Behavioral Momentum and the Law of Effect

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Behavioral Momentum and the Law of Effect See discussions, stats, and author profiles for this publication at: https://www.researchgate.net/publication/12031687 Behavioral momentum and the Law of Effect Article in Behavioral and Brain Sciences · March 2000 Impact Factor: 20.77 · DOI: 10.1017/S0140525X00002405 · Source: PubMed CITATIONS READS 300 460 2 authors: John A Nevin Randolph Grace University of New Hampshire University of Canterbury 125 PUBLICATIONS 4,412 CITATIONS 135 PUBLICATIONS 2,481 CITATIONS SEE PROFILE SEE PROFILE All in-text references underlined in blue are linked to publications on ResearchGate, Available from: Randolph Grace letting you access and read them immediately. Retrieved on: 25 May 2016 BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (2000) 23, 73–130 Printed in the United States of America Behavioral momentum and the Law of Effect John A. Nevin Department of Psychology, University of New Hampshire, Durham, NH 03824 [email protected] Randolph C. Grace Department of Psychology, University of Canterbury, Christchurch, New Zealand [email protected] Abstract: In the metaphor of behavioral momentum, the rate of a free operant in the presence of a discriminative stimulus is analogous to the velocity of a moving body, and resistance to change measures an aspect of behavior that is analogous to its inertial mass. An ex- tension of the metaphor suggests that preference measures an analog to the gravitational mass of that body. The independent functions relating resistance to change and preference to the conditions of reinforcement may be construed as convergent measures of a single construct, analogous to physical mass, that represents the effects of a history of exposure to the signaled conditions of reinforcement and that unifies the traditionally separate notions of the strength of learning and the value of incentives. Research guided by the momentum metaphor encompasses the effects of reinforcement on response rate, resistance to change, and preference and has implications for clin- ical interventions, drug addiction, and self-control. In addition, its principles can be seen as a modern, quantitative version of Thorndike’s (1911) Law of Effect, providing a new perspective on some of the challenges to his postulation of strengthening by reinforcement. Keywords: behavioral momentum; clinical interventions; drug addiction; preference; reinforcement; resistance to change; response strength; self-control 1. Introduction to change and preference covary and that they provide in- dependent, convergent measurement of a single construct The stimulus presented by the experimenter, the response analogous to the mass of a physical body. In terms of the tra- of the organism, and the reinforcer that follows the re- ditional distinction between learning and performance, ve- sponse are fundamental elements in the science of behav- locity (identified with response rate) characterizes ongoing ior. Skinner (1969) suggested that these three terms define performance, whereas mass (derived from resistance to the discriminated operant as a unit for analysis. This target change and preference) reflects the learning that results article argues that there are two separable aspects of dis- from a history of reinforcement in the presence of a dis- criminated operant behavior that has been trained to asymp- tinctive stimulus situation. tote: its rate of occurrence, which depends primarily on the We begin by contrasting response rate and resistance to contingencies between the response and the reinforcer, and change as measures of the traditional construct of response its resistance to change, which depends primarily on the contingencies between the stimulus and the reinforcer. The distinction between response rate and resistance to John A. Nevin is Professor Emeritus of Psychology at change is captured by the metaphor of behavioral momen- the University of New Hampshire. He is the author of tum, in which the rate of a simple, repeatable response in the about 100 articles and book chapters on stimulus con- presence of a distinctive stimulus is analogous to the velocity trol and reinforcement processes in animals, and the of a physical body in motion. Following Newton’s second law, relevance of these processes for human well-being. when responding is disrupted in some way that is analogous Randolph C. Grace began his professional life as an to imposing an external force on a moving body, resistance to electrical engineer but became more interested in psy- change of response rate is related to an aspect of behavior chology, and he received his Ph.D. in that subject from that is analogous to inertial mass in classical mechanics. the University of New Hampshire in 1995. He is cur- To pursue the metaphor, Newton’s law of gravitation sug- rently Lecturer in Psychology at the University of Can- gests that an analog to gravitational mass may be derived terbury, and his research and teaching interests include basic learning processes and choice, human decision from the attractiveness or value of access to reinforced re- making, and statistics and research methods. He spends sponding as measured by preference. Although they refer some of his time away from the university playing ten- to different aspects of behavior – namely, resistance to nis, exploring the South Island of New Zealand, and try- change in the presence of a stimulus and responding that ing to understand rugby and cricket. gains access to that stimulus – we will argue that resistance © 2000 Cambridge University Press 0140-525X/00 $12.50 73 Nevin & Grace: Law of Effect strength and describe some research on resistance to change effects of reinforcement on average response rate. Presum- that distinguishes response rate and resistance. After a re- ably, if shaping contingencies were kept constant across con- view of related work on preference, the convergence of ditions that varied in the rate or amount of reinforcement, av- resistance and preference is treated via the momentum erage steady-state response rate would give a direct measure metaphor. Supporting research involving concurrent mea- of the strengthening effect of reinforcement. surement of resistance and preference is described, and the In his review of the literature, however, Morse noted that discrepancy between resistance and preference resulting the steady-state rate of a single response maintained by a sin- from the partial reinforcement extinction effect is resolved gle schedule of reinforcement was not always an orderly by a model of resistance to change that incorporates gener- function of reinforcer amount when reinforcement contin- alization decrement. After considering some extensions to gencies were constant. For example, Keesey and Kling clinical interventions, drug effects, and self-control, we argue (1961) found that response rates maintained by variable-in- that the findings of research on behavioral momentum con- terval (VI) schedules were essentially constant when rein- stitute a modern, quantitative version of Thorndike’s (1911) forcer amount was varied. However, Keesey and Kling also Law of Effect and we review some challenges to the Law of reported that response rate was positively related to rein- Effect from the perspective of behavioral momentum. forcer amount when each of three different stimuli signaled a different amount and alternated within each session (see also Shettleworth & Nevin 1965). In effect, Keesey and 2. The strength of steady-state free Kling’s method established three discriminated operants de- operant behavior fined jointly by the antecedent stimuli, the responses in their presence, and the consequences of responding signaled by The idea that behavior varies along a dimension of strength the stimuli (Skinner 1969). Following Skinner, we take the appears in Sherrington’s (1906) studies of reflexive behavior, discriminated operant to be a fundamental unit in the sci- where strength was measured by the latency and amplitude ence of behavior. The relations between the strength of dis- of response to an eliciting stimulus. It appears also in Pavlov’s criminated operant behavior and the signaled conditions of (1927) studies of conditional reflexes, where strength was reinforcement will be explored in sections 3, 4, and 7. measured by resistance to extinction or to external inhibition as well as by the latency or amplitude of response to a condi- 2.2. Choice, strength, and value tional stimulus. Hull’s (1943) theorizing relied heavily on the construct of habit strength, which was established by rein- Extensions of the steady-state operant paradigm to choice forcement and expressed in performance measures such as between two continuously available operants inspired a latency, amplitude, probability, and resistance to extinction new approach to the measurement of response strength of a learned response. However, these measures did not al- and reinforcement value. In a much-cited study, Herrnstein ways covary, casting doubt on the utility of the construct. (1961) arranged concurrent VI VI schedules for pigeons’ Moreover, as was suggested by Logan (1956), responses that responses to two keys, effectively arranging two simultane- varied along dimensions such as latency and amplitude could ous discriminated operants defined by key location, and be construed as different responses rather than as instances found that the relative frequency of responses to one alter- of a single response that varied in strength. native roughly equaled (matched) the relative frequency of Following Skinner’s (1938) relatively atheoretical ap- food
Recommended publications
  • Uncertainty and Hyperbolic Discounting
    Uncertainty and Hyperbolic Discounting By PARTHA DASGUPTA AND ERIC MASKIN* Empirical studies in economics and behav- they have become more impatient than they ioral ecology suggest that, ceteris paribus, ani- were in January. mals and humans appear to place less weight on Both the O’Donoghue-Rabin and Strotz ex- the future than on the present, i.e., they act as amples accord with “hyperbolic discounting,”2 though they discount future payoffs. Further- which has attracted considerable interest among more (and more interestingly), they do so with economists because it appears to shed light on discount rates that increase as the time before important economic phenomena such as house- those payoffs are realized grows shorter.1 In hold saving behavior (see David Laibson, 1997; other words, subjects act as though they become B. Douglas Bernheim et al., 2001; Christopher less patient when payoffs are more imminent. Harris and Laibson, 2003). An anecdotal (human) example is offered by One might ask whether there is some reason Ted O’Donoghue and Matthew Rabin (1999): for such behavior. The point of view that we when offered the choice in February between a take is that, to a considerable extent, animal and painful seven-hour task (e.g., preparing a tax human behavior is shaped by preferences that return) on April 1 and a painful eight-hour task are the outcome of evolutionary forces. That is, on April 15, most of us, they suggest, will opt cravings, urges, or instincts—the operational for the earlier date. But as April 1 approaches, manifestations of preferences—induce the ani- we are apt to change our minds, if we can, and mal or human to make the right choice in the postpone the pain to April 15, even though it “average” situation that it, he, or she is likely to will then be greater.
    [Show full text]
  • Principles of Behavioral Economics for Personal Development 30 Giugno 2018 Rodica Ianole-Calin
    Tribunale Bologna 24.07.2007, n.7770 - ISSN 2239-7752 Direttore responsabile: Antonio Zama Principles of Behavioral Economics for Personal Development 30 Giugno 2018 Rodica Ianole-Calin Contributo selezionato da Filodiritto tra quelli pubblicati nei Proceedings “International Conference on Economics and Administration 2017” Per acquistare i Proceedings clicca qui: http://www.filodirittoeditore.com/index.php?route=product/product&path=78&product_id=143 Contribution selected by Filodiritto among those published in the Proceedings “International Conference on Economics and Administration 2017” To buy the Proceedings click here: http://www.filodirittoeditore.com/index.php?route=product/product&path=78&product_id=143 IANOLE-C?LIN Rodica [1], BRATU Anca [2] [1] Faculty of Business and Administration, University of Bucharest (ROMANIA) [2] Faculty of Business and Administration, University of Bucharest (ROMANIA) Emails: [email protected], [email protected] Abstract The paper aims to illustrate how becoming aware of our own behavioral patterns, by exposure to the experiments brought forward by behavioral economics, can trigger a significant transformation of our personal habits, in the direction of a better congruence with our true self and finally of better decision- making. The argumentation highlights three main focal points: the tensioned choice between maximizing and satisficing approaches, the inter-temporal conundrum between now and later, and the gap between planning and action. Introduction Understanding standard economic thinking – how a market works, how prices are formed, how economic agents interact – is without any doubt a first premise for achieving economic development. The following step, that of becoming acquainted with behavioral economic thinking, can further refine this development, but in a reverse order: creating initially a favorable space for personal development, that may gradually be led to wellbeing, also from a financial perspective.
    [Show full text]
  • Will As Intertemporal Bargaining: Implications for Rationality
    WILL AS INTERTEMPORAL BARGAINING: IMPLICATIONS FOR RATIONALITY GEORGE AINSLIEt &JOHN MONTEROSSOtt Rationality has been understood as conducting yourself according to reason rather than passion. In modern times this endeavor has become synonymous with maximizing your expected goods, with the value of expected but delayed goods dis- counted exponentially. However, behavioral research has found a robust tendency for delayed goods to be discounted hyperbolically, that is, for their value to be di- vided by their delay. This finding supplies a simple hypothesis about the origin of irrationality, but greatly complicates the problem of rationality, since it depicts a limited warfare relationship among interests within an individual. Recent re- search on the combining properties of hyperbolically discounted rewards supports the hypothesis that a person s will arisesfrom a prisoner's-dilemma-likerelationship among successive motivational states. This picoeconomic hypothesis provides a mechanism for both the strength and 'freedom" of the will, and predicts pathologies of overcontrol that make strength of will something very different from pure ration- ality. This approach offers insights into current puzzles about criminal responsi- bility and the disease model of addiction. INTRODUCTION Rationality is an ancient concept, one that Plato contrasted with passion to form a dichotomy of choice principles.' Through the ages rationality has meant the good way to make choices, the way that will maximize your satisfaction with the outcome. As such, it has been a norm rather than a description of actual behavior. However, since utility theory has postulated that people always maximize their ex- pected utility, rationality has acquired a descriptive implication: the rational is what anyone inevitably will do whenever she is aware of the true contingencies she faces.
    [Show full text]
  • Neuroeconomics: How Neuroscience Can Inform Economics
    mr05_Article 1 3/28/05 3:25 PM Page 9 Journal of Economic Literature Vol. XLIII (March 2005), pp. 9–64 Neuroeconomics: How Neuroscience Can Inform Economics ∗ COLIN CAMERER, GEORGE LOEWENSTEIN, and DRAZEN PRELEC Who knows what I want to do? Who knows what anyone wants to do? How can you be sure about something like that? Isn’t it all a question of brain chemistry, signals going back and forth, electrical energy in the cortex? How do you know whether something is really what you want to do or just some kind of nerve impulse in the brain. Some minor little activity takes place somewhere in this unimportant place in one of the brain hemispheres and suddenly I want to go to Montana or I don’t want to go to Montana. (White Noise, Don DeLillo) 1. Introduction such as finance, game theory, labor econom- ics, public finance, law, and macroeconomics In the last two decades, following almost a (see Colin Camerer and George Loewenstein century of separation, economics has begun 2004). Behavioral economics has mostly been to import insights from psychology. informed by a branch of psychology called “Behavioral economics” is now a prominent “behavioral decision research,” but other fixture on the intellectual landscape and has cognitive sciences are ripe for harvest. Some spawned applications to topics in economics, important insights will surely come from neu- roscience, either directly or because neuro- ∗ Camerer: California Institute of Technology. science will reshape what is believed about Loewenstein: Carnegie Mellon University. Prelec: psychology which in turn informs economics. Massachusetts Institute of Technology.
    [Show full text]
  • Economic Theory and Experimental Economics*
    ECONOMIC THEORY AND EXPERIMENTAL ECONOMICS* Larry Samuelson Department of Economics University of Wisconsin 1180 Observatory Drive Madison, WI 53706-1321 USA September 24, 2004 Contents 1 Introduction 1 2 An Example 2 3 A Theoretical Perspective 9 3.1 A Model . 9 3.2 Why Experiments? . 14 3.3 Why Theory? . 18 4 Combining theory and experiments 21 4.1 Using Experiments to Learn About Theory . 21 4.1.1 Testing Theory: Accuracy . 21 4.1.2 The Margin of Error: Precision . 27 4.2 Using Theory to Learn about Experiments . 30 4.2.1 External Validity . 30 4.2.2 Internal Validity . 35 5 The Search for Theory 40 5.1 Perceived Protocols . 41 5.2 Evolutionary Foundations . 47 6 Conclusion 52 7 Appendix: Proof of Proposition 1 54 *I thank Jim Andreoni, Jakob Goeree, Roger Gordon, John McMillan, Georg NÄoldeke and three referees for helpful comments. I thank the Ex- perimental Science Association for the invitation to give a talk at the 2003 Pittsburgh meetings that developed into this paper. I thank the National Science Foundation (SES-0241506) and Russell Sage Foundation (82-02-04) for ¯nancial support. Economic Theory and Experimental Economics Larry Samuelson 1 Introduction Game theory had its beginnings in economics as a separate topic of analysis, practiced by a cadre of specialists. It has since become commonplace. Every economist is acquainted with the basic ideas, often without notice, and there is free movement between the use of game theory and other techniques. This incorporation as a standard economic tool has helped shape the nature of game theory itself|the mix of questions has changed and more attention has been devoted to how game theoretic models are to be interpreted as capturing economic interactions.
    [Show full text]
  • Excessive Trading Volume, Agreement Price
    Coherent Preferences and Reference Point Updating in Bargain, Competition, and Interactive Trading in Stock Market Leilei Shi*,1,2, Mato Njavro3, and Boris Podobnik-6 1University of Science and Technology of China (USTC), China 2Bank of China International (China) Co. Ltd 3Institute of Management in Asia, University of St. Gallen, Switzerland 4Center for Polymer Studies and Department of Physics, Boston University, USA 5Faculty of Civil Engineering, University of Rijeka, Croatia 6Zagreb School of Economics and Management, Croatia We welcome comments from the fields of behavior analysis, psychology, sociology, econophysics as well as from economics, finance, and management. We would appreciate it very much if you recommended a proper journal for publication after thorough peer reviews across those fields. (November 14, 2016) *Corresponding author: E-mail address: [email protected] or [email protected] (Leilei Shi) Mobile phone: (0086)18611270598, 13671328061 Postal address: Bank of China International (China) Co. Ltd.—Beijing Business Branch Room 103, 1/FL., Global Finance & News Center, #A1 Xuanwaidajie, Xicheng District, Beijing 100052, China 1 Coherent Preferences and Reference Point Updating in Bargain, Competition, and Interactive Trading in Stock Market Extended Abstract (298 words) Individuals have preferences and beliefs in their judgment and decision making. These are two broad topics in behavioral economics and finance. However, it is a challenge to find the right way to measure individual preferences in choice and beliefs in assessment because such behaviors are unobservable outside laboratory. We assume that a speculative trader might trade a stock as any another trader or collective traders have done in intraday trading although we observe that he trades it at a sure price.
    [Show full text]
  • Laboratory Experimentation in Economics
    Laboratory experimentation in economics Laboratory experimentation in economics Six points of view Edited by ALVIN E. ROTH University of Pittsburgh T/ie r/gA/ o/ the University of Cambridge to print and sell all manner of books was granted by Henry VIII in 1534. The University has printed and published continuously since 1584. CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS Cambridge New York New Rochelle Melbourne Sydney CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS Cambridge, New York, Melbourne, Madrid, Cape Town, Singapore, Sao Paulo Cambridge University Press The Edinburgh Building, Cambridge CB2 2RU, UK Published in the United States of America by Cambridge University Press, New York www.cambridge.org Information on this title: www.cambridge.org/9780521333924 © Cambridge University Press 1987 This publication is in copyright. Subject to statutory exception and to the provisions of relevant collective licensing agreements, no reproduction of any part may take place without the written permission of Cambridge University Press. First published 1987 This digitally printed first paperback version 2005 A catalogue record for this publication is available from the British Library Library of Congress Cataloguing in Publication data Laboratory experimentation in economics. 1. Economics - Experiments. I. Roth, Alvin E., 1951- HB131.L32 1987 330'.0724 87-10343 ISBN-13 978-0-521-33392-4 hardback ISBN-10 0-521-33392-X hardback ISBN-13 978-0-521-02281-1 paperback ISBN-10 0-521-02281-9 paperback Contents Acknowledgments page vii List of contributors viii 1 Introduction and overview 1 Alvin E. Roth 2 Bargaining phenomena and bargaining theory 14 Alvin E. Roth 3 Equity and coalition bargaining in experimental three-person games 42 Reinhard Selten 4 The psychology of choice and the assumptions of economics 99 Richard Thaler 5 Hypothetical valuations and preference reversals in the context of asset trading 131 Marc Knez and Vernon L.
    [Show full text]
  • THE NEW BEHAVIORISM Mind, Mechanism and Society
    THE NEW BEHAVIORISM Mind, Mechanism and Society John Staddon CONTENTS Part 1: History Chapter 1: Early Behaviorism Chapter 2: Behaviorism and Learning Psychology Part 2: Radical Behaviorism Chapter 3: Radical Behaviorism, I: Method Chapter 4: Radical Behaviorism, II: Explanation Chapter 5: Skinner and Theory Chapter 6: Variation and Selection Chapter 7: Behavior-Evolution Parallels Chapter 8: Rationality Chapter 9: Truth, Science and Behaviorism Chapter 10: Free Will and Utopia Chapter 11: Values Chapter 12: Skinner and Mental Life Part 3: The New Behaviorism Chapter 13: Cognitivism and The New Behaviorism i Chapter 14: Internal States: The Logic of Historical Systems Chapter 15: Consciousness and Theoretical Behaviorism Postscript to Parts 1-3: Alchemy of the Mind Part 4: Behaviorism and Society Chapter 16: Law, Punishment and Behaviorism Chapter 17: The Health-Care Schedule Chapter 18: Reinforcement and ‘Socialized’ Medicine Chapter 19: Teaching ii Preface to the Second Edition This edition is almost completely rewritten. It is about 45% longer than the first. I cover two new social issues and also devote more space to the philosophy of cognitivism and the science behind theoretical behaviorism. B. F. Skinner figures less prominently in this edition than the last, but his work is a theme that still runs through many chapters – because his influence has been so great and his writings raise so many provocative issues that are identified with behavior- ism. But, as readers of the first edition detected, my position is far from Skinnerian. Many reviewers thought well of the first edition but, naturally, I want to attend to those who did not.
    [Show full text]
  • Examining the Utility of Behavioral Economic Demand in Addiction Science
    University of Kentucky UKnowledge Theses and Dissertations--Psychology Psychology 2019 EXAMINING THE UTILITY OF BEHAVIORAL ECONOMIC DEMAND IN ADDICTION SCIENCE Justin Charles Strickland University of Kentucky, [email protected] Digital Object Identifier: https://doi.org/10.13023/etd.2019.030 Right click to open a feedback form in a new tab to let us know how this document benefits ou.y Recommended Citation Strickland, Justin Charles, "EXAMINING THE UTILITY OF BEHAVIORAL ECONOMIC DEMAND IN ADDICTION SCIENCE" (2019). Theses and Dissertations--Psychology. 154. https://uknowledge.uky.edu/psychology_etds/154 This Doctoral Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Psychology at UKnowledge. It has been accepted for inclusion in Theses and Dissertations--Psychology by an authorized administrator of UKnowledge. For more information, please contact [email protected]. STUDENT AGREEMENT: I represent that my thesis or dissertation and abstract are my original work. Proper attribution has been given to all outside sources. I understand that I am solely responsible for obtaining any needed copyright permissions. I have obtained needed written permission statement(s) from the owner(s) of each third-party copyrighted matter to be included in my work, allowing electronic distribution (if such use is not permitted by the fair use doctrine) which will be submitted to UKnowledge as Additional File. I hereby grant to The University of Kentucky and its agents the irrevocable, non-exclusive, and royalty-free license to archive and make accessible my work in whole or in part in all forms of media, now or hereafter known. I agree that the document mentioned above may be made available immediately for worldwide access unless an embargo applies.
    [Show full text]
  • Procrastination Is the Basic Impulse
    Procastination—Ainslie 1/19 Procrastination: The Basic Impulse George Ainslie Presented at the CUNY workshop, Procrastination New York, NY July 9, 2008 George Ainslie, MD Research Psychiatrist 151 Veterans Affairs Medical Center Coatesville, PA 19081 610 383-0260 voice 610 380-4377 fax [email protected] www.Picoeconomics.com Procastination—Ainslie 2/19 Key words: hyperbolic discounting, impulsiveness, self-control, motivational conflict, commitment, will, personal rules, recursive self-prediction, intertemporal bargaining, bundling [prospective rewards], emotional reward, visceral reward Text Webster defines “procrastinate” as “to put off until tomorrow, or from day to day;” it generally means to put off something burdensome or unpleasant, and to do so in a way that leaves you worse off. By procrastinating you choose a course that you would avoid if you chose from a different vantage point, either from some time in advance or in retrospect. Thus the urge to procrastinate meets the basic definition of an impulse— temporary preference for a smaller, sooner (SS) reward over a larger, later (LL) reward. I will argue that it is the most basic impulse, the one in which the disproportionate value of the immediate future can be seen without confounding factors. The motives we think of as impulses usually involve an impending thrill, a vivid sensation that is hard to resist. Examples include eating rich food, drinking, taking recreational drugs, having sexual encounters and making purchases. Often impulses are focused on a physical activity or consumption good, which makes them easier to understand in terms of conventional utility theory. But many impulses involve no consumption.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction Michael Hechter
    Introduction Michael Hechter The basic tenet of rational choice theory is that both behavior and social institutions arise from the action of individuals, each of whom makes their own decisions.* The theory also focuses on the determinants of these individual choices. It holds that individuals have complete and transitive preferences over the options available to them.1 These preferences allow the options to be ranked according to their relative desirability. Rational actors take account of the available information, the probabilities of attaining their preferred ends, and the potential costs and benefits of doing so. Ultimately, they act consistently to choose the course of action that they deem to be optimal for them. Due to its emphasis on methodological individualism – the contention that social explanations ultimately must be derivable from facts about individuals – and its ostensible commitment to self-interested behavioral assumptions, sociology has long been blind, if not downright hostile, to the virtues of rational choice.2 Since I am a sociologist, perhaps it is worth retracing my path to intellectual heresy and the dark side. This is a long story. It begins, I suppose, in high school in Worcester, Massachusetts. My father, a biochemist, was a passionate believer in science. Science had enabled him to escape a dreadful childhood of poverty and parental irresponsibility in his Maxwell Street neighborhood – Chicago’s answer to Manhattan’s Lower East Side. Over dinner, he would regale us with descriptions of his research and tales of academic politics. Truth to tell, the intricacies of his research seemed beyond me; they were exceedingly technical, involving benzene rings, hydroxyl groups and a multitude of other molecules and interactions.
    [Show full text]
  • Five Principles for the Unification of the Behavioral Sciences Herbert
    Five Principles for the Unification of the Behavioral Sciences Herbert Gintis May 13, 2008 1 Introduction The behavioral sciences include economics, anthropology, sociology, psychology, and political science, as well as biology insofar as it deals with animal and hu- man behavior. These disciplines have distinct research foci, but they include four conflicting models of decision-making and strategic interaction, as determined by what is taught in the graduate curriculum, and what is accepted in journal articles without reviewer objection. The four are the psychological, the sociological, the biological, and the economic. These four models are not only different, which is to be expected given their distinct explanatory goals, but incompatible. This means, of course, that at least three of the four are certainly incorrect, and I will argue that in fact all four are flawed, but can be modified to produce a unified framework for modeling choice and strategic interaction for all of the behavioral sciences. Such a framework would then be enriched in different ways to meet the particular needs of each discipline. In the past, cross-disciplinary incoherence was tolerated because distinct dis- ciplines dealt largely with distinct phenomena. Economics dealt with market ex- change. Sociology dealt with stratification and social deviance. Psychology dealt with brain functioning. Biology avoided dealing with human behavior altogether. In recent years, however, the value of transdisciplinary research in addressing ques- tions of social theory has become clear, and sociobiologyhas become a major arena of behavioral research. Moreover, contemporary social policy involves issues that fall squarely in the interstices of the behavioral disciplines, including substance abuse, crime, corruption, tax compliance, social inequality, poverty, discrimina- Santa Fe Institute and Central European University.
    [Show full text]