<<

C H E N N I N G Y A N G

The law of parity conservation and other symmetry laws of

Nobel Lecture, December 11, 1957

It is a pleasure and a great privilege to have this opportunity to discuss with you the question of parity conservation and other symmetry laws. We shall be concerned first with the general aspects of the role of the symmetry laws in physics; second, with the development that led to the disproof of parity conservation; and last, with a discussion of some other symmetry laws which physicists have learned through experience, but which do not yet together form an integral and conceptually simple pattern. The interesting and very exciting developments since parity conservation was disproved, will be cov- ered by Dr. Lee in his lecture 1.

I

The existence of symmetry laws is in full accordance with our daily ex- perience. The simplest of these symmetries, the isotropy and homogeneity of space, are concepts that date back to the early history of human thought. The invariance of physical laws under a coordinate transformation of uni- form velocity, also known as the invariance under Galilean transformations, is a more sophisticated symmetry that was early recognized, and formed one of the corner-stones of Newtonian mechanics. Consequences of these sym- metry principles were greatly exploited by physicists of the past centuries and gave rise to many important results. A good example in this direction is the theorem that in an isotropic solid there are only two elastic constants. Another type of consequences of the symmetry laws relates to the con- servation laws. It is common knowledge today that in general a symmetry principle (or equivalently an invariance principle) generates a conservation law. For example, the invariance of physical laws under space displacement has as a consequence the conservation of momentum, the invariance under space rotation has as a consequence the conservation of angular momentum. While the importance of these conservation laws was fully understood, their close relationship with the symmetry laws seemed not to have been clearly recognized until the beginning of the twentieth century 2. (Cf. Fig. 1.) 394 1957 C.N.YANG

Fig. 1 .

With the advent of special and , the symmetry laws gained new importance. Their connection with the dynamic laws of physics takes on a much more integrated and interdependent relationship than in , where logically the symmetry laws were only conse- quences of the dynamical laws that by chance possess the symmetries. Also in the relativity theories the realm of the symmetry laws was greatly en- riched to include invariances that were by no means apparent from daily experience. Their validity rather was deduced from, or was later confirmed by complicated experimentation. Let me emphasize that the conceptual sim- plicity and intrinsic beauty of the symmetries that so evolve from complex are for the physicists great sources of encouragement. One learns to hope that Nature possesses an order that one may aspire to comprehend. It was, however, not until the development of that the use of the symmetry principles began to permeate into the very language of physics. The quantum numbers that designate the states of a system are often identical with those that represent the symmetries of the system. It in- deed is scarcely possible to overemphasize the role played by the symmetry principles in quantum mechanics. To quote two examples: The general struc- ture of the Periodic Table is essentially a direct consequence of the isotropy of Coulomb’s law. The existence of the antiparticles - namely the positron, the , and the antineutron - were theoretically anticipated as con- sequences of the symmetry of physical laws with respect to Lorentz trans- formations. In both cases Nature seems to take advantage of the simple mathematical representations of the symmetry laws. When one pauses to consider the elegance and the beautiful perfection of the mathematical rea- soning involved and contrast it with the complex and far-reaching physical PARITY CONSERVATION AND OTHER SYMMETRY LAWS 395 consequences, a deep sense of respect for the power of the symmetry laws never fails to develop. One of the symmetry principles, the symmetry between the left and the right, is as old as human civilization. The question whether Nature exhibits such symmetry was debated at length by philosophers of the pasts. Of course, in daily life, left and right are quite distinct from each other. Our hearts, for example, are on our left sides. The language that people use both in the orient and the occident, carries even a connotation that right is good and left is evil. However, the laws of physics have always shown complete symmetry between the left and the right, the asymmetry in daily life being attributed to the accidental asymmetry of the environment, or initial conditions in organic life. To illustrate the point, we mention that if there existed a mirror- image man with his heart on his right side, his internal organs reversed com- pared to ours, and in fact his body molecules, for example sugar molecules, the mirror image of ours, and if he ate the mirror image of the food that we eat, then according to the laws of physics, he should function as well as we do. The law of right-left symmetry was used in , but was not of any great practical importance there. One reason for this derives from the fact that right-left symmetry is a discrete symmetry, unlike rotational sym- metry which is continuous. Whereas the continuous symmetries always lead to conservation laws in classical mechanics, a discrete symmetry does not. With the introduction of quantum mechanics, however, this difference between the discrete and continuous symmetries disappears. The law of right-left symmetry then leads also to a conservation law: the conservation of parity. The discovery of this conservation law dates back to 1924 when Laporte 4 found that energy levels in complex can be classified into « gestriche- ne » and « ungestrichene » types, or in more recent language, even and odd levels. In transitions between these levels during which one photon is emitted or absorbed, Laporte found that the level always changes from even to odd or vice versa. Anticipating later developments, we remark that the evenness or oddness of the levels was later referred to as the parity of the levels. Even levels are defined to have parity +1, odd levels parity -1 . One also defines the photon emitted or absorbed in the usual atomic transitions to have odd parity. Laporte’s rule can then be formulated as the statement that in an atomic transition with the emission of a photon, the parity of the initial state is equal to the total parity of the final state, i.e. the product of the parities of the final atomic state and the photon emitted. In other words, parity is conserved, or unchanged, in the transition. 396 1957 C. N. YANG In 1927 Wigners took the critical and profound step to prove that the empirical rule of Laporte is a consequence of the reflection invariance, or right-left symmetry, of the electromagnetic forces in the . This fun- damental idea was rapidly absorbed into the language of physics. Since right- left symmetry was unquestioned also in other interactions, the idea was fur- ther taken over into new domains as the subject matter of physics extended into nuclear reactions, mesoninteractions, and strange-particle phys- ics. One became accustomed to the idea of nuclear parities as well as atomic parities, and one discusses and measures the intrinsic parities of the mesons. Throughout these developments the concept of parity and the law of parity conservation proved to be extremely fruitful, and the success had in turn been taken as a support for the validity of right-left symmetry.

II

Against such a background the so-called puzzle developed in the last few years. Before explaining the meaning of this puzzle it is best to go a little bit into a classification of the forces that act between subatomic particles, a classification which the physicists have learned through experience to use in the last 50 years. We list the four classes of interactions below. The strength of these interactions is indicated in the column on the right.

The strongest interactions are the nuclear interactions which include the forces that bind nuclei together and the interaction between the nuclei and the mesons. It also includes the interactions that give rise to the observed strange-particle production. The second class of interactions are the electromagnetic interactions of which physicists know a great deal. In fact, the crowning achievement of the physicists of the 19th century was a detailed understanding of the electromagnetic forces. With the advent of quantum mechanics, this understanding of electromagnetic forces gives in principle an accurate, integral and detailed description of practically all the physical and chemical phenomena of our daily experience. The third class of forces, the weak interactions, was first discovered around the beginning of PARITY CONSERVATION AND OTHER SYMMETRY LAWS 397 this century in the β-radioactivity of nuclei, a phenomena which especially in the last 25 years has been extensively studied experimentally. With the discovery of decays and µ capture it was noticed independently 6 by Klein, by Tiomno and Wheeler, and by Lee, Rosenbluth and me, that these interactions have roughly the same strengths as β-interactions. They are called weak interactions, and in the last few years their rank has been con- stantly added to through the discovery of many other weak interactions responsible for the decay of the strange particles. The consistent and striking pattern of their almost uniform strength remains today one of the most tan- talizing phenomena - a topic which we shall come back to later. About the last class of forces, the gravitational forces, we need only mention that in atomic and nuclear interactions they are so weak as to be completely neg- ligible in all the observations with existing techniques. Now to return to the puzzle. In 1953, Dalitz and Fabri 7 pointed out that in the decay of the and τ mesons

some information about the spins and parities of the τ and mesons can be obtained. The argument is very roughly as follows. It has previously been determined that the parity of a π meson is odd (i.e. = - 1). Let us first neglect the effects due to the relative motion of the π mesons. To conserve parity in the decays, the meson must have the total parity, or in other words, the product parity, of two π mesons, which is even (i.e. = + 1). Similarly, the τ meson must have the total parity of three π mesons, which is odd. Actually because of the relative motion of the π mesons the argument was not as simple and unambiguous as we just discussed. To render the ar- gument conclusive and definitive it was necessary to study experimentally the momentum and angular distribution of the π mesons. Such studies were made in many laboratories, and by the spring of 1956 the accumulated ex- perimental data seemed to unambiguously indicate, along the lines of rea- soning discussed above, that ϑ and τ do not have the same parity, and con- sequently are not the same particle. This conclusion, however, was in marked contradiction with other experimental results which also became definite at about the same time. The contradiction was known as the ϑ -τ puzzle and was widely discussed. To recapture the atmosphere of that time allow me to quote a paragraph concerning the conclusion that and τ are not the same 398 1957 C.N.YANG particle from a report entitled « Present Knowledge about the New Par- ticles » which I gave at the International Conference on 8 in Seattle, in September 1956. « However it will not do to jump to hasty conclusions. This is because ex- perimentally the K mesons (i.e. τ and ϑ) seem all to have the same masses and the same lifetimes. The masses are known to an accuracy of, say, from 2 to 10 electron masses, or a fraction of a percent, and the lifetimes are known to an accuracy of, say, 20 percent. Since particles which have different and parity values, and which have strong interactions with the nucleons and pions, are not expected to have identical masses and lifetimes, one is forced to keep the question open whether the inference mentioned above that the and are not the same particle is conclusive. Parenthetically, I might add that the inference would certainly have been regarded as conclusive, and in fact more well-founded than many inferences in physics, had it not been for the anomaly of mass and lifetime degeneracies. » The situation that the physicist found himself in at that time has been likened to a man in a dark room groping for an outlet. He is aware of the fact that in some direction there must be a door which would lead him out of his predicament. But in which direction? That direction turned out to lie in the faultiness of the law of parity con- servation for the weak interactions. But to uproot an accepted concept one must first demonstrate why the previous evidence in its favor were insuffi- cient. Dr. Lee and I9 examined this question in detail, and in May 1956 we came to the following conclusions: (A) Past experiments on the weak inter- actions had actually no bearing on the question of parity conservation. (B) In the strong interactions, i.e. interactions of classes 1 and 2 discussed above, there were indeed many experiments that established parity conservation to a high degree of accuracy, but not to a sufficiently high degree to be able to reveal the effects of a lack of parity conservation in the weak interactions. The fact that parity conservation in the weak interactions was believed for so long without experimental support was very startling. But what was more startling was the prospect that a space-time symmetry law which the phys- icists have learned so well may be violated. This prospect did not appeal to us. Rather we were, so to speak, driven to it through frustration with the various other efforts at understanding the puzzle that had been made 10 . As we shall mention later there is known in physics a conservation law - the conservation of isotopic spin - that holds for interactions of class I but breaks down when weaker interactions are introduced. Such a possibility of PARITY CONSERVATION AND OTHER SYMMETRY LAWS 399 an approximate symmetry law was, however, not expected of the sym- metries related to space and time. In fact one is tempted to speculate, now that parity conservation is found to be violated in the weak interactions, whether in the description of such phenomena the usual concept of space and time is adequate. At the end of our discussion we shall have the occasion to come back to a closely related topic. Why was it so that among the multitude of experiments on the most exhaustively studied of all the weak interactions, there was no informa- tion on the conservation of parity in the weak interactions? The answer de- rives from a combination of two reasons. First, the fact that the neutrino does not have a measurable mass introduces an ambiguity that rules out 11 indirect information on parity conservation from such simple experiments as the spectrum of, β-decay. Second, to study directly parity conservation in β-decay it is not enough to discuss nuclear parities, as one had always done. One must study parity conservation of the whole decay process. In other words, one must design an that tests right-left symmetry in the decay. Such experiments were not done before. Once these points were understood it was easy to point out what were the experiments that would unambiguously test the previously untested assump- tion of parity conservation in the weak interactions. Dr. Lee and I proposed 9 in the summer of 1956 a number of these tests concerning β-decay, and strange-particle decays. The basic principles involved in these exper- iments are all the same: One constructs two sets of experimental arrangements which are mirror images of each other, and which contain weak interactions. One then examines whether the two arrangements always give the same results in terms of the readings of their meters (or counters). If the results are not the same, one would have an unequivocal proof that right-left symmetry, as we usually understand it, breaks down. The idea is illustrated in Fig. 2 which shows the experiment proposed to test parity conservation in This experiment was first performed in the latter half of 1956 and finished early this year by Wu, Ambler, Hayward, Hoppes, and Hudson 12 . The actual experimental setup was very involved, because to eliminate disturbing out- side influences the experiment had to be done at very low temperatures. The technique of combining β-decay measurement with low temperature ap- paratus was unknown before and constituted a major difficulty which was successfully solved by these authors. To their courage and their skill, phys- icists owe the exciting and clarifying developments concerning parity con- servation in the past year. 1957 C.N.YANG

Fig. 2.

The results of Drs. Wu, Ambler, and their collaborators was that there is a very large difference in the readings of the two meters of Fig. 2. Since the behavior of the other parts of their apparatus observes right-left sym- metry, the asymmetry that was found must be attributed to the of cobalt. Very rapidly after these results were made known, many experi- ments were performed which further demonstrated the violation of parity conservation in various weak interactions. In his lecturer Dr. Lee will discuss these interesting and important developments.

I I I

The breakdown of parity conservation brings into focus a number of ques- tions concerning symmetry laws in physics which we shall now briefly dis- cuss in general terms: (A) As Dr. Lee 1 will discuss, the experiment of Wu, Ambler, and their collaborators also proves 13,14 that charge conjugation invariance 15 is violated for Another symmetry called time reversal invariance 16 is at the present moment still being experimentally studied for the weak interactions. PARITY CONSERVATION AND OTHER SYMMETRY LAWS 401 The three discrete invariances - reflection invariance, charge conjugation invariance, and time reversal invariance - are connected by an important theorem 17 called the CPT theorem. Through the use of this theorem one can prove 13 a number of general results concerning the experimental manifesta- tions of the possible violations of the three symmetries in the weak inter- actions. Of particular interest is the possibility that time reversal invariance in the weak interactions may turn out to be intact. If this is the case, it follows from the CPT theorem that although parity conservation breaks down, right-left symmetry will still hold if 18 one switches all particles into antiparticles in taking a mirror image. In terms of Fig. 2 this means that if one changes all the matter that composes the apparatus at the right into anti-matter, the meter reading would become the same for the two sides if time reversal invariance holds. It is important to notice that in the usual definition of re- flection, the electric field is a vector and the magnetic field a pseudovector while in this changed definition their transformation properties are switched. The transformation properties of the electric charge and the magnetic charge are also interchanged. It would be interesting to speculate on the possible relationship between the nonconservation of parity and the symmetrical or unsymmetrical role played by the electric and magnetic fields. The question of the validity of the continuous space time symmetry laws has been discussed to some extent in the past year. There is good evidence that these symmetry laws do not break down in the weak interactions. (B) Another symmetry law that has been widely discussed is that giving rise to the conservation of isotopic spin 19 . In recent years the use of this sym- metry law has produced a remarkable empirical order among the phenom- ena concerning the strange particles 2 0 . It is however certainly the least under- stood of all the symmetry laws. Unlike Lorentz invariance or reflection invariance, it is not a « geometrical » symmetry law relating to space time invariance properties. Unlike charge conjugation invariance 21 it does not seem to originate from the algebraic property of the complex numbers that occurs in quantum mechanics. In these respects it resembles the conservation laws of charge and heavy particles. These latter laws, however, are exact while the conservation of isotopic spin is violated upon the introduction of electromagnetic interactions and weak interactions. An understanding of the origin of the conservation of isotopic spin and how to integrate it with the other symmetry laws is undoubtedly one of the outstanding problems in high-energy physics today. 402 1957 C.N.YANG (C) We have mentioned before that all the different varieties of weak interactions share the property of having very closely identical strengths. The experimental work on parity nonconservation in the past year reveals that they very likely also share the property of not respecting parity conservation and charge conjugation invariance. They therefore serve to differentiate be- tween right and left once one fixes one’s definition of matter vs. anti-mat- ter. One could also use the weak interactions to differentiate between matter and anti-matter once one chooses a definition of right vs. left. If time rever- sal invariance is violated, the weak interactions may even serve to differen- tiate simultaneously right from left, and matter from anti-matter. One senses herein that maybe the origin of the weak interactions is intimately tied in with the question of the differentiability of left from right, and of matter from anti-matter.

1. T. D. Lee, Nobel Lecture, this volume, p. 406. 2. For references to these developments see E. P. Wigner, Proc. Am. Phil. Soc., 93 (1949) 521. 3. Cf. the interesting discussion on bilateral symmetry by H. Weyl, Symmetry, Prince- ton University Press, 1952. 4. O. Laporte, Z. Physik, 23 (1924) 135. 5. E. P. Wigner, Z. Physik, 43 (1927) 624. 6. O. Klein, Nature, 161 (1948) 897; J. Tiomno and J. A. Wheeler, Rev. Mod. Phys., 21 (1949) 144; T. D. Lee, M. Rosenbluth, and C. N. Yang, Phys. Rev., 75 (1949) 905. 7. R. Dalitz, Phil. Mag., 44 (1953) 1068; E. Fabri, Nuovo Cimento, II (1954) 479. 8. C. N. Yang, Rev. Mod. Phys., 29 (1957) 231. 9. T. D. Lee and C. N. Yang, Phys. Rev., 104 (1956) 254. 10. T. D. Lee and J. Orear, Phys. Rev., 100 (1955) 932; T. D. Lee and C. N. Yang, Phys. Rev., 102 (1956) 290; M. Gell-Mann, (unpublished); R. Weinstein, (private communication) ; a general discussion of these ideas can be found in the Proceedings of the Rochester Conference , April 1956, Session VIII, Interscience, New York, 1957. 11. C. N. Yang and J. Tiomno, Phys. Rev., 79 (1950) 495. 12. C. S. Wu, E. Ambler, R. W. Hayward, D. D. Hoppes, and R. P. Hudson, Phys. Rev., 105 (1957) 1413. 13. T. D. Lee, R. Oehme, and C. N. Yang, Phys. Rev., 106 (1957) 340. 14. B. L. Ioffe, L. B. Okun, and A. P. Rudik, J.E.T.P. (U.S.S.R.), 32 (1957) 396. English translation in Soviet Phys. ]ETP, 5 (1957) 328. 15. Charge conjugation invariance is very intimately tied with the hole theory inter- pretation of Dirac’s equation. The development of the latter originated with P. A. M. Dirac, Proc. Roy. Soc. London, A126 (1930) 360; J. R. Oppenheimer, Phys. Rev., PARITY CONSERVATION AND OTHER SYMMETRY LAWS 403 35 (1930) 562 and H. Weyl, Gruppentheorie und Quantenmechanik, 2nd ed., 1931, p. 234. An account of these developments is found in P. A. M. Dirac, Proc. Roy. SOc. London, A133 (1931) 60 . Detailed formalism and application of charge con- jugation invariance started with H. A. Kramers, Proc. Acad. Sci. Amsterdam, 40 (1937) 814 and W. Furry, Phys. Rev., 51 (1937) 125. 16. E. P. Wigner, Nachr. Akad. Wiss. Goettingen, Math.-Physik., 1932, p. 546. This paper explains in terms of time reversal invariance the earlier work of H. Kramers, Proc. Acad. Sci. Amsterdam, 33 (1930) 959. 17. J. Schwinger, Phys. Rev., 91 (1953) 720, 723; G. Lüders, Kgl. Danske Videnskab. Selskab., Mat.-Fys. Medd., 28, No. 5 (1954); W. P au li ‘s article in and the Development of Physics, Pergamon Press, London, 1955. See also Ref. 21. 18. This possibility was discussed by T. D. Lee and C. N. Yang and reported by C. N. Yang at the International Conference on Theoretical Physics in Seattle in Septem- ber 1956. (See Ref. 8.) Its relation with the CPT theorem was also reported in the same conference in one of the discussion sessions. The speculation was later pub- lished in T. D. Lee and C. N. Yang, Phys. Rev., 105 (1957) 1671 . Independently the possibility has been advanced as the correct one by L. Landau, J.E.T.P. (U.S.S.R.), 32 (1957) 405. An English translation of Landau’s article appeared in Soviet Phys. JETP, 5 (1957) 336. 19. The concept of a total isotopic spin quantum number was first discussed by B. Cassen and E. U. Condon, Phys. Rev., 50 (1936) 846 and E. P. Wigner, Phys. Rev., 51 (1937) 106 . The physical basis derived from the equivalence of p-p and n-p forces, pointed out by G. Breit, E. U. Condon, and R. D. Present, Phys. Rev., 50 (1936) 825 . The isotopic spin was introduced earlier as a formal mathematical parameter by W. Heisenberg, Z. Physik, 77 (1932) I. 20. A. Pais, Phys. Rev., 86 (1952) 663 , introduced the idea of associated production of strange particles. An explanation of this phenomenon in terms of isotopic spin conservation was pointed out by M. Gell-Mann, Phys. Rev., 92 (1953) 833 and by K. Nishijima, Progr. Theoret. Phys. (Kyoto), 12 (1954) 107 . These latter authors also showed that isotopic spin conservation leads to a convenient quantum number called strangeness. 21. R. Jost, Helv. Phys. Acta, 30 (1957) 409.