Chapter Eleven

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Chapter Eleven Knowledge of human nature is the beginning and end of political education. (Henry Adams) CHAPTER ELEVEN THE STATE OF NATURE & THE INFLUENCE OF ORGANIZED SOCIETY HUMAN NATURE? READING QUESTIONS We know how to create This question has been treated by arguments and test them. And a number of thinkers, and you can As you study this chapter, keep these questions in mind for critical we’ve found that some issues are bet they come down on both thinking and analysis. far more complicated than they sides. Some say we’re nasty and • Explain the “Ring of Gyges” seemed to be before we looked only act or become good thought experiment. What is at them. It’s important to ask because organized society its point? whether God exists, and what sort changes us (so, person 0, society • Explain the importance of of being God might be if God 1). Others say we’re just great, but thought experiments in exists. Now what sort of things are society corrupts us (so, person 1, testing philosophical we? What is our nature, our society 0). Which arguments arguments or theories. essence? When you look at a seem more compelling? • What is the difference human being as such (human qua between negative and positive Finally, if we are purely evil or human), what is it? philosophy? What is the role purely good, then how in the of each in the philosophical This is a multi-part question. The first world can we act contrary to our pursuit of truth? part we’ll treat in this chapter (and nature? How is it possible that • Explain the notion called the the others in the rest of this text). something essentially good can “State of Nature.” This question asks about our go sour or something essentially • Explain and analyze nature as moral or virtuous. Are we bad can rise to moral greatness? Hobbes’ state of nature good? Are we evil? If you could How could we change our very argument. What is his theoretically remove us from essential nature? conclusion? How does his argument work? society, and just look at us as Logically, it would seem we individuals—like pinned insects on • Explain Xunzi’s argument couldn’t. that we are essentially, a card or samples in a Petri dish— naturally evil. How does he what would we be like? explain our ability to do good? Analyze his argument. Is it valid? Sound? How can he explain how something can go against its nature? Does his explanation work? • How do Hobbes and Master Hsün disagree regarding human nature and the role of organized society? Do either agree with Glaucon’s suggestion in the Ring of Gyges though experiment? continued… Chapter 11, page 343 The State of Nature & The Influence of Organized Society HUMAN NATURE IS THE ONLY SCIENCE OF MAN; AND READING QUESTIONS, YET HAS BEEN HITHERTO THE MOST NEGLECTED. continued. • How does Xunzi differ (DAVID HUME) from Mengzi regarding human nature? How do they account for the presence of evil? FOUNDATIONS • Explain Rousseau’s state We’ll be maintaining our use of LL: (x = y) → (Px & Py) of nature arguments. How the logical principles we learned We’ll also learn the following : does he reach his final already: conclusion? What is his X is a thought experiment iff x is conclusion? The Principle of Non- a conceptual exploration of a Contradiction (PNC): It is a • Explain Locke’s state of possible SOFA that tests one logical law that for any nature argument. What is particular concept or thesis. his conclusion? How does claim p, it is false that both it differ from Rousseau’s? p and not-p. X is the essence of something y iff x is the most basic, • What is natural law, and PNC: ~(p&~p) necessary, and unalterable how is it different than the The Law of Excluded Middle part of y that defines y as y and law we find in organized society? (LEM): It is a logical law that not something else. for claim p, either p is true • What do all the European X is an accidental property (or or p is not true. philosophers agree on? accident) of y iff x is a part of y What things do all humans LEM: p ∨ ~p that may be understood as share in the State of important but still could be Nature? Bivalence: Every claim or theory removed or changed without has exactly one truth value, • What influence does making y into something other either true or false. (That is, Locke’s account have on than y. both PNC and LEM apply.) American political thought, both historically Leibniz’s Law (LL): It is a logical TASKS AND CQs and currently? law that for anything x, There three critical questions and • Compare and contrast all anything y, and any one task in this chapter. There is the state of nature property P, if x is identical arguments. Who would also one team project. with y, then x and y will agree with whom, and both have P. over what? Which position (or positions) seem(s) to you best supported, both by evidence and by argument? • Explain why one might think humans are naturally evil. What arguments can be supplied for this thesis? Why might one think we’re naturally good? What problems come from taking one position over the other? • What are some criticisms of the social contract theory of justice? Chapter 11, page 344 The State of Nature & The Influence of Organized Society ON THOUGHT EXPERIMENTS One way philosophers attempt to tease out specific problems or issues, as we’ve seen from the last chapter, is the thought experiment. Rowe’s deer in the forest fire scenario is a thought experiment. But what is a thought experiment? X is a thought experiment iff x is a (probably implausible) hypothetical scenario that is designed to isolate and analyze intuitions concerning some philosophical issue. CHAPTER Notice that thought experiments are only probably implausible. OVERVIEW Rowe’s isn’t. But the Matrix is. The Allegory of the Cave is. Most In this chapter, we are primarily thought experiments are implausible because they are isolating concerned with another problem specific intuitions—specific gut feelings or pre-reflective beliefs. In the that deals with metaphysics, but it Allegory of the Cave, for example, Plato wants to look at only the is more directly related to questions process of learning and the nature of reality.* It doesn’t matter that of value theoretical philosophy like somebody who’s spent their whole life strapped to a chair would have ethics and political philosophy. For certain practices and values to atrophied muscles, so wouldn’t be able to clamber out of a steep cave. make sense—to be to some extent It doesn’t matter that somebody who’s never seen color would fail to rational values—reality needs to be grasp the riot of hues behind him, let alone the dizzying array outside certain ways. For example, if it of the sunless cave. In a thought experiment, it does not matter how turned out that human beings probable the scenario is. Saying, this is absurd. It’d never happen! is have no power to direct their own unhelpful, and totally missing the point. Of course this scenario would actions but were instead probably never happen. We’ve probably taken away from it all the marionettes being directed by complexities that would make it possible, in order to focus on the some cosmic puppeteer, it would important intuitions (or those intuitions that are important to the seem very irrational to blame current discussion). people for doing what they do, for calling those actions morally Instead of worrying about how likely a certain scenario is, focus on wrong. * Responsibility requires what the key point of the experiment might be. Thought experiments some ability to control one’s own are like laboratory experiments. In a lab, scientists create artificial actions. More generally, then, how conditions—that would never happen otherwise—in order to narrow the world is (metaphysics) relates down their study to one or two key variables. (A Petrie dish isn’t directly to how we value things in the world. exactly a natural environment!) Specifically for this chapter, we’re continued… looking at what sort of thing a * He’s actually looking at both. The Allegory of the Cave shows up alongside two other human being is. We’ll ask “what is a allegories, which explain the nature of reality in his metaphysical system, and human qua human?” The term qua learning about reality is going to be directly related to the nature of reality itself. If (pronounced ‘quay’) is Latin for as, reality were different, then the path to coming to understand it would be different. or to the extent that (among many other things). When we talk of ‘x * This is a pretty succinct description of the importance of the problem of free will, which we discuss in chapter 13. Chapter 11, page 345 The State of Nature & The Influence of Organized Society qua x,’ we mean we want to talk about x itself, stripped of everything but the core essence of x, without ON THOUGHT EXPERIMENTS, any extras. So in this chapter, we’re continued. going to look at the essence of being human. They set up circumstances with strict parameters in order to limit the We’re also going to try to see how this human qua human is affected variables to only those they wish to study. Thought experiments do by organized society. Once we the same thing, but with concepts.
Recommended publications
  • Plato's Euthyphro and Meno
    Plato's Euthyphro and Meno Reading and Essays Questions Exeter College, Oxford University, HT13 Tutor: Simona Aimar E-mail: [email protected] Weekly Meetings: TBA General Information This is a syllabus for eight weeks work for the first-year course on Plato’s Meno and Euthyphro. Please email your assignments to me 24h before the tutorials. I am afraid that I will not be able to write comments on essays that are handed in later than this (unless – for exceptional reasons, e.g. illness – I have agreed to this beforehand). You are required to do at least five essays in the course of the term, plus one set of gobbets. You should each write an essay for the first tutorial. In week 7, you will write gobbets (comments on passages) instead of an essay. In any week when you do not do an essay/gobbets, you should do the reading and think about the question in advance of the tutorial, so that you are ready to discuss the essay question in the tutorial. We shall focus each week on one of the essays in the tutorial, alternating between you and the other student who will be attending the tutorials with you. If we are focusing on your essay, I’ll ask you to summarize it at the start of the tutorial. If we are focusing on someone else’s essay, you should have read her/his essay before the tutorial, and have spent some time thinking about whether you agree with it and how it might be improved.
    [Show full text]
  • Plato's "Euthyphro"
    24.231 Ethics – Handout 1 Plato, “The Euthyphro” I. Plato’s Dialogue Plato’s Question: What is it to be pious? - He is not looking for a list of things that are pious - He is not looking for a property that (even all) pious things have. Euthyphro’s (best?) answer: To be pious is to be loved by all the gods. Plato’s Argument against Euthyphro’s answer: Perhaps all and only those things/actions that are loved by the gods are pious. But why is that? Are pious things loved by the gods because they are pious, or are they pious because they are loved by the gods? Socrates and Euthyphro agree that they must be loved by the gods because they are pious. But, says Socrates, in that case, being pious cannot be the same thing as being god-beloved. Because something that is god-beloved is so because it is loved by the gods. But something that is pious isn’t so because it is loved by the gods; rather, it is loved by the gods because it is pious. Being loved by the gods causes god-belovedness, but being loved by the gods does not cause piety. So god-belovedness and piety cannot be the same thing. (This kind of argument will be relevant again in the selection from Moore that we’re reading for Wednesday.) II. The “Euthyphro Problem” Socrates’ question about whether what’s loved by the gods is pious because it is loved by them, or loved by them because it is pious, forms the lynchpin of an important contemporary debate about what moral philosophers call “Divine Command Theory.” According to DCT, morally good actions are good because they are commanded by God.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Arrangement of the Platonic Dialogues
    Ryan C. Fowler 25th Hour On the Arrangement of the Platonic Dialogues I. Thrasyllus a. Diogenes Laertius (D.L.), Lives and Opinions of Eminent Philosophers 3.56: “But, just as long ago in tragedy the chorus was the only actor, and afterwards, in order to give the chorus breathing space, Thespis devised a single actor, Aeschylus a second, Sophocles a third, and thus tragedy was completed, so too with philosophy: in early times it discoursed on one subject only, namely physics, then Socrates added the second subject, ethics, and Plato the third, dialectics, and so brought philosophy to perfection. Thrasyllus says that he [Plato] published his dialogues in tetralogies, like those of the tragic poets. Thus they contended with four plays at the Dionysia, the Lenaea, the Panathenaea and the festival of Chytri. Of the four plays the last was a satiric drama; and the four together were called a tetralogy.” b. Characters or types of dialogues (D.L. 3.49): 1. instructive (ὑφηγητικός) A. theoretical (θεωρηµατικόν) a. physical (φυσικόν) b. logical (λογικόν) B. practical (πρακτικόν) a. ethical (ἠθικόν) b. political (πολιτικόν) 2. investigative (ζητητικός) A. training the mind (γυµναστικός) a. obstetrical (µαιευτικός) b. tentative (πειραστικός) B. victory in controversy (ἀγωνιστικός) a. critical (ἐνδεικτικός) b. subversive (ἀνατρεπτικός) c. Thrasyllan categories of the dialogues (D.L. 3.50-1): Physics: Timaeus Logic: Statesman, Cratylus, Parmenides, and Sophist Ethics: Apology, Crito, Phaedo, Phaedrus, Symposium, Menexenus, Clitophon, the Letters, Philebus, Hipparchus, Rivals Politics: Republic, the Laws, Minos, Epinomis, Atlantis Obstetrics: Alcibiades 1 and 2, Theages, Lysis, Laches Tentative: Euthyphro, Meno, Io, Charmides and Theaetetus Critical: Protagoras Subversive: Euthydemus, Gorgias, and Hippias 1 and 2 :1 d.
    [Show full text]
  • Can God's Goodness Save the Divine Command Theory
    CAN GOD’S GOODNESS SAVE THE DIVINE COMMAND THEORY FROM EUTHYPHRO? JEREMY KOONS Georgetown University School of Foreign Service in Qatar Abstract. Recent defenders of the divine command theory like Adams and Alston have confronted the Euthyphro dilemma by arguing that although God’s commands make right actions right, God is morally perfect and hence would never issue unjust or immoral commandments. On their view, God’s nature is the standard of moral goodness, and God’s commands are the source of all obligation. I argue that this view of divine goodness fails because it strips God’s nature of any features that would make His goodness intelligible. An adequate solution to the Euthyphro dilemma may require that God be constrained by a standard of goodness that is external to Himself – itself a problematic proposal for many theists. The Euthyphro dilemma is often thought to present a fatal problem for the divine command theory (aka theological voluntarism). Are right acts commanded by God because they are right, or are they right because they are commanded by God? If the former, then there is a standard of right and wrong independent of God’s commands; God’s commands are not relevant in determining the content of morality. This option seems to compromise God’s sovereignty in an important way. But the second horn of the dilemma presents seemingly insurmountable problems, as well. First, if God’s commands make right actions right, and there is no standard of morality independent of God’s commands, then that seems to make morality arbitrary. Thus, murder is not wrong because it harms someone unjustly, but merely because God forbids it; there is (it seems) no good connection between reason and the wrongness of murder.
    [Show full text]
  • Socrates on the Definition of Piety: Euthyphro 10A- 11 B
    Socrates on the Definition of Piety: Euthyphro 10A- 11 B S. MARC COHEN PLATO'S Et~rt~reHRo is a clear example of a Socratic definitional dialogue. The concept to be defined is that of holiness or piety (z6 r the need for a defini- tion is presented in a manner characteristic of the early dialogues. Euthyphro is about to prosecute his father on a charge of murder, Socrates expresses surprise at Euthyphro's action, and Euthyphro defends himself by saying that to prosecute his father is pious, whereas not to prosecute him would be impious. Socrates then wonders whether Euthyphro's knowledge of piety and impiety is sufficient to guarantee that he is not acting impiously in prosecuting his father. The trap has been set; Euthyphro's vanity is stung, and the search for a definition begins. The outcome of the search is also familiar; all of Euthyphro's efforts miscarry. The dialogue ends with no satisfactory definition of piety either produced or in the offing. The central argument in the dialogue is the one Socrates advances (10a-lib) against Euthyphro's definition of piety as "what all the gods love." The argument is interesting on several counts. First, the argument is sufficiently unclear as to warrant discussion of what its structure is. Second, it is at least open to question whether there is any interpretation or reconstruction of the argument according to which it is valid and non-fallacious. Third, there are a number of points of con- temporary philosophical interest that inevitably arise in any adequate discussion of the argument.
    [Show full text]
  • The Religious and the Just in Plato's Euthyphro
    Ancient Philosophy 5 41 ©Mathesis Publications, Inc. The Religious and the Just in Plato's Euthyphro William S. Cobb Many traditional perplexities about Plato's dialogues can be resolved by taking the dialogue form seriously. One such puzzle is that concerning Socrates' apparent rejec­ tion in the Euthyphro of the view of the relation between the religious 1 and the just that he defends in the Protagoras. 2 I will examine this case as an illustration ofa method that attends carefully to the dialogue-form, appealing to dramatic setting and charac­ terization in interpreting the argument and noting possible ways areader might respond to the dialogue. 3 The question is: Does Plato have Socrates maintain in the Euthyphro that the reli­ gious is only apart of the just, in conflict with the claim in the Protagoras that the religious and the just are the same? It is generally assumed that he does. In the well­ known exchange between VIastos and Penner on the unity of virtue(s) which focuses on the Protagoras, both claim that Socrates holds a conflicting thesis in the Euthyphro. 4 Others have also expressed this view. S Indeed, C.C.W. Taylor has recently asserted that the claim that the religious is only apart of the just 'is not Euthyphro's hypothe­ sis, but Socrates', and must therefore be assumed to have Plato's approval'. 6 The fact that this claim conflicts with what Socrates defends in detail in the Pro­ tagoras has led some commentators to say that Plato did not intend us to see Socrates' affirmation that the religious is only part of the just in the Euthyphro as something he would defend in the final analysis; so A.E.
    [Show full text]
  • The Euthyphro
    1 (portion of) T H E E U T H Y P H R O By Plato Written 380 B.C. Persons of the Dialogue S O C R A T E S E U T H Y P H R O Scene The Porch of the Archon. ------------------------------------------------------------------------ Note on ‘holiness’, by the translator: The term ‘holy’ translates the Greek term ‘hosion’, which means something like ‘required by religion’ or ‘permitted by religion’, but which was also very widely used as a term of commendation that was felt to have independent ethical content. The English word ‘sin’ is a good paralel for this kind of word. ‘Sin’ has strong religious connotations; it is a term hardly used at all by non-religious people; yet everyone can easily understand the claim that ‘to do such and such would be a sin’ — whether they hold any religious views or not. The word has a perfectly clear ethical implication. ‘Hosion’ works in the same way, but as a positive rather than negative term, meaning something like ‘in accordance with religion’ but also ‘morally right’. Almost all terms of religiously-grounded ethical approval or disapproval, in all cultures, acquire this dual role as terms with ethical content and religious content. Religious terminology, whatever else it does, expresses ethical ideas, and always has done (and always will) entirely regardless of whether the cosmological and theological beliefs behind it are true, or false. It is exactly that feature, that mixing of ethical and religious thought that is the subject of the dialogue. The dialogue asks this central question: How can any concept
    [Show full text]
  • PDF Download Five Dialogues Apology, Crito, Euthyphro, Meno
    FIVE DIALOGUES APOLOGY, CRITO, EUTHYPHRO, MENO AND PHAEDO 1ST EDITION PDF, EPUB, EBOOK Plato | 9780915145225 | | | | | Five Dialogues Apology, Crito, Euthyphro, Meno and Phaedo 1st edition PDF Book Watch list is full. Longtime member. The Great Books programs, I decided, are a charming fringe eccentricity that shouldn't have been treated as generally representative Euthyphro and Meno, on the other hand, were remarkable for my understanding. This is a humbling experience, when we consider how foolish our own answers will appeat in the distant future. It depicts a conversation between Socrates and his wealthy friend Crito regarding justice, injustice, and the appropriate response to injustice. However silly and callow it may be, there's no point rewriting a review this old without re-reading the book. What does it mean for the human soul, and how can we, in waking life, ensure that our souls will live on in a greater and better way, after separation from the bodily shell? The obvious personal interest of his accusers in using the law to gain their own ends, and even the simple fact that the human laws of any state can easily be used to attain nearly any goal by one skilled enough in their manipulation, left me feeling that in this regard Socrates was either being willfully simple, or making an ironic comment on law itself. Five Dialogues Translated by Benjamin Jowett. Details if other :. Some of the techniques listed in Five Dialogues: Euthyphro, Apology, Crito, Meno, Phaedo may require a sound knowledge of Hypnosis, users are advised to either leave those sections or must have a basic understanding of the subject before practicing them.
    [Show full text]
  • Plato, Euthyphro & Meno
    PLATO, EUTHYPHRO & MENO READING LIST & ESSAY QUESTIONS I’ll be your tutor for this paper, Plato’s Euthyphro and Meno. The best email address for you to contact me on is [email protected]. Below is the current plan for topics and suggested reading with suggested essay titles. Please aim to read the preliminary reading and then read selectively (but carefully) from the suggested further reading. (It’s much better that you carefully read and respond to two papers rather than skimming through many.) Don’t feel constrained to only these texts – but it is helpful if everyone has a common starting point for discussion. These texts will be available either in your college library or online. There are far more topics than we’d actually have time to cover in tutorials. Hopefully, however, what we cover will be a useful springboard for your further study. The faculty reading list provides even more suggestions for reading, as will the relevant Stanford Encyclopaedia entry and, of course, the texts you read will inevitably lead you on to other texts. Obviously lectures are especially useful at giving you a thorough foundation for further study. If you do go further in your reading—great! However there’s always the chance that I or your partner have not read the specific text you address. So for all your reading it is important that you carefully lay out the author’s arguments and you reference accurately in your essays. The Harvard inline referencing style is easiest to follow (and most common in philosophy).
    [Show full text]
  • Plato's Euthyphro and the Earlier Theory of Forms
    PLATO'S 'EUTHYPHRO' AND THE EARLIER THEORY OF FORMS R. E. Allen ROUTLEDGE LIBRARY EDITIONS: PLATO ROUTLEDGE LIBRARY EDITIONS: PLATO PLATO’S ‘EUTHYPHRO’ AND THE EARLIER THEORY OF FORMS PLATO’S ‘EUTHYPHRO’ AND THE EARLIER THEORY OF FORMS R. E. ALLEN Volume 1 ROUTLEDG Routledge E Taylor &. Francis Group LONDON AND NEW YORK First published in1970 This edition first published in 2013 by Routledge 2 Park Square, Milton Park, Abingdon, Oxon, OX14 4RN Simultaneously published in the USA and Canada by Routledge 711 Third Avenue, New York, NY 10017 Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group, an informa business © 1970 R. E. Allen All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or reproduced or utilised in any form or by any electronic, mechanical, or other means, now known or hereafter invented, including photocopying and recording, or in any information storage or retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publishers. Trademark notice: Product or corporate names may be trademarks or registered trademarks, and are used only for identification and explanation without intent to infringe. British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library ISBN: 978-0-415-59194-2 (Set) eISBN: 978-0-203-10006-6 (Set) ISBN: 978-0-415-62630-9 (Volume 1) eISBN: 978-0-203-10169-8 (Volume 1) Publisher’s Note The publisher has gone to great lengths to ensure the quality of this reprint but points out that some imperfections in the original copies may be apparent. Disclaimer The publisher has made every effort to trace copyright holders and would welcome correspondence from those they have been unable to trace.
    [Show full text]
  • Identity and Explanation in the Euthyphro
    Created on 17 May 2017 at 11.15 hours page 77 IDENTITY AND EXPLANATION IN THE EUTHYPHRO DAVID EBREY CORE Metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk Provided by PhilPapers . Introduction I many of Plato’s Socratic dialogues Socrates emphasizes the im- portance of knowing the answer to a ‘what is it?’ question. What, exactly, is he looking for when he asks these questions? The Eu- thyphro is widely acknowledged as important for determining this, but scholars have not agreed on what insight the dialogue offers. Richard Sharvy, in a classic paper, presents an appealing and influ- ential account, and more recently Lindsay Judson has defended the same sort of account. According to their accounts, Socrates thinks that an answer to ‘what is the holy?’ should identify some more fun- damental feature of holy things that is prior to their being holy and explains why they are holy. (I use the word ‘feature’ for what is © David Ebrey I have received valuable feedback on this paper from Hugh Benson, David Bron- stein, Victor Caston, Andy Engen, Matt Evans, Emily Fletcher, Joe Karbowski, Sean Kelsey, Richard Kraut, Alison Mastny, Kirsten Pickering, John Wynne, the two anonymous referees, and the audiences at the NEH Summer Seminar on Socrates at Lewis and Clark College, King’s College London, the Chicago Area Consortium in Ancient Greek and Roman Philosophy, and the University of Arkansas. I do not mean the phrase ‘Socratic dialogue’ to indicate any particular view about chronology. For this use see J. Cooper (ed.), Plato: Complete Works [Complete Works] (Indianapolis, ), pp.
    [Show full text]
  • The Euthyphro Problem Revisited
    Katja Maria Vogt, katjavogt.com, Columbia University 1 The Euthyphro Problem Revisited. For Explorations in Ethics, ed. David Kaspar The Euthyphro Problem Revisited It is a fairly consensual view that Plato’s Euthyphro is the “urtext” of metaethics. 1 And yet, standard specifications of this view go astray. The Euthyphro is often thought to illustrate the concerns of Divine Command Theory. It is also thought to be the ancestor of metaethical realism, the view that value is attitude-independent. As I argue, the Euthyphro is neither concerned with Divine Command Theory nor is it a defense of realism in today’s sense. Instead, the Euthyphro argues that there is realist value, anti-realist value, and value that is both. Plato’s proposal should strike us as radically revisionist, to the extent that it is not clear whether today’s philosophical “map” can accommodate it. This, I submit, is why the Euthyphro deserves our attention. On standard readings, Plato is a dull dogmatist, rather than an ingenious philosopher raised on a steady diet of rebellious ideas by the likes of Heraclitus, Parmenides, Socrates, and Protagoras. On my reading, the Euthyphro offers a refutation of relativism, finds a place for anti- realism, sketches the beginnings of realism about the good, and envisages a kind of value that is realist and yet constituted by attitudes. After a brief conspectus of how philosophers reconstruct the so-called Euthyphro Problem (section 1), I sketch the most important bits of text (sections 2 and 3). Then I turn to contemporary work by Richard Swinburne, Connie Rosati, Selim Berker, Crispin Wright, and Sharon Street that invokes the Euthyphro.
    [Show full text]