Which Voting Systems Are Statistically Robust?

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Which Voting Systems Are Statistically Robust? Statistical Robustness of Voting Rules Ronald L. Rivest∗ and Emily Sheny Abstract you get on a rainy day (when only some fraction of the vot- ers show up). (We assume here that the chance of a voter We introduce a notion of “statistical robustness” for voting showing up on a rainy day is independent of his preferences.) rules. We say that a voting rule is statistically robust if the winner for a profile of ballots is most likely to be the winner We show that plurality voting is statistically robust, of any random sample of the profile, for any positive sam- while—perhaps surprisingly—approval voting, STV, and ple size. We show that some voting rules, such as plurality, most other familiar voting rules are not statistically robust. veto, and random ballot, are statistically robust, while others, We consider the property of being statistically robust a such as approval, score voting, Borda, single transferable vote desirable one for a voting rule, and thus consider lack of (STV), Copeland, and Maximin are not statistically robust. such statistical robustness a defect in voting rules. In gen- Furthermore, we show that any positional scoring rule whose eral, we consider a voting rule to be somewhat defective if scoring vector contains at least three different values (i.e., any applying the voting rule to a sample of the ballots may give positional scoring rule other than t-approval for some t) is not misleading guidance regarding the likely winner for the en- statistically robust. tire profile. Keywords: social choice, voting rule, sampling, statistical One reason why statistical robustness may be desirable robustness is for “ballot-auditing” (Lindeman and Stark 2012), which attempts to confirm the result of the election by checking that the winner of a sample is the same as the overall winner. 1 Introduction Similarly, in an AI system that combines the recommen- It is well known that polling a sample of voters before an dations of expert subsystems according to some aggregation election may yield useful information about the likely out- rule, it may be of interest to know whether aggregating the come of the election, if the sample is large enough and the recommendations of a sample of the experts is most likely voters respond honestly. to yield the same result as aggregating the recommendations It is less well known that the effectiveness of a sample in of all experts. In some situations, some experts may have predicting an election outcome also depends on the voting transient faults or be otherwise temporarily unavailable (in a rule (social choice function) used. manner independent of their recommendations) so that only We say a voting rule is “statistically robust” if for any a sample of recommendations is available for aggregation. profile the winner of any random sample of that profile is Since our definition is new, there is little or no directly most likely to be the same as the (most likely) winner for the related previous work. The closest work may be that of complete profile. While the sample result may be “noisy” Walsh and Xia (Walsh and Xia 2011), who study various due to sample variations, if the voting rule is statistically “lot-based” voting rules with respect to their computational robust the most common winner(s) for a sample will be the resistance to strategic voting. In their terminology, a voting same as the winner(s) of the complete profile. rule of the form “Lottery-Then-X” (a.k.a. “LotThenX”) first To coin some amusing terminology, we might say that a takes a random sample of the ballots, and then applies voting statistically robust voting rule is “weather resistant”—you rule X (where X may be plurality, Borda, etc.) to the sam- expect to get the same election outcome if the election day ple. Their work is not concerned, as ours is, with the fidelity weather is sunny (when all voters show up at the polls) as of the sample winner to the winner for the complete profile. ∗ Amar (Amar 1984) proposes actual use of the “random bal- Computer Science and Artificial Intelligence Laboratory, lot” method. Procaccia et al. (Procaccia, Rosenschein, and Massachusetts Institute of Technology, Cambridge, MA 02139 Kaminka 2007) study a related but different notion of “ro- [email protected] bustness” that models the effect of voter errors. yComputer Science and Artificial Intelligence Laboratory, Massachusetts Institute of Technology, Cambridge, MA 02139 The rest of this paper is organized as follows. Section 2 [email protected] introduces notation and the voting rules we consider. We Copyright c 2012, Association for the Advancement of Artificial define the notion of statistical robustness for a voting rule in Intelligence (www.aaai.org). All rights reserved. Section 3, determine whether several familiar voting rules are statistically robust in Section 4, and close with some dis- eliminated. Each ballot is counted as a vote for its highest- cussion and open questions. ranked alternative that has not yet been eliminated. The winner of the election is the last alternative remaining. 2 Preliminaries • Plurality with runoff : The winner is the winner of the Ballots, Profiles, Alternatives. Assume a profile P = pairwise election between the two alternatives that receive (B1;B2;:::;Bn) containing n ballots will be used to de- the most first-choice votes. A = fA ;A ;:::;A g termine a single winner from a set 1 2 m • Copeland: The winner is an alternative that maximizes m of alternatives. The form of a ballot depends on the vot- the number of alternatives it beats in pairwise elections. ing rule used. We may view a profile as either a sequence or a multiset; it may contain repeated items (identical ballots). • Maximin: The winner is an alternative whose lowest score in any pairwise election against another alternative is the greatest among all the alternatives. Social choice functions. Assume that a voting rule (social choice function) f maps profiles to a single outcome (one Other (non-preferential) voting rules we consider are: of the alternatives): for any profile P , f(P ) produces the • Score voting (also known as range voting): Each allow- winner for the profile P . able ballot type is associated with a vector that specifies We allow f to be randomized, in order for “ties” to be a score for each alternative. The winner is the alternative handled reasonably. Our development could alternatively that maximizes its total score. have allowed f to output the set of tied winners; we prefer allowing randomization, so that f always outputs a single • Approval (Brams and Fishburn 1978; Laslier and Sanver alternative. In our analysis, however, we do consider the set 2010): Each ballot gives a score of 1 or 0 to each alter- ML(f(P )) of most likely winners for a given profile. native. The winner is an alternative whose total score is Thus, we say that A is a “most likely winner” of P if no maximized. other alternative is more likely to be f(P ). There may be • Random ballot (Gibbard 1977) (also known as random several most likely winners of a profile P . For most profiles dictator): A single ballot is selected uniformly at random and most voting rules, however, we expect f to act deter- from the profile, and the alternative named on the selected ministically, so there is a single most likely winner. ballot is the winner of the election. Often the social choice function f will be neutral— symmetric with respect to the alternatives—so that chang- 3 Sampling and Statistical Robustness ing the names of the alternatives won’t change the outcome Sampling. The profile P is the universe from which the distribution of f on any profile. While there is nothing in sample will be drawn. our development that requires that f be neutral, we shall sampling process restrict attention in this paper to neutral social choice func- We define a to be a randomized function G P n tions. Thus, for example, a tie-breaking rule used by f in that takes as input a profile of size and an integer k 1 ≤ k ≤ n S this paper will not depend on the names of the alternatives; parameter ( ) and produces as output a sample P k S it will pick one of the tied alternatives uniformly at random. of of expected size , where is a subset (or sub-multiset) P We do assume that social-choice function f is anony- of . mous—symmetric with respect to voters: reordering the bal- We consider three kinds of sampling: lots of a profile leaves the outcome unchanged. • Sampling without replacement. Here GW OR(P; k) pro- We will consider the following voting rules. (For more duces a set S of size exactly k chosen uniformly without details on voting rules, see (Brams and Fishburn 2002), for replacement from P . example.) • Sampling with replacement. Here GWR(P; k) produces Many of the voting rules are preferential voting rules; that a multiset S of size exactly k chosen uniformly with re- is, each Bi gives a linear order Ai1 Ai2 ::: Aim. placement from P . (In the rest of the paper, we will omit the symbols and just • Binomial sampling. Here G (P; k) produces a sample write Ai1Ai2 :::Aim, for example.) BIN S of expected size k by including each ballot in P in the • A positional scoring rule is defined by a vector ~α = sample S independently with probability p = k=n. hα1; : : : ; αmi; we assume αi ≥ αj for i ≤ j. Thus, the output of the voting rule on a sample might be Alternative i gets α points for every ballot that ranks al- j denoted as f(S), or f(G(P; k)), depending on the situation.
Recommended publications
  • Governance in Decentralized Networks
    Governance in decentralized networks Risto Karjalainen* May 21, 2020 Abstract. Effective, legitimate and transparent governance is paramount for the long-term viability of decentralized networks. If the aim is to design such a governance model, it is useful to be aware of the history of decision making paradigms and the relevant previous research. Towards such ends, this paper is a survey of different governance models, the thinking behind such models, and new tools and structures which are made possible by decentralized blockchain technology. Governance mechanisms in the wider civil society are reviewed, including structures and processes in private and non-profit governance, open-source development, and self-managed organisations. The alternative ways to aggregate preferences, resolve conflicts, and manage resources in the decentralized space are explored, including the possibility of encoding governance rules as automatically executed computer programs where humans or other entities interact via a protocol. Keywords: Blockchain technology, decentralization, decentralized autonomous organizations, distributed ledger technology, governance, peer-to-peer networks, smart contracts. 1. Introduction This paper is a survey of governance models in decentralized networks, and specifically in networks which make use of blockchain technology. There are good reasons why governance in decentralized networks is a topic of considerable interest at present. Some of these reasons are ideological. We live in an era where detailed information about private individuals is being collected and traded, in many cases without the knowledge or consent of the individuals involved. Decentralized technology is seen as a tool which can help protect people against invasions of privacy. Decentralization can also be viewed as a reaction against the overreach by state and industry.
    [Show full text]
  • Democracy Lost: a Report on the Fatally Flawed 2016 Democratic Primaries
    Democracy Lost: A Report on the Fatally Flawed 2016 Democratic Primaries Election Justice USA | ElectionJusticeUSA.org | [email protected] Table of Contents I. INTRODUCTORY MATERIAL........................................................................................................2 A. ABOUT ELECTION JUSTICE USA...............................................................................................2 B. EXECUTIVE SUMMARY...............................................................................................................2 C. ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS..............................................................................................................7 II. SUMMARY OF DIRECT EVIDENCE FOR ELECTION FRAUD, VOTER SUPPRESSION, AND OTHER IRREGULARITIES.......................................................................................................7 A. VOTER SUPPRESSION..................................................................................................................7 B. REGISTRATION TAMPERING......................................................................................................8 C. ILLEGAL VOTER PURGING.........................................................................................................8 D. EVIDENCE OF FRAUDULENT OR ERRONEOUS VOTING MACHINE TALLIES.................9 E. MISCELLANEOUS........................................................................................................................10 F. ESTIMATE OF PLEDGED DELEGATES AFFECTED................................................................11
    [Show full text]
  • Crowdsourcing Applications of Voting Theory Daniel Hughart
    Crowdsourcing Applications of Voting Theory Daniel Hughart 5/17/2013 Most large scale marketing campaigns which involve consumer participation through voting makes use of plurality voting. In this work, it is questioned whether firms may have incentive to utilize alternative voting systems. Through an analysis of voting criteria, as well as a series of voting systems themselves, it is suggested that though there are no necessarily superior voting systems there are likely enough benefits to alternative systems to encourage their use over plurality voting. Contents Introduction .................................................................................................................................... 3 Assumptions ............................................................................................................................... 6 Voting Criteria .............................................................................................................................. 10 Condorcet ................................................................................................................................. 11 Smith ......................................................................................................................................... 14 Condorcet Loser ........................................................................................................................ 15 Majority ...................................................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • 2016 US Presidential Election Herrade Igersheim, François Durand, Aaron Hamlin, Jean-François Laslier
    Comparing Voting Methods: 2016 US Presidential Election Herrade Igersheim, François Durand, Aaron Hamlin, Jean-François Laslier To cite this version: Herrade Igersheim, François Durand, Aaron Hamlin, Jean-François Laslier. Comparing Voting Meth- ods: 2016 US Presidential Election. 2018. halshs-01972097 HAL Id: halshs-01972097 https://halshs.archives-ouvertes.fr/halshs-01972097 Preprint submitted on 7 Jan 2019 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. WORKING PAPER N° 2018 – 55 Comparing Voting Methods: 2016 US Presidential Election Herrade Igersheim François Durand Aaron Hamlin Jean-François Laslier JEL Codes: D72, C93 Keywords : Approval voting, range voting, instant runoff, strategic voting, US Presidential election PARIS-JOURDAN SCIENCES ECONOMIQUES 48, BD JOURDAN – E.N.S. – 75014 PARIS TÉL. : 33(0) 1 80 52 16 00= www.pse.ens.fr CENTRE NATIONAL DE LA RECHERCHE SCIENTIFIQUE – ECOLE DES HAUTES ETUDES EN SCIENCES SOCIALES ÉCOLE DES PONTS PARISTECH – ECOLE NORMALE SUPÉRIEURE INSTITUT NATIONAL DE LA RECHERCHE AGRONOMIQUE – UNIVERSITE PARIS 1 Comparing Voting Methods: 2016 US Presidential Election Herrade Igersheim☦ François Durand* Aaron Hamlin✝ Jean-François Laslier§ November, 20, 2018 Abstract. Before the 2016 US presidential elections, more than 2,000 participants participated to a survey in which they were asked their opinions about the candidates, and were also asked to vote according to different alternative voting rules, in addition to plurality: approval voting, range voting, and instant runoff voting.
    [Show full text]
  • Landry, Celeste
    HB 5404: Study Ranked-Choice Voting in CT, Committee on Government Administration and Elections March 4, 2020 testimony by Celeste Landry, 745 University Ave, Boulder, CO 80302 Bio: I have been researching voting methods since 2012 and have given a variety of Voting Methods presentations including at the 2018 LWVUS convention, the 2019 Free and Equal Electoral Reform Symposium and the 2020 CO Dept of State Alternative Voting Method Stakeholder Group meeting. Four Proposed Amendments: Amendments #1 and #2 below address language in the current text, but Amendments #3 and #4 provide for better and broader resolutions to the bill’s limitations. Issue #1. The description of ranked-choice voting (RCV) in HB5404 is too limited. For instance, the 2018 Maine Congressional District 2 election would NOT fit the definition below: 6 are defeated and until one candidate receives over fifty per cent of the 7 votes cast, and (3) the candidate receiving over fifty per cent of the votes 8 cast is deemed to have been elected to such office. Such study shall Example: The Maine CD2 winner, Jared Golden, did NOT receive over 50% of the votes cast (144,813 out of 289,624). More people preferred Golden’s opponents to Golden. In the last round, Golden received over 50% of the votes if you only count the non-exhausted ballots. The definition of RCV in the bill effectively claims that more than two thousand cast votes were actually not cast! 2018 Maine CD2 election results: https://www.maine.gov/sos/cec/elec/results/results18.html#Nov6 Resolution: The definition should read 6 are defeated and until one candidate receives over fifty per cent of the 7 votes cast on non-exhausted ballots, and (3) the candidate receiving over fifty per cent of the votes 8 cast on non-exhausted ballots is deemed to have been elected to such office.
    [Show full text]
  • Least-Resistance Consensus: Applying Via Negativa to Decision-Making ∗
    Least-Resistance Consensus: applying Via Negativa to decision-making ∗ Aleksander Kampa [email protected] July 2019 Abstract This paper introduces Least-Resistance Consensus (LRC), a cardinal voting system that focuses entirely on measuring resistance. It is based on the observation that our \negative gut feeling" is often a strong, reliable indicator and that our dislikes are stronger than our likes. Measuring resistance rather than acceptance is therefore likely to provide a more accurate gauge when a choice between multiple options has to be made. But LRC is not just a voting system. It encourages an iterative process of consensus- seeking in which possible options are proposed, discussed, amended and then either discarded or kept for a further round of voting. LRC also proposes to take the structure of group opinion into account, with a view not only to minimizing overall group resistance but also to avoiding, as much as possible, there being sizeable groups of strong dissenters. 1 Introduction In Western societies, the opinion that parliamentary democracy based on majority rule is the best possible form of government is widely held. We do know that minority opinions are not always represented and, as is the case in the UK with its first-past-the-post system, a party can gain an absolute majority with far fewer than half of the votes, but this seems to be considered a minor issue. Not just in government but at all levels of society, majority voting holds sway. Members of tribal societies in Africa and elsewhere, who are used to the lengthy and complex processes needed for reaching a wide consensus among community members, would probably call the idea of majority voting primitive.
    [Show full text]
  • Enhanced Tally Scheme for the DEMOS End-2-End Verifiable E
    Enhanced Tally Scheme for the DEMOS End-2-End Verifiable E-voting Thomas Souliotis Master of Science School of Informatics University of Edinburgh 2018 Abstract E-voting can solve many problems that traditional conventional voting systems can- not, in a secure mathematically proven way. The DEMOS e-voting system is one of the many examples of modern state of the art e-voting systems. The DEMOS e-voting system has many desirable properties and uses many novel techniques. However, DE- MOS has some problems that need to be solved, so as to extend its usability. In this dissertation, we explain how DEMOS works and what makes it so special. Moreover, we extend DEMOS usability by providing a new way of conducting enhanced voting schemes in the context of DEMOS. This is achieved by changing the way that the ballots are encoded and by providing a new zero knowledge proof approach. Further- more, our work is supported by the necessary security proofs, while a first practical implementation is also provided. We also provide a novel theoretical proof of concept, for far more complex voting systems like STV, which might be the first of its kind for homomorphic systems. Finally, we provide a new zero knowledge proof of a shuffle argument, which can be used for applications outside of this dissertation purposes. Keywords: E-voting, DEMOS, Standard Model, Shuffle Proofs, E2E Verifiability, Receipt-freeness, Borda count, Preferential Voting, STV, Homomorphic Encryption. iii Acknowledgements This project was supervised by professor Aggelos Kiayias. His background and exper- tise helped me a lot during our discussions for further understanding and developing complex protocols.
    [Show full text]
  • Best Democracy US V2.0
    Inclusive Democracy for the 99% William T. Wiley - Do We Have A Lot In Common Jesse Kumin Founder & Exec. Dir. Best Democracy Inclusive Democracy for the 99% Directory Would You Rather Be Included? Slide 4 King’s Process, Observation, We Have a Problem Slides 5 - 8 Slavery and US Elections Slides 9 - 15 Oligarchy and the Cartel Parties Slides 16 - 18 Predetermined Elections, Concentrated and Dispersed Power Slides 19 - 22 Families of Electoral Systems, Majoritarian and Proportional Slides 23 - 26 Voter Engagement, At Large, Distortions in Representation Slides 27 - 31 Debates and Other Obstructions to Democracy Slides 32 & 33 Remedies and Rationale Slides 34 - 40 How Proportional Representation Systems Work Slides 41 - 51 Should Voters and Candidates Support Pro Rep? Slides 52 & 53 Hybrid Proportional Representation (HPR) Slide 54 Before and After HPR Sample Systems Slides 55 - 81 Range/Score Voting Slide 82 Abolish or Maybe Rescue the Senate Slides 83 & 84 Democratize the Supreme Court Slide 85 Attention and Action Plans Slides 86 - 90 Credits Slide 91 Would you rather be included or excluded from decision making? Everyone who votes wants to be included, otherwise we wouldn’t vote. Proportional systems include everyone in outcomes. 2/3rds of the US “Voting Eligible Population” voted in the 2020 Presidential election, high for the US. A completely biased sample of engaged voters, from this 2/3rds, who saw and completed the Best Democracy Election Survey, preferred Proportional Representation, to be included in decision making, over “Winner Take All”, that excludes large blocks of voters. The outlier was a troll. In an informal survey at a Libertarian Lunch, 14 of 14 attendees voted for Proportional Representation, after this presentation.
    [Show full text]
  • STAR Voting FAQ
    STAR Voting FAQ: What is STAR Voting? ● STAR Voting is a more expressive voting method using a 5 star ballot. ● Give each candidate a score from 0 - 5. ● If you don’t have a preference you can give candidates the same scores. ● Those you leave blank get a zero. What’s wrong with our current system? ● “Choose One” Plurality Voting is only accurate when there are two candidates in the race. That’s why we have a two party system. ● When there are more than 2 candidates, vote splitting can cause a majority coalition to end up divided and conquered. (The Spoiler Effect is one kind of vote splitting.) ● Voters in our current system often have to be strategic and vote lesser-evil. Are you talking about the electoral college? ● The voting system itself and the electoral college are different, but vote splitting, which STAR eliminates, was a major factor every time the electoral college has failed to elect the winner of the popular vote. Is this the “Jungle Primary” California Top 2 system? ● No! That’s the system we already use for Oregon nonpartisan elections in places like Eugene, Multnomah County, Lane County, and more. What happens in the runoff if I gave both finalists the same scores? ● All your scores still make a difference and help your favorites advance. ● If you gave both finalists the same scores, that is a vote of no-preference between those two. You like or dislike them equally. ● The ability to give candidates a tie is critical for maintaining accurate elections when there are many candidates in a race.
    [Show full text]
  • Voting Systems: from Method to Algorithm
    Voting Systems: From Method to Algorithm A Thesis Presented to The Faculty of the Com puter Science Department California State University Channel Islands In (Partial) Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree M asters of Science in Com puter Science b y Christopher R . Devlin Advisor: Michael Soltys December 2019 © 2019 Christopher R. Devlin ALL RIGHTS RESERVED APPROVED FOR MS IN COMPUTER SCIENCE Advisor: Dr. Michael Soltys Date Name: Dr. Bahareh Abbasi Date Name: Dr. Vida Vakilian Date APPROVED FOR THE UNIVERITY Name Date Acknowledgements I’d like to thank my wife, Eden Byrne for her patience and support while I completed this Masters Degree. I’d also like to thank Dr. Michael Soltys for his guidance and mentorship. Additionally I’d like to thank the faculty and my fellow students at CSUCI who have given nothing but assistance and encouragement during my time here. Voting Systems: From Method to Algorithm Christopher R. Devlin December 18, 2019 Abstract Voting and choice aggregation are used widely not just in poli­ tics but in business decision making processes and other areas such as competitive bidding procurement. Stakeholders and others who rely on these systems require them to be fast, efficient, and, most impor­ tantly, fair. The focus of this thesis is to illustrate the complexities inherent in voting systems. The algorithms intrinsic in several voting systems are made explicit as a way to simplify choices among these systems. The systematic evaluation of the algorithms associated with choice aggregation will provide a groundwork for future research and the implementation of these tools across public and private spheres.
    [Show full text]
  • Which Voting System Do Voters Prefer? Survey Report
    WHICH VOTING SYSTEM DO VOTERS PREFER? SURVEY REPORT FEBRUARY 2017 ROBIN QUIRKE AND TOM BOWERMAN ABSTRACT Public opinion polls reflected Trump and Clinton to be extraordinarily unpopular among Americans, and with the current plurality voting system, voters had virtually no hope of a third party candidate winning the 2016 presidential election. Do the current electoral structural processes impede preferred candidates from winning and does the two-party power structure simply protect the status quo? Some voting experts claim that alternative voting systems more honestly reflect the will of the people, but policy reform requires constituent support. This report describes five sequential studies which together explore the question: would Americans be open to an alternative voting system for presidential elections? Although a majority of the study participants supported the idea of revamping the current voting system, there was a lack of strong support for the specific alternative voting systems tested in these five studies. EXPLORING VOTING SYSTEM ALTERNATIVES 1. Introduction For most Americans, voting is the only means through which they exercise civic power. For a genuine and principled democracy, that may be sufficient, but authorities from several disciplines, including the fields of political science and mathematics, commonly express concern that the prevalent voting system used in most U.S. elections does not facilitate a fair level of representation. For example, The United States’ electoral practices received a moderately low score by the international Electoral Integrity Project compared to other democratic countries (in 2012, the U.S. received a score of 70, Norway received the highest score of 87 and Romania received the lowest score of 58), which is partially due to concerns on the fairness of U.S.
    [Show full text]
  • An Analysis of Random Elections with Large Numbers of Voters Arxiv
    An Analysis of Random Elections with Large Numbers of Voters∗ Matthew Harrison-Trainor September 8, 2020 Abstract In an election in which each voter ranks all of the candidates, we consider the head- to-head results between each pair of candidates and form a labeled directed graph, called the margin graph, which contains the margin of victory of each candidate over each of the other candidates. A central issue in developing voting methods is that there can be cycles in this graph, where candidate A defeats candidate B, B defeats C, and C defeats A. In this paper we apply the central limit theorem, graph homology, and linear algebra to analyze how likely such situations are to occur for large numbers of voters. There is a large literature on analyzing the probability of having a majority winner; our analysis is more fine-grained. The result of our analysis is that in elections with the number of voters going to infinity, margin graphs that are more cyclic in a certain precise sense are less likely to occur. 1 Introduction The Condorcet paradox is a situation in social choice theory where every candidate in an election with three or more alternatives would lose, in a head-to-head election, to some other candidate. For example, suppose that in an election with three candidates A, B, and C, and three voters, the voter's preferences are as follows: arXiv:2009.02979v1 [econ.TH] 7 Sep 2020 First choice Second choice Third choice Voter 1 A B C Voter 2 B C A Voter 3 C A B There is no clear winner, for one can argue that A cannot win as two of the three voters prefer C to A, that B cannot win as two of the three voters prefer A to B, and that C cannot win as two of the three voters prefer B to C.
    [Show full text]