The Critique of Scriptural Politics

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Critique of Scriptural Politics CHAPTE R TW O The Critique of Scriptural Politics Whoever hath an absolute authority to interpret any written or spoken laws, it is he who is truly the lawgiver to all intents and purposes, and not the person who firstspoke or wrote them. -Bishop Benjamin Hoadly The first treatise of Locke's Tw o Treatises of Government has the unfortunatedist inction of being, along with the latter half of the Leviathan, among the most neglected, indeed maligned, major portion of an otherwise celebrated and much discussed body of work in political theory. In fact, a scholarly tradition chronicles and advertises this neglect. Already in the nineteenth century, Fox Bourne, a generally sympathetic critic and biographer, found the First Treatise "entirely out of date" and with little to recommend it. 1 Early in the twentieth century, Harold Laski, notwithstanding his remarkable capacity to illuminate works of alleged insignificance, corroborated Fox Bourne's view, adding that the work was a "tiresome response to the historic imagina­ tion of Sir Robert Filmer."2 Similarly, Richard Aaron, although not usually rushed in his scholarly endeavors, found the work sufficiently barren so as not to be long detained by it. 3 This list 1 F. H. R. Bourne, The Lifeof john Locke (London, 1867) , 1:16 9. 2 Laski, Political Thought in England, p. 38. 3 Richard Aaron, John Locke, 2d ed. (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1955), p. 274. 3 7 38 The Anxiety of Freedom could easily be extended into the present. The attitude it would evince is sufficiently encapsulated in Dante Germino's remark that "the First Treatise, which virtually no one reads anymore, is a line-by-line refutation of Filmer's tome. Te dious would be per­ haps too flattering an adjective forit ."4 Clearly, Herbert Rowen's admonition almost thirty-five years ago that the First Treatise merits more attention has, among scholars writing in English, yet to be fullyacknow ledged. 5 Some obvious and weighty reasons do underlie and inform this distinguished tradition of neglect. Most conspicuous is that interest in Locke's political thought has usually been spurred by an interest in the normative concerns that attend liberalism. Given these motivating concerns, the Second Treatise is clearly the principal text for their interrogation, and the First Treatise has apparently less, if anything, to offer. The First Treatise is, after all, in the main reactive, and as such it at least appears to be implicated by the narrow purview of Filmer's own concerns. Related to the obsolescence of the First Treatise is the simple fact of the work's main foci. Divine grant and paternity as the basis of political sovereignty are substantive claims that are, at best, tangential to the major theoretical and concrete preoccupa­ tions of political life since at least the seventeenth century. The 4 Dante Gennino, "The Contemporary Relevance of the Classics of Political Philosophy," in Handbook ofPo litical Science, ed. Fred I. Greenstein and Nelson W. Polsby (Reading, Mass.: Addison-Wesley, 1975), 1:264. Charles D. Ta rlton, in "A Rope of Sand: Interpreting Locke's First Treatiseon Government," Historical Journal 21, no. 1 (1978), 43-73, gives a synoptic survey of what he calls "a vicious circle of oversight, prejudgment, and caricature which has effectively prohibited detailed, structural interpretation of the First Treatise." s Herbert H. Rowen, "A Second Thought on Locke's First Treatise,"Journal ofthe History of Ideas 17 (1956), 132. In the journal literature, there are a few exceptions to this claim; see, for example, Tarlton, "A Rope of Sand," Dunn, Political Thought of John Locke, Pangle, The Sp irit of Modern Republicanism, and James Tully's truly creative and synthetic work, "Governing Conduct," in Conscience and Casuistry in Early ModernEurope, ed . E. Leites (Cambridge: Cam­ bridge University Press, 1986). The Critique of Scriptural Politics 39 silencing of these Filmerian positions especially in the aftermath of the political and ecclesiastical settlement of 1688 is decisive. In the fractious working out of church, state, and crown relations, in the internecine denominational debates of the eighteenth cen­ tury, in the protracted process through which the meaning of the Toleration Act was settled, in all these and virtually anything else of consequence Filmer's arguments are merely distant and inaudible embarrassments. 6 It is not surprising, then, even if ironical, that Locke's First Treatise in having contributed to Fil­ mer's eclipse is by association similarly afflicted. From a more specificallytextual standpoint, the First Treatise is burdened by a variety of limitations that almost assure and contribute to its obsolescence. Notwithstanding the controversy regarding its date of writing, the First Treatise more than the Second appears to be an outcome of a very precise and local contextual pressure. 7 Locke himself identified the work as orig­ inating in the particular and surprising reception given Filmer's Patriarcha. Perhaps forreasons of his own, Locke emphasizes the dramatic effect of Filmer's work: "Had not the Gravity of the Title, and Epistle, the Picture in the Front of the Book, and the Applause that followed it, required me to believe, that the Au­ thor and the Publisher were both in earnest," he would have given it up as "another exercise of Wit" (First Treatise, p. 159). Filmer is clearly an author of doubtful seriousness. It appears 6 See Laski, Political Thought in England, pp. 54-85. 7 The classic statement of the issues surrounding the dating of Locke's two treatises remains Laslett's well-known introduction to his edited version of the Tw o Treatises. Laslett places great significance in the discovery that the Second Treatisewas , in fact, written before the First Treatise. This claim appears to belie Locke's own emphasis in view of the fact that the treatises were published in their present order on at least two separate occasions, on Locke's sanction during his own lifetime. Also see Richard Ashcraft's Revolutionary Politics and Locke's Tw o Treatisesof Government(Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1986), especially pp. 39-127. 40 The Anxiety of Freedom that but for the circumstances surrounding his work he would have been an unworthy opponent. 8 Finally there is the style of Locke's text, which limits its viability to a specific political and intellectual milieu. The First Treatise is a painfullyrepetitive work, a feature that suggests the intention of rhetorical effectivity rather than careful theoretical articulation. It is a response to what Locke believes are ultimately mischievous interests and which must therefore, at least in part, be countered with polemical flair.Locke creates an atmosphere of sophistic combat in which his adversary is entangled in shreds of his own verbiage. When Locke strays fromthis style, he does so only to settle into an arcane form of scriptural hermeneutics in which citations of chapter and verse are marshaled in the manner of scholastic disputation. And all this in a work that ends in midsentence, and in which the missing section is acknowledged to be "more than all the rest" (Preface, p. 1 5 5 ). Clearly, the scholarly tradition of neglect has much with which to justify its omission of the FirstTrea tise. Indeed, the onus of justificationappears to lie with those who, in the faceof such reasons, insist on its theoretical significance, both as a worthy if not a necessary precursor to its more studied successor and for the broader role it plays in the understanding of Locke's political and moral thought. It is to these reasons that I turn. Scriptural Politics: An Underlying Discourse The confrontation taken up in the First Treatise is plainly of fundamental and foundationalsig nificance. At the broadest level s My point here is simply that Lockepresents Filmer in such a doubtful light. This view, as with so much else in the FirstTrea tise, is repeatedly emphasized in the preface and the first few chapters. My claim, therefore, is not meant as a challenge to Gordon Schochet, Mark Goldie, and Richard Ashcraft, all of whom have persuasively argued that Filmer's theory was an important, perhaps The Critique of Scriptural Politics 4 1 it involves two uncompromisingly conflictingvis ions of the ori­ gins and basis of political power and authority, the status of fatherhood and the family, the role and significance of property, and the relationships among property, paternity, and authority. Despite the degree to which, in Locke's view, Filmer's motives may be impugned by expedience, his doctrine incoherently pre­ sented, and its implications irredeemably contradictory, nev­ ertheless Filmer does in a systematic manner deny the view that human beings are naturally freeand that thereforethere is a limit to the legitimate authority that fathers, property holders, and governments can have over them. By braiding together mon­ archy, paternity, and property and giving them, as Locke em­ phasizes, an inescapable and extensive reach, Filmer conflates the very terms around which Locke places demarcating and limiting fences. Filmer's views in a general sense sustain the edificeof feudal authority relations. Hence, notwithstanding the plausibility of the reasons that make the First Treatise appear puzzling and of questionable significance, if considered in terms of the issues at stake it is of unquestionable gravity. But there is a danger in viewing the First Treatiseas merely the stage on which this precise confrontation on issues of sover­ eignty, paternity, and property occurs. Despite the stakes at­ tending these issues, if they alone are allowed to determine our view on the First Treatise, we are liable to overlook its multi­ farious echoes and to recognize their collective significance. We are liable to overlook, not only that the conception of political power Locke articulates at the outset of the Second Treatise is different in its specifics and implications fromFilmer's concep­ tion, but that this difference stems from a more general diver­ gence regarding the appropriate language, context, and method even principal, source of royal absolutist doctrines during the seventeenth century.
Recommended publications
  • The Cambridge School Richard Bourke
    The Cambridge School Richard Bourke 1. What are the origins of the Cambridge School? The existence of a “Cambridge School” was first identified by J. G. A. Pocock in the early 1970s, but the description was intended to refer to an approach to the history of ideas that began to achieve prominence in the 1960s. The practitioners whom Pocock had in mind as exemplary members of this School included himself, Quentin Skinner and John Dunn. Over time, it became clear that these three figures had distinct concerns in the fields of intellectual history and political theory. Pocock himself has tended to focus his research on the history of historiography, Skinner on the history of philosophy, and Dunn on political theory understood as a branch of historical inquiry. However, in the 1960s they shared much common ground. By the end of the decade, they had all contributed to methodological debates in the history of ideas. At the same time, each of them had made significant contributions to the study of the history of political thought itself: Pocock, the eldest of the three, had produced a major account of the ideology of ancient constitutionalism in seventeenth-century English political debate; Dunn had produced his classic treatment of the political thought of John Locke; and Skinner had published original studies of the political philosophy of Thomas Hobbes. What distinguished these works was their use of properly historical forms of investigation to explore the writings of past thinkers. This meant eschewing a range of historical fallacies: most importantly, anachronism, prolepsis, and teleology. It also entailed treating ideas as arguments rather than as disembodied entities.
    [Show full text]
  • Oui2.Pdf (2.141Mb)
    COLONIAL CAPITALISM AND THE DILEMMAS OF LIBERALISM: LOCKE, BURKE, WAKEFIELD AND THE BRITISH EMPIRE A Dissertation Presented to the Faculty of the Graduate School of Cornell University in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy by Onur Ulas Ince August 2013 © 2103 Onur Ulas Ince Colonial Capitalism and the Dilemmas of Liberalism: Locke, Burke, Wakefield and the British Empire Onur Ulas Ince, PhD Cornell University 2013 This dissertation offers a historical investigation of liberalism as a unified yet internally variegated intellectual field that has developed in relation to “colonial capitalism.” I examine the impact of colonial economic relations on the historical formation of liberalism, which is often overlooked in the scholarship on the history of political thought. Focusing on the British Empire between the late-seventeenth and early-nineteenth centuries, I analyze three historical cases in which the liberal self-image of capitalism in Britain was contradicted by the manifestly illiberal processes of displacement and coercion in its imperial possessions. I situate this contradiction within the debates on property claims in American colonies, the trade relation between Britain and its Indian dominions, and the labor problem during the colonial settlement of Australia and New Zealand. Corresponding to the three nodal questions of “property,” “exchange,” and “labor,” I analyze the works of John Locke, Edmund Burke, and Edward Gibbon Wakefield as three prominent political theorists who attempted to reconcile the liberal image of Britain as a commercial and pacific society with the illiberal processes of conquest, expropriation, and extraction of British colonialism. Highlighting the global and colonial as opposed to the national or European terrain on which modern economic relations and their political theorization have emerged, I emphasize the need to situate the history of political thought in a global context.
    [Show full text]
  • Peter Laslett (1915–2002)
    Copyright: Alan Macfarlane 2002 (People who have influenced me most, by Alan Macfarlane) Peter Laslett (1915–2002) Peter Laslett was a major intellectual figure in the world of political philosophy, social and demographic history and the organization and communication of knowledge in the second half of the twentieth century. (q.v. ‘100 thinkers’). I first encountered him through his book The World we have lost (1965). This came out in the middle of my D.Phil on witchcraft at Oxford and caused a great stir. I remember it had an enormously stimulating effect on me, along with his famous article on English listings, ‘Clayworth and Cogenhoe’. It was a time when a new social history, based on local historical documents, was being born. Peter’s combination of broad questions, no-nonsense approach, interest in social structure and demography fitted well with a growing interest in the French social historians like Bloch, Braudel, Ariès, Goubert, Ladurie and was a breath of fresh air. I remember arguing with Christopher Hill, who was very dismissive of his attempt to reject the Marxist class war model and of Peter’s scholarship. I also remember starting to encounter the exciting works of Peter’s colleagues at the newly formed ‘Cambridge Group for the History of Population and Social Structure’, in particular Tony Wrigley, at this time. I remember a walk through the Parks at Oxford with Charles Phythian-Adams, when he introduced me both to Ariès, Centuries of Childhood, and Wrigley’s method of family reconstitution. In my research on witchcraft I was already using local records, parish registers, ecclesiastical court records, quarter sessions and assize records.
    [Show full text]
  • Political Theory and the Functions of Intellectual History: a Response to Emmanuel Navon
    Review of International Studies (2003), 29, 151–160 Copyright © British International Studies Association DOI: 10.1017/S026021050300010X Political theory and the functions of intellectual history: a response to Emmanuel Navon DUNCAN S. A. BELL* Words may, through the devotion, the skill, the passion, and the luck of writers prove to be the most powerful thing in the world.1 Introduction In his recent article Emmanuel Navon offers a scathing critique of the so-called ‘Third Debate’ in International Relations (IR). In short, he argues that the issues that he considers to have infused and shaped the ‘first debate’ (clashing visions of human nature) and the ‘second debate’ (clashing visions of knowledge) remain pertinent, indeed central to IR theory. He thus seeks to challenge the ‘very relevance’ of the ‘third debate’, claiming that it is chimerical, composed of hollow post- modernist rhetoric and the re-hashed ideas of constructivism.2 In this brief reply I challenge these assertions, and in so doing offer a broad defence of an alternative mode of historical interpretation. Firstly, I argue that Navon employs a problematic approach to intellectual history and that consequently he misconceives the evolutionary trajectory of the discipline, and the nature of the purported ‘debates’. The critique is then widened into a general defence of inter- pretative contextualism: this hermeneutic method is of great utility in furthering IR’s disciplinary self-understanding, and, perhaps more importantly, it can help to further enrich contemporary theoretical discourse. In the final section I criticise briefly Navon’s inaccurate view of recent IR and in particular his cavalier caricatures of constructivism and postmodernism.
    [Show full text]
  • Early Modern English Kinship in the Long Run: Reflections on Continuity
    Continuity and Change 25 (1), 2010, 15–48. f Cambridge University Press 2010 doi:10.1017/S0268416010000093 Early modern English kinship in the long run: reflections on continuity and change NAOMI TADMOR* ABSTRACT. The article highlights the significance of alliances of blood and marriage in early modern England and beyond, including both positive and negative relations among kin. Examining different historiographical approaches, it emphasizes the role of kinship in explanations of historical change and continuity. Rather than focusing on the isolated nuclear family or, conversely, on an alleged decline of kinship, it highlights the importance of enmeshed patterns of kinship and connectedness. Such patterns were not only important in themselves (whether culturally, socially, econ- omically, or politically), it is suggested, but they also invite new comparisons with other early modern societies, and in the long run. Even patterns typical of present-day ‘new families’ and ‘families of choice’, or aspects of the present-day language of kinship may bring to mind some similarities with notions of kinship and related ‘household-family’ ties characteristic of the early modern period, the article proposes. 1. INTRODUCTION Fifty years ago, an academic field specializing in the history of kinship and the family in early modern England barely existed, yet there was a shared understanding of what that history must have been; today there is a large body of research on English kinship c. 1550–1800, but there is consider- able lack of clarity as to the long-term patterns of continuity and change.1 This tension stands at the heart of this article. Its aim is to examine central trends in the history of English kinship with particular reference to the early modern period, to assess important traits, and to suggest new foci for inquiry.
    [Show full text]
  • JGA Pocock's Barbarism and Religion
    erudition and the republic of letters 2 (2017) 431-458 brill.com/erl J.G.A. Pocock’s Barbarism and Religion B.W. Young Christ Church, Oxford [email protected] Abstract There are no parallels to the career of J.G.A. Pocock in Anglophone scholarship; the singularity of his intellectual trajectory is traced here through constant appeal to his enquiry into the intellectual environments in which Gibbon conceived and wrote his Decline and Fall; the present essay is an attempt at applying much the same interpretative principles at work in the six volumes of Barbarism and Religion both to Pocock and to this culminating study, interpreted as a summa of his practice as an intellectual histori- an. Pocock is an historian, not a philosopher, and this affects his conception of Enlight- enment, which he treats critically as an historian rather than reifying it in the manner of many philosophers. Pocock’s project is to undo the very idea of an ‘Enlightenment Project.’ Barbarism and Religion is not only a study of eighteenth-century conceptions of erudition and the Republic of Letters; it is a contemporary contribution to both. Keywords J.G.A. Pocock – Gibbon – Hobbes – Venturi – Oakeshott – historiography – historical theology – contextual scholarship … He was, we may suspect, a historian first and a philosopher second.1 ∵ 1 J.G.A. Pocock, Barbarism and Religion, 6 vols. (Cambridge, 1999–2016), 6: 132: hereinafter cited in the body of the text as br followed by volume and page number. An earlier version of this © koninklijke brill nv, leiden, 2017 | doi 10.1163/24055069-00204003Downloaded from Brill.com09/26/2021 10:24:05PM via free access <UN> 432 Young Few if any historians at work today can begin to match J.G.A.
    [Show full text]
  • Without Laslett to the Lost Worlds: Quentin Skinner's Early Methodology
    Japanese Journal of Political Science (2021), 22, 144–162 doi:10.1017/S1468109921000104 RESEARCH ARTICLE ’ . Without Laslett to the lost worlds: Quentin Skinner s early methodology Takuya Furuta Hiroshima University: Higashi-Hiroshima, Hiroshima 7390046, Japan Corresponding author. E-mail: [email protected] (Received 28 January 2021; revised 22 April 2021; accepted 27 April 2021; first published online 7 June 2021) https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms Abstract The aim of this paper is to suggest that the emergence of the so-called Cambridge School of history of political thought can best be understood in terms of two competing visions of the relationship between history and social science, focusing on Peter Laslett and Quentin Skinner. Although Laslett is often dis- tinguished as a founder of the Cambridge School, this paper suggests an alternative view by emphasizing the theoretical discontinuity between Laslett and Skinner rather than their continuity. Laslett, a practi- tioner of Karl Manheim’s ideas, promoted the idea of a comprehensive scientific social history, within which intellectual history was located. This paper argues that Skinner broke with Laslett’s idea. For Skinner, (1) Laslett was a positivist who applied the natural scientific model to intellectual history; (2) Laslett’s positivism was actually ‘contextualism’; and (3) the alternative to Laslett’s contextualism was the history of ideology. Skinner’s early methodology was, in part, a rhetorical redescription of ‘ideology’, which opposed both Mannheim and Laslett. As such, this paper focuses on the discursive disconnection between Laslett and Skinner, thus providing a clue to construct a platform for facilitating a further dis- cussion of the history of ideas and the social sciences.
    [Show full text]
  • Anthropology, Family History, and the Concept of Strategy
    IRSH 47 (2002), pp. 423–452 DOI: 10.1017/S002085900200072X # 2002 Internationaal Instituut voor Sociale Geschiedenis Anthropology, Family History, and the Concept of Strategy Pier Paolo Viazzo and Katherine A. Lynch INTRODUCTION In this essay, we consider family history as a common field of substantive and theoretical interest shaped by contacts among several disciplines. These disciplines obviously include social history and population studies, but also – and rather prominently – social anthropology. One major component of the growth of family history has been the increasing amount of attention that historians pay to topics such as marriage, kinship, and the family, which have long been of central significance in the anthropological investigation of social structure. On the other hand, anthropologists have become aware of the serious limitations of synchronic, present-oriented field research, and most of them now probably agree that historical analysis is essential if they are to understand social and cultural processes. This realization has gradually changed many anthropologists from reluctant consumers of historical work into active and often quite enthusiastic producers.1 The fruitfulness of this rapprochement was perhaps best demonstrated as early as the 1970s by the advances made possible by the adoption in family history of the anthropological concept of developmental cycle of the domestic group. Although Chayanov’s work already foreshadowed this concept, it was independently formulated in 1949 by Meyer Fortes, one of the leading British social anthropologists, and further refined by Fortes himself and by his colleagues and pupils in Cambridge in the 1950s.2 When its potentialities were revealed to the nascent field of family history by the works of anthropologists like Goody and Hammel and, 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Quentin Skinner on Encountering the Past*
    QUENTIN SKINNER ON ENCOUNTERING THE PAST* ETRI KOIKKALAINEN AND SAMI SYRJÄMÄKI: When and how Pdid you first become interested in political theory and its history? QUENTIN SKINNER: Before trying to answer, may I first say how deeply grateful I am to you for this interview, and for showing such a generous interest in my work. I shall of course try to answer your questions as honestly as possible, but I need to stress at the outset how conscious I am of the fact that it is all too easy to tidy up and even unintentionally to invent the historical record. I know that some scholars like to tell the story of their intellectual pilgrimage as a se- ries of contingencies, unforeseen developments, one thing unexpect- edly leading to another. But with me the danger is the opposite one. I am a terribly tidy person, and what I have to fight against is the desire to produce a story of smooth progression from my original (and, of course, true and important) insights to their elaboration in a sequence of connected and unfolding historical works. In fact I’m aware that my progress has never been linear; it has included many halts as well as a lot of swerving around as a result of trying to ac- commodate the insights and discoveries of others. So there is no simple story to narrate. * The date of the interview was 4th October, 2001. 34 ON ENCOUNTERING THE PAST It helps me a lot, however, that your initial question asks me how I ever became interested in political theory and its history.
    [Show full text]
  • Domestic Servants and Service in Early Colonial India*
    Modern Asian Studies , () pp. –. © The Author(s) . This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http:// creativecommons.org/licenses/by/./), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited. doi:./SX First published online March Who Is (Not) a Servant, Anyway? Domestic servants and service in early colonial India* NITIN SINHA Leibniz-Zentrum Moderner Orient (Centre for Modern Oriental Studies), Berlin Email: [email protected] Abstract The article deals with one of the under-researched themes of Indian history, which is the history of domestic servants. Thinking about servants raises two fundamental questions: who were they and what did domestic service mean? The identities of a servant as a contract wage earner or a person either belonging as a member or tied to the family through fictive/constructed claims of kinship were not mutually exclusive. Servants’ identity existed in a continuum running from ‘free’ waged coolie on the one hand to ‘unfree’ slave on the other. The article traces the history of domestic servants along two axes: the slave–servant continuum, but, more importantly, the coolie–servant conundrum, which is a lesser-explored field in South Asian labour history or burgeoning scholarship on domesticity and household. Charting through the dense history of terminologies, the space of the city, and legal frameworks adopted by the Company state to regulate servants, it also underscores the difficulties of researching on a subaltern group that is so ubiquitous yet so fragmented in the archives. In order to reconstruct servants’ pasts, we need to shake up our own fields of history writing—urban, labour, gender, and social—to discover servants’ traces wherever they are found.
    [Show full text]
  • The Enlightenment of Sympathy
    The Ethics of Interpretation in Political Theory and Intellectual History Michael L. Frazer, University of East Anglia [email protected] Abstract Intellectual historians who seek to contextualize classic texts and “presentist” political theorists who seek to reclaim their still-valid insights are pursuing different intellectual goals. The two approaches do not have a methodological dispute to be settled in instrumental terms, but an ethical one that can only be settled in terms of competing values. Quentin Skinner’s famous attacks on presentism must therefore be evaluated, not only as part of a methodological program, but also as a collection of ethical arguments. This essay demonstrates why none of Skinner’s arguments can establish that his approach is ethically acceptable while presentism is not. While both contextualist history and presentist theory are justifiably seen as valuable, Skinner’s best justification of the former enterprise is that it can help us achieve the purposes of the latter. Introduction Ethics, under a roughly Habermasian view, is a realm of discourse in which any of us may be called to offer justifications of our evaluative stances in terms of values that we expect our interlocutors to share. Sometimes, a reasonable response to a discursive demand for justification is “That’s none of your business!” In other contexts, however, evading another’s demand for justification would itself be unjustified; whether, when and why this is the case is itself a matter of further ethical debate. Moral philosophers and political theorists have devoted considerable energy to analyzing and evaluating the sort of ethical justifications that individuals offer each other across a wide 1 variety of discursive settings.
    [Show full text]
  • PETER LASLETT Copyright © British Academy 2005 – All Rights Reserved
    PETER LASLETT Copyright © British Academy 2005 – all rights reserved Thomas Peter Ruffell Laslett 1915–2001 PETER LASLETT was born in Bedford on 18 December 1915 and died on 8 November 2001 in his eighty-sixth year. He was one of seven children of George Henry Ruffell Laslett, a Baptist minister, and his wife Eveline Elizabeth, née Alden. Much of his childhood was spent in Oxford but his secondary education took place in the Grammar School at Watford, where his father had become minister. Both his paternal grandparents belonged to the Plymouth Brethren, while his mother’s family, the Aldens, were closely connected with the Alden Press. Peter himself saw his upbringing as puritanical (no dancing, no cinema), and retained through- out his life a stern critical distance from the English establishment, along with a keen (and sometimes gleeful) interest in its workings: an instinctive nonconformist, if no sectarian. At school he showed early promise as an historian, but much regretted in later life that he was obliged to give up mathematics before learning the calculus, ‘leaving me at a permanent disadvantage’.1 In 1935 he went up to St John’s College, Cambridge to read history, graduating with a double first in 1938. Despite some irritation at the con- descension of wealthier public school contemporaries, he played an active part in college life, rowing at Henley for the Lady Margaret boat club. After graduation he spent eighteen months in research in the History Faculty before joining the Fleet Air Arm in 1940. Of the men who appeared in his degree photograph, Peter subsequently noted, seven did 1 English transcript of an interview with the Italian journal Passato e Presente (1989).
    [Show full text]