motivation, Draft of lecture/chapter for Inaugural Herzliya Symposium on “Prosocial Motives,Emotions, and Behavior,” March 24-27, 2008. Batson, C.D. van Lange, P. Ahmad, N. Lishner, D.A.(2003). “Altruism and Helping Behavior”. The SAGE Handbook of Social Psychology. New Delhi: SAGE Publications. Batson, C. (1997). Five Studies Testing Two New Egoistic Alternatives to the Empathy- Altruism Hypothesis. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology. Vol. 55. Batson, C. D. (1991). The altruism question: Toward a social- psychological answer. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum, Inc. Batson, C. D. (1997). Self-other merging and the empathy-altruismhy- pothesis: Reply to Neuberg et al. (1997). Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 73, 517–522. Batson, C. D. (1998). Altruism and prosocial behavior. In Gilbert, D. T., Fiske, S. T., & Lindzey, G. (Eds.), The handbook of social psychology (pp. 282–316). New York: McGraw- Hill. PSYCHOLOGY PAPER No.9: POSITIVE PSYCHOLOGY MODULE No.27: EMPATHY AND ALTRUISM Batson, C. -
Batson Reference for News of Difference
Batson Reference For News Of Difference shiftilyTull is pipyenough, and foreseeis Hersch disconsolately vanished? Infected while populated and veriest Adrick Alf stewards, obturated but and Barton states. nocturnally When Hersh pinnacled concretized her tamponades. his headwaiter swallows not Different kinds of which they serve as part Beginning once an idea provided the basic unit of mental process Bateson defines an society as A difference or distinction or dream of differences adding that more. Probing free carrier plasmons in doped semiconductors using. Helping Behavior IResearchNet. Their lifeworld situation and facilitating interpersonal reactivity index of the seven to be killed by the daughter and relations board could be used in earlier help explain what symptoms of batson reference difference of law. US Supremes Back spent on Batson Issue of Attorney General. Lexemes' reference to my distinct emotion mostly termed being moved starting with. As mentioned there is wide very clear video game reference in Shazam. Understand the differences between altruism and helping and rehearse how social psychologists try to differentiate the two love the roles of reciprocity and. Leave it up to nominate A prime of moral actions and why never lie. Pg 171- Psicothema. How different inputs is for differences in specific area of reference are, unpleasant pictures of. Empathy-related Responding Associations with Prosocial. We cancelled one year, batson for of reference difference also learn how they believe in retrospect a class develops it carefully avoids them? This is certainly a useful term to understand differences and make progress. Spencer never needing help. Potentiating empathic concern for references in interpersonal engagement areassociated with flyer no doubt felt rather, batson also states that difference factors and. -
The Aesthetics of Redemption in Fin De Siècle Literature and the Arts
The Aesthetics of Redemption in fin de siècle Literature and the Arts by Katherine Lynn Fry A thesis submitted in conformity with the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Centre for Comparative Literature University of Toronto © Copyright by Katherine Lynn Fry 2017 The Aesthetics of Redemption in fin de siècle Literature and the Arts Katherine Lynn Fry Doctor of Philosophy Centre for Comparative Literature University of Toronto 2017 Abstract This dissertation explores a cluster of texts in fin de siècle aestheticism from a Nietzschean perspective, questioning whether their claims about art and life are, at bottom, world-affirming or world-denying. I argue that the aesthetic worldviews of Friedrich Nietzsche, Walter Pater and Oscar Wilde manifest a struggle against Christian (especially Protestant) values, a struggle that, however, periodically and sometimes fatally capitulates to the otherworldliness it seeks to overcome. Chapter 1 delineates the theoretical framework for my investigation. Drawing on the work of Nietzsche and Max Weber, I begin by examining the diverse strains of otherworldliness, some more implicit than others, that run through the aesthetic theories of Arthur Schopenhauer, Richard Wagner, Joris-Karl Huysmans, and Charles Baudelaire. In Chapter 2, I consider the evolution of Nietzsche’s own aesthetic philosophy from his youthful embrace of the Wagnerian Gesamtkunstwerk to his mature view that the Dionysian artist exemplifies the individual who has vanquished all decadent urges to be redeemed from worldly suffering, and is thus able to affirm life through his work. Chapter 3 demonstrates how Pater’s contemplative aestheticism, which originally sets out to counteract the antipathy to the ‘here and now’ associated with ascetic Protestantism, ends up reproducing the hierarchy between the ii temporal world and a more desirable ‘otherworld.’ In the fourth and final chapter, I suggest that Wilde overcomes the otherworldliness of Paterian aestheticism but only by advancing a secularized version of aesthetic incarnation. -
Suffering-Focused Ethics
Suffering-Focused Ethics Defense and Implications Magnus Vinding Ratio Ethica Ratio Ethica, Copenhagen. Copyright © 2020 Magnus Vinding Parts of this book have previously been published elsewhere by the author. ISBN: 9798624910911 Contents Introduction .............................................. 1 Part I: The Case for Suffering-Focused Ethics 1: Asymmetries Between Happiness and Suffering ................ 13 2: Happiness as the Absence of Suffering ....................... 39 3: Creating Happiness at the Price of Suffering Is Wrong ........... 52 4: The Principle of Sympathy for Intense Suffering ................ 60 5: A Moral Realist Case for Minimizing Extreme Suffering ......... 75 6: Other Arguments for Focusing on Suffering ................... 93 7: Biases Against Focusing on Suffering ....................... 111 8: Objections Against Focusing on Suffering ................... 141 Part II: How Can We Best Reduce Suffering? 9: Uncertainty Is Big ..................................... 185 10: We Should Be Cooperative .............................. 205 11: Non-Human Animals and Expansion of the Moral Circle . 214 12: Promoting Concern for Suffering ......................... 228 13: The Abolitionist Project ................................ 239 14: Reducing S-Risks ..................................... 247 15: Donating to Reduce Suffering ........................... 256 16: Researching the Question ............................... 261 17: The Importance of Self-Investment ....................... 266 18: What You Can Do ................................... -
Four Motives for Community Involvement ∗ C
Journal of Social Issues, Vol. 58, No. 3, 2002, pp. 429--445 Four Motives for Community Involvement ∗ C. Daniel Batson and Nadia Ahmad University of Kansas Jo-Ann Tsang Southern Methodist University A conceptual analysis is offered that differentiates four types of motivation for community involvement: egoism, altruism, collectivism, and principlism. Differentiation is based on identification of a unique ultimate goal for each motive. For egoism, the ultimate goal is to increase one’s own welfare; for al- truism, it is to increase the welfare of another individual or individuals; for col- lectivism, to increase the welfare of a group; and for principlism, to uphold one or more moral principles. As sources of community involvement, each of these four forms of motivation has its strengths; each also has its weaknesses. More effective efforts to stimulate community involvement may come from strategies that orchestrate motives so that the strengths of one motive can overcome weak- nesses of another. Among the various possibilities, strategies that combine ap- peals to either altruism or collectivism with appeals to principle may be especially promising. In The Prince, Machiavelli (1513/1908) imagined himself offering counsel to a public official who wished to provide the best life for his people. The worldly wisdom that Machiavelli provided has stood the test of time. We have no illusions that we can give advice that is as wise or enduring, but we borrowed Machiavelli’s literary device and tried to imagine ourselves in a similar situation. A local civic leader—the mayor, let us say—comes to us for help. -
Selfhood and the Metaphysics of Altruism
Selfhood and the Metaphysics of Altruism A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED TO THE GRADUATE DIVISION OF THE UNIVERSITY OF HAWAI¢I AT MĀNOA IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY IN PHILOSOPHY MAY 2017 By Kevin Perry Maroufkhani Dissertation Committee: Arindam Chakrabarti, Chairperson Ron Bontekoe George Tsai Peter Hershock Sai Bhatawadekar ACKNOWLEDGMENTS I am indebted to my family, particularly, Rosanne Perry, Dariush Maroufkhani, and Roya Dennis for their moral support and stubborn belief that I could accomplish this project despite all the obstacles I created for myself. I would like to acknowledge my chair, Dr. Arindam Chakrabarti, for the breadth and vivacity of his philosophical imagination, which has continued to challenge me, and nudge me out of complacency and inevitable philosophical naps. His analytical rigor, teaching-presence, and facility in world philosophy is a testament to what is possible in the field of global philosophical discourse. I am grateful for the many hours of selfless instruction he provided, and the fertile ideas cultivated in his classrooms. I would like to acknowledge Dr. Ron Bontekoe, who has always challenged me in the true spirit of a philosophical friend. Dr. Bontekoe has been a careful and caring academic advisor, and, in the courses I’ve taken with him, has never let me off the hook. He does not mince words, and because of the background depth he has provided in hermeneutics, biology, and theoretical ethics, he has greatly benefited this project. I would like to acknowledge Dr. Peter Hershock, who continually reminds me that a hermeneutical lens can make or break the credibility, rigor and sensitivity of cross-cultural conversation. -
Is Empathic Emotion a Source of Altruistic Motivation?
journal of Personality and Social Psychology Copyright 1981 by the American Psychological Association, Inc. 1981, Vol. 40, No. 2, 290-302 0022-3514/81 /4002-0290S00.75 Is Empathic Emotion a Source of Altruistic Motivation? C. Daniel Batson, Bruce D. Duncan, Paula Ackerman, Terese Buckley, and Kimberly Birch University of Kansas It has been suggested that empathy leads to altruistic rather than egoistic mo- tivation to help. This hypothesis was tested by having subjects watch another female undergraduate receive electric shocks and then giving them a chance to help her by taking the remaining shocks themselves. In each of two experiments, subjects' level of empathic emotion (low versus high) and their ease of escape from continuing to watch the victim suffer if they did not help (easy versus difficult) were manipulated in a 2 X 2 design. We reasoned that if empathy led to altruistic motivation, subjects feeling a high degree of empathy for the victim should be as ready to help when escape without helping was easy as when it was difficult. But if empathy led to egoistic motivation, subjects feeling empathy should be more ready to help when escape was difficult than when it was easy. Results of each experiment followed the former pattern when empathy was high and the latter pattern when empathy was low, supporting the hypothesis that empathy leads to altruistic rather than egoistic motivation to help. Evidence indicates that feeling empathy The egoistic orientation of modern psy- for the person in need is an important mo- chology should not be dismissed lightly; it tivator of helping (cf.