Thoughts on the Liberal Peace

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Thoughts on the Liberal Peace The Liberal Peace: Ethical, Historical, and Philosophical Aspects Markus Fischer 2000-07 April 2000 CITATION AND REPRODUCTION This document appears as Discussion Paper 2000-07 of the Belfer Center for Science and International Affairs. BCSIA Discussion Papers are works in progress. Comments are welcome and may be directed to the author in care of the Center. This paper may be cited as: Markus Fischer. “The Liberal Peace: Ethical, Historical, and Philosophical Aspects” BCSIA Discussion Paper 2000-07, Kennedy School of Government, Harvard University, April 2000. The views expressed in this paper are those of the author and publication does not imply their endorsement by BCSIA and Harvard University. This paper may be reproduced for personal and classroom use. Any other reproduction is not permitted without written permission of the Belfer Center for Science and International Affairs, Publications, 79 JFK Street, Cambridge, MA 02138, telephone (617) 495-4708, telefax (617) 496-4403 or email: [email protected]. Since the publication of Michael Doyle's seminal articles in 1983 and 1986,1 a growing number of students of international relations have argued that democracy causes states to live in peace with each other. For the United States and France have not been at war since 1798, the U.S. and Britain since 1812, and Britain and France since 1815. France ended its historical conflict with Germany as the latter became democratic after 1945. Indeed, war seems to have become almost unthinkable among the democratic nations of the West. This democratic peace argument is of the greatest significance for our understanding of foreign affairs, for it suggests nothing less than suspension of anarchic constraint—the fact that fear induces every state to perceive all others at least as potential enemies. Moreover, since such a suspension cannot be plausibly claimed for any other period of history—be it antiquity with its perpetually warring city-states, tribes, and empires, the middle ages with its feudal anarchy, or modernity with its cataclysmic contests between nation-states—a fundamental change of international politics seems to be taking place before our eyes. Democracy and Liberalism Whereas Michael Doyle—in keeping with his Kantian inspiration—was careful to attribute this peace in large part to liberal norms, most writers have pointed to the democratic character of the states in question. Likewise, policy makers regularly speak of the need to promote democracy 1 Michael W. Doyle, “Kant, liberal legacies, and foreign affairs,” Philosophy and Public Affairs vol. 12, no. 3 (1983), pp. 205–35; Michael W. Doyle, “Kant, liberal legacies, and foreign affairs, part 2,” Philosophy and Public Affairs vol. 12, no. 4 (1983), pp. 322–53; and Michael W. Doyle, “Liberalism and world politics,” American Political Science Review vol. 80, no. 4 (December 1986), pp. 1151–69. for the sake of peace, rather than liberalism.2 This conflation may seem insignificant since both theorists and practitioners refer quite obviously to the liberal kind of democracy that has come to prevail in the West. Nonetheless, it is important to appreciate the significant differences between the democratic and the liberal aspect of these regimes in order to grasp the peace that prevails among them. Simply put, democracy prescribes the rule of the people in the sense that every member of a collective should have equal weight in deciding how it is to be governed. In the direct democracies of antiquity, such decisions were made by assemblies where each male citizen had one vote; in the representative democracies of modernity, they are made by public officials who are periodically elected by the citizens who care to go the polling stations. Accordingly, democratic institutions promote every citizen's equal capacity to determine government by means of: open, fair, and competitive elections at all levels of collectivity (from legislators and chief executives to judges, town sheriffs, city clerks, and school boards), the concentration of supreme authority in the people and its representatives, referenda and plebiscites that allow the people to decide important issues directly, measures aimed at enhancing the representatives' responsiveness to the electorate (e.g., shortening their terms of office and reducing the number of voters in their electoral districts), widening the franchise, and taxation and welfare policies that promote equality. In contrast, liberalism aims at the freedom of the individual from oppression, especially from the rulers, and enshrines this freedom in a number of rights that must be respected under almost all circumstances: the right to life or immunity from violence, the right to assemble freely, to speak one's mind, to move about and choose one's abode, to acquire and dispose of property, to engage in arts, crafts, and commerce without hindrance, to profess and practice one's chosen faith, to educate one's children as one sees fit, etc. Liberal institutions guarantee and promote these rights through: a constitution that enumerates the basic rights of the citizens and limits the powers of government (usually dividing it into separate institutions, such as parliament, executive, and courts), the strict rule of law, separation of church and state, protection of private 2 See, for instance, Ronald Reagan, “Address to Parliament,” New York Times, June 9, 1982; Howard Baker on February 5 and April 21, 1992, as quoted by Bruce Russett, Grasping the Democratic Peace (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1993), pp. 128–29; Anthony Lake, “From containment to enlargement,” U.S. Department of State, Bureau of Public Affairs, Dispatch 4, no. 39 (September 1993), p. 3; William Jefferson Clinton, “Confronting the challenges of a broader world,” U.S. Department of State, Bureau of Public Affairs, Dispatch 3, no. 39 (September 1993), p. 3; “Excerpts from President Clinton's State of the Union Message,” New York Times, January 26, 1994, A17; and Anthony Lake, “The reach of democracy: Tying power to diplomacy,” New York Times, September 23, 1994, A35. 2 property, the free exchange of goods and services on an open and competitive market, and keeping regulation and taxation at a minimum. As a result of this laissez faire attitude, a free market society develops, where individuals compete for goods that satisfy their desires while government provides security and procedural justice. In Western modernity, these two approaches to government have been regularly combined in what are called “liberal democracies.” This combination is congenial in the sense that a democracy must, at a minimum, grant its citizens the freedom to vote in order to function as the rule of the people. In addition, it may allow them to form parties that compete for votes, voice political opinions, and publish newspapers. Conversely, liberalism enshrines these liberties as the right to vote, to practice free speech, to assemble, and to associate. Further, the liberal principle of equality before the law (which derives from respect for rights in abstraction from men's concrete attributes), tends to agree with the democratic passion for equality (which arises from resentment of whatever exceeds the common measure), but only insofar as the latter does not lead to a levelling of all social and economic conditions. Thus, the democratic impulse contains at least three illiberal tendencies as well. First, the plenitude of power asserted by the democratic assembly tends to diminish the rights of individuals, especially those in the minority, and may even put the will of the majority above the law; for power corrupts commoners just as much as princes, perhaps even more since they taste it for the first time. Second, the democratic tendency to equalize all conditions curtails the kind of freedom that issues in or thrives on distinctiveness, as when the diligent and enterprising have to yield the fruits of their labor to support the lazy and incompetent, or when the creative and wise are forbidden to express what offends the majority. Third, the common people are easily swayed by demagogues, who stir their passions and mislead their reason in order to gain power or pursue policies that sacrifice the common good to the ambition of the few—contrary to the rational deliberation prized by liberals. Athens, the world's first democracy, instantiates each of these illiberal tendencies only too well. Its citizens were free to participate in political life and enjoyed the protection of laws. Yet, its assembly acted not only as legislature but also as magistrate and judge, leading to such abuses as condemning to death generals who had lost in battle, expelling undesirable but otherwise innocent individuals, and executing Socrates for using reason to challenge popular pieties. In other words, it was the Athenian experience that gave rise to the 3 classical view that democracy degenerates by nature into the despotic rule of the mob.3 Until the end of the nineteenth century, liberals used to share this view. For instance, Alexander Hamilton called for vigorous government on the grounds that “of those men who have overturned the liberties of republics, the greatest number have begun their career by paying an obsequious court to the people, commencing demagogues and ending tyrants.”4 James Madison assumed that “the instability, injustice, and confusion introduced into the public councils have, in truth, been the mortal diseases under which popular governments have everywhere perished,” as policies are decided by the “superior force of an interested and overbearing majority.”5 Thus, although democracy may imply some of the rights that liberalism holds dear, it tends to infringe so many others that it cannot be considered a cause of liberty. The deeper reason for this illiberal tendency of democracy is this: liberalism assumes human beings to be individuals, whereas democracy not only permits the assumption that they think and act collectively but positively thrives on it; for the more opinions are alike, the more they can be said to express the will of “the people” as a unitary actor.
Recommended publications
  • Kant's Foedus Pacificum
    University of Texas Rio Grande Valley ScholarWorks @ UTRGV Political Science Faculty Publications and Presentations College of Liberal Arts 12-2020 Kant’s foedus pacificum: athP to peace or prolegomena to neoliberalism and authoritarian corporatist globalization in contemporary liberal democratic states? Terence Garrett University of Texas Rio Grande Valley, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.utrgv.edu/pol_fac Part of the Political Science Commons Recommended Citation Garrett, Terence. 2020. “Kant’s Foedus Pacificum: Path to Peace or Prolegomena to Neoliberalism and Authoritarian Corporatist Globalization in Contemporary Liberal Democratic States?” Annales. Ethics in Economic Life 23 (2): 7–20. https://doi.org/10.18778/1899-2226.23.2.01. This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the College of Liberal Arts at ScholarWorks @ UTRGV. It has been accepted for inclusion in Political Science Faculty Publications and Presentations by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks @ UTRGV. For more information, please contact [email protected], [email protected]. Annales. Ethics in Economic Life 2020 Vol. 23, No. 2, 7–20 doi: http://dx.doi.org/10.18778/1899-2226.23.2.01 Terence M. Garrett University of Texas Rio Grande Valley Public Affairs and Security Studies Department Department of Political Science e-mail: [email protected] Kant’s foedus pacificum: Path to peace or prolegomena to neoliberalism and authoritarian corporatist globalization in contemporary liberal democratic states? Abstract Immanuel Kant’s language and concept of foedus pacificum (league of peace) combined with his call for a spirit of trade promised a prescription for world peace—“seeking to end all wars forever” (Kant, 1795/1983, p.
    [Show full text]
  • The Strongmen Strike Back Robert Kagan
    POLICY BRIEF The strongmen strike back Robert Kagan Authoritarianism has returned as an ideological and strategic force. And it returns at just the moment when the liberal world is suffering a major crisis of confidence. EXECUTIVE SUMMARY INTRODUCTION Today, authoritarianism has emerged as the Of all the geopolitical transformations confronting greatest challenge facing the liberal democratic the liberal democratic world these days, the one world—a profound ideological, as well as strategic, for which we are least prepared is the ideological challenge. Or, more accurately, it has reemerged, and strategic resurgence of authoritarianism. We for authoritarianism has always posed the most are not used to thinking of authoritarianism as a potent and enduring challenge to liberalism, since distinct worldview that offers a real alternative the birth of the liberal idea itself. Authoritarianism to liberalism. Communism was an ideology—and has now returned as a geopolitical force, with strong some thought fascism was, as well—that offered a nations such as China and Russia championing comprehensive understanding of human nature, anti-liberalism as an alternative to a teetering politics, economics and governance to shape the liberal hegemony. It has returned as an ideological behavior and thought of all members of a society in force, offering the age-old critique of liberalism, every aspect of their lives. and just at the moment when the liberal world is suffering its greatest crisis of confidence since We believed that “traditional” autocratic the 1930s. It has returned armed with new and governments were devoid of grand theories about hitherto unimaginable tools of social control and society and, for the most part, left their people disruption that are shoring up authoritarian rule at alone.
    [Show full text]
  • HABERMAS [Kabinettskriege], Philosophy Assumed This Role a Second Time
    8 Does the Constitutionalization of International Law Still Have a Chance?1 The Introduction Divided As the European system of states was taking shape, phi losophy, in the persons of Francisco Suarez, Hugo Grotius, West and Samuel Pufendorf, still played the role of pacemaker in the creation of modern international law. Moreover, when legally constrained international relations later stabilized at the level of violence of so-called cabinet wars BY JORGEN HABERMAS [Kabinettskriege], philosophy assumed this role a second time. With his conception of a-"cosmopolitan condition" or "wekburgerlichen Zustand," Kant took a decisive step Edited and Translated by beyond international law centered exclusively on states. Since then, international law has not only developed into CIABAN CRONIN a specialized brand of legal theory. Following two world wars, the constitutionalization of international law has evolved along the lines prefigured by Kant toward cosmo politan law and has assumed institutional form in inter national constitutions, organizations, and procedures.2 Since the end of the bipolar world order and the emergence of the US as the pre-eminent world power, an alternative to the evolution of a cosmopolitan constitution has emerged. A world dominated by nation-states is indeed 2-00 in transition toward the postnational constellation of a polity global society. States are losing their autonomy in part as they become increasingly enmeshed in the horizontal 115 THE KANTIAN PROJECT THE CXJNSTITUTIONALIZATION OF INTERNATIONAL LAW networks of a global society.3 But in this situation the accord priority to its own, ethically rather than legally, Kantian project of a cosmopolitan order not only has to justified national interests, even over the objections of its confront the traditional objection of "realists" who affirm allies.
    [Show full text]
  • Perpetual Peace, a Philosophical Essay, by Immanuel Kant, 1795
    Perpetual peace, a philosophical essay, by Immanuel Kant, 1795; tr. with introduction and notes by M. Campbell Smith ... with a preface by Professor Latta. Kant, Immanuel, 1724-1804. London, G. Allen & Unwin ltd.; [1915] http://hdl.handle.net/2027/mdp.39015063009818 Public Domain in the United States, Google-digitized http://www.hathitrust.org/access_use#pd-us-google We have determined this work to be in the public domain in the United States of America. It may not be in the public domain in other countries. Copies are provided as a preservation service. Particularly outside of the United States, persons receiving copies should make appropriate efforts to determine the copyright status of the work in their country and use the work accordingly. It is possible that current copyright holders, heirs or the estate of the authors of individual portions of the work, such as illustrations or photographs, assert copyrights over these portions. Depending on the nature of subsequent use that is made, additional rights may need to be obtained independently of anything we can address. The digital images and OCR of this work were produced by Google, Inc. (indicated by a watermark on each page in the PageTurner). Google requests that the images and OCR not be re-hosted, redistributed or used commercially. The images are provided for educational, scholarly, non-commercial purposes. Generated for member (Columbia University) on 2015-09-09 17:18 GMT / http://hdl.handle.net/2027/mdp.39015063009818 Public Domain in the United States, Google-digitized / http://www.hathitrust.org/access_use#pd-us-google PERPETUAL PEACE A PHILOSOPHICAL ESSAY BY IMMANUEL KANT 1 795 Translated with Introduction and Notes BY M.
    [Show full text]
  • East Asian Democratization and Value Change
    Noises and A Comparative Survey of DEMOCRACY, GOVERNANCE AND DEVELOPMENT Working Paper Series: No. 11 Noises and Interruptions – The Road to Democracy Wai-man Lam Hsin-Chi Kuan Chinese University of Hong Kong Issued by Asian Barometer Project Office National Taiwan University and Academia Sinica 2003 Taipei 1 Asian Barometer A Comparative Survey of Democracy, Governance and Development Working Paper Series The Asian Barometer (ABS) is an applied research program on public opinion on political values, democracy, and governance around the region. The regional network encompasses research teams from twelve East Asian political systems (Japan, Mongolia, South Korea, Taiwan, Hong Kong, China, the Philippines, Thailand, Vietnam, Cambodia, Singapore, and Indonesia), and five South Asian countries (India, Pakistan, Bangladesh, Sri Lanka, and Nepal). Together, this regional survey network covers virtually all major political systems in the region, systems that have experienced different trajectories of regime evolution and are currently at different stages of political transition. The ABS Working Paper Series is intended to make research result within the ABS network available to the academic community and other interested readers in preliminary form to encourage discussion and suggestions for revision before final publication. Scholars in the ABS network also devote their work to the Series with the hope that a timely dissemination of the findings of their surveys to the general public as well as the policy makers would help illuminate the public discourse on democratic reform and good governance. The topics covered in the Series range from country-specific assessment of values change and democratic development, region-wide comparative analysis of citizen participation, popular orientation toward democracy and evaluation of quality of governance, and discussion of survey methodology and data analysis strategies.
    [Show full text]
  • Perpetual Peace? Critical Remarks on Mortimer J
    Perpetual Peace? Critical Remarks on Mortimer J. Adler's Book By Waldemar Gurian jj\4ORTIMER J. Adler's much quoted address in which he castigated American professors has been widely misunderstood. When he declared that their errors were more dangerous than -the threat from Hitler, he did not intend to discount them. On the contrary, he was paying a most impressive compliment, to the importance and effect of their writings and other activities. Adler is professor of the philosophy of law in the University of Chicago, and his yardstick must be applied to himself. It would be inappropriate to pass over his How to Think About War and Peace' in silence or to regard it as an unimportant and uninfluential work. This new book, praised as a product of hard thinking, will be read only by few, even though it will be bought by many in response to the intense propaganda of the publisher. Adler claims that he describes the necessary approach to a most urgent problem. It is true that he modestly abstains from presenting any blueprints for the postwar world. He humbly abandons to Prime Minister Churchill and President Roosevelt a concern with such mat- ters of immediate practical importance as relations with the Soviet Union or the fate of Germany. But on the other hand, he is more ambitious than those who are preoccupied with planning for our gen- eration. He is trying not only to find principles of thought about peace and war but also to circumscribe the realm and the, direction of pract- ical, meaningful work in behalf of a truly lasting, and therefore uni- versal and perpetual, peace.
    [Show full text]
  • Military Neoliberalism: Endless War and Humanitarian Crisis in the Twenty-First Century Michael Schwartz Stony Brook State University
    Societies Without Borders Volume 6 | Issue 3 Article 3 2011 Military Neoliberalism: Endless War and Humanitarian Crisis in the Twenty-First Century Michael Schwartz Stony Brook State University Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarlycommons.law.case.edu/swb Part of the Human Rights Law Commons, and the Social and Behavioral Sciences Commons Recommended Citation Schwartz, Michael. 2011. "Military Neoliberalism: Endless War and Humanitarian Crisis in the Twenty-First Century." Societies Without Borders 6 (3): 190-303. Available at: https://scholarlycommons.law.case.edu/swb/vol6/iss3/3 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Cross Disciplinary Publications at Case Western Reserve University School of Law Scholarly Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Societies Without Borders by an authorized administrator of Case Western Reserve University School of Law Scholarly Commons. Schwartz: Military Neoliberalism: Endless War and Humanitarian Crisis in th M. Schwartz/Societies Without Borders 6:3 (2011) 190-303 Military Neoliberalism: Endless War and Humanitarian Crisis in the Twenty-First Century Michael Schwartz Stony Brook State University Received January 2011; Accepted August 2011 ______________________________________________________ Abstract This article seeks to understand the dynamics of twenty-first century military intervention by the United States and its allies. Based on an analysis of Bush and Obama administration policy documents, we note that these wars are new departures from previous interventions, calling on the military to undertake post-conflict reconstruction in ways that was previously left to indigenous government or to the civilian aspects of the occupation. This military-primary reconstruction is harnessed to ambitious neoliberal economics aimed at transforming the host country’s political economy.
    [Show full text]
  • Capitalism, Peace, and the Historical Movement of Ideas
    International Interactions, 36:169–184, 2010 Copyright © Taylor & Francis Group, LLC ISSN: 0305-0629 print/1547-7444 online DOI: 10.1080/03050621003785066 GINI0305-06291547-7444International Interactions,Interactions Vol. 36, No. 2, Apr 2010:Capitalism, pp. 0–0 Peace, and the Historical Movement of Ideas Capitalism,J. Mueller Peace, and Historical Movement of Ideas JOHN MUELLER Ohio State University A logical and causal exploration of the growing acceptance of capitalism and peace, or war aversion, is part of what Robert Dahl has called “the historical movement of ideas.” Although war aversion and the acceptance of free-market capitalism have undergone parallel and substantially overlapping historical trajectories, support for capitalism does not on its own logically or necessarily imply war aversion or support for peace. Not only must capital- ism be embraced as an economic system, but at least three other ideas must be accepted as well: prosperity and economic growth must be taken as a dominant goal; peace must be seen as a better motor than war for development, progress, and innovation; and trade, rather than conquest, must be held to be the best way to achieve the dominant goal. Moreover, the causal direction may well be misspecified: it is not that free-market capitalism and the economic development it spawns cause peace, but rather that peace causes—or facilitates—capitalism and its attendant economic development. This also may explain why peace is more closely associ- ated with capitalism than with democracy. KEYWORDS capitalism, democracy, ideas, peace, war Downloaded By: [Ohio State University Libraries] At: 17:49 20 December 2010 Robert Dahl has observed that “because of their concern with rigor and their dissatisfaction with the ‘softness’ of historical description, generalization, and explanation,” most social scientists have turned away from what he calls, “the historical movement of ideas”.
    [Show full text]
  • The Political Economy of Liberal Democracy*
    THE POLITICAL ECONOMY OF LIBERAL DEMOCRACY* Sharun Mukand Dani Rodrik Department of Economics John F. Kennedy School of Government University of Warwick Harvard University Coventry CV4 7AL Cambridge, MA 02138 United Kingdom U.S.A. Revised January 2016 * The first draft of this paper was written at the Institute for Advanced Study, to which we are grateful for support. We also thank members of the IAS School of Social Science lunch table for useful discussions, as well as Carles Boix, William Ferguson, Sumon Majumdar, Jan-Werner Müller, Ira Katznelson, and commentators at presentations at Northwestern, London School of Economics, the NBER, Brown, and WINIR-Rio for helpful suggestions. -2- THE POLITICAL ECONOMY OF LIBERAL DEMOCRACY ABSTRACT We distinguish between three sets of rights – property rights, political rights, and civil rights – and provide a taxonomy of political regimes. The distinctive nature of liberal democracy is that it protects civil rights (equality before the law for minorities) in addition to the other two. When democratic transitions are the product of a settlement between the elite (who care mostly about property rights) and the majority (who care mostly about political rights), they generically fail to produce liberal democracy. This is because the minority has neither the resources nor the numbers to make a contribution to the settlement. We develop a formal model to sharpen the contrast between electoral and liberal democracies and highlight circumstances under which liberal democracy can emerge. We discuss informally the difference between social mobilizations sparked by industrialization and decolonization. Since the latter revolve around identity cleavages rather than class cleavages, they are less conducive to liberal politics.
    [Show full text]
  • LUCA KRISTÓF* Cultural Policy in an Illiberal State. a Case Study Of
    LUCA KRISTÓF Intersections. EEJSP Cultural Policy in an Illiberal State. A Case Study of 3(3): 126-147. DOI: 10.17356/ieejsp.v3i3.328 Hungary after 2010 http://intersections.tk.mta.hu [[email protected]] (Institute for Sociology, Centre for Social Sciences, Hungarian Academy of Sciences) This work was supported by the Bolyai scholarship of the Hungarian Academy of Sciences. Abstract In social sciences literature, numerous attempts have been made to capture the political essence and features of Hungary’s ‘illiberal’ regime but few were aimed at analyzing specific public policy fields in the illiberal democracy. This paper analyses the cultural policy of the Orbán regime, focusing on the role of ideology. A qualitative case study based on document analysis looks at the legitimizing function of post-communist traditionalism in a managed illiberal democracy (Csillag and Szelényi, 2015). Governmental policy making in the field of culture is analyzed on two interrelated levels: (1) attempts to rewrite the cultural canon, and (2) institutional and financial changes. The results show that post-communist traditionalism serves as a discursive framework for the partial replacement of the cultural elite as well as the redistribution of cultural positions and resources, thus contributing to the creation of a new, loyal elite for the managed illiberal political system. Keywords: Cultural Policy; Cultural Elite; Illiberalism; Post-communist Traditionalism; Hungary. INTERSECTIONS. EAST EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF SOCIETY AND POLITICS, 3 (3): 126-147. CULTURAL POLICY IN AN ILLIBERAL STATE 127 1. Introduction: illiberal democracy in Hungary? Fared Zakaria in his famous article noted noticed already in the 1990s that, in contrast with Francis Fukuyama’s popular democratic teleology, countries that had recently undergone the process of democratization, did not turn into western type liberal democracies.
    [Show full text]
  • Herder's Debate with Kant
    [Intellectual History Archive 2, 2018] Piirimäe, Imperialism and Peace HUMAN RIGHTS, IMPERIALISM AND PEACE AMONG NATIONS: HERDER’S DEBATE WITH KANT Eva Piirimäe,12 University of Tartu I Human rights is a central normative idea in contemporary political thinking. Yet it is also increasingly common to argue that this idea is not a ‘fixed thing’. As Lynn Hunt has suggested, it is rather a ‘field of conflict’ or ‘a programme, an outlook, embedded in our political and cultural imagination and sensibility’.3 Perhaps it is therefore not entirely surprising that strongly diverging interpretations have been put forward about the origins of this idea during the recent decade. Lynn Hunt herself has charted its complex and often ruptured evolution, tracing its origins back to the emerging values of bodily integrity and empathetic selfhood in the eighteenth century.4 Samuel Moyn, by contrast, has argued that there is not much in common between the Enlightenment’s ‘eternal’ or natural rights of man and human rights, the latter constituting ‘a different conception altogether’.5 The Enlightenment’s natural rights were to be achieved through the construction of spaces of citizenship in which rights were accorded and protected, while human rights are ‘entitlements that might contradict the sovereign nation-state from above and outside’.6 Even more recently, in an Oxford Amnesty lecture of 2012, James Tully has restated the idea of the Enlightenment origins of human rights, focusing on the ways in which rights are derived and seen to be implemented both within states as well as outside them.7 In his lecture, Tully provides what he characterises as a ‘simple historical overview’ of two distinctive traditions of human rights.
    [Show full text]
  • Emancipation and Kantian Critique 'Towards Perpetual Peace'*
    PSA 66th Annual International Conference, 21-23 March 2016, Brighton Emancipation and Kantian Critique ‘Towards Perpetual Peace’* Mustafa A. Sezal Yildirim Beyazit University [email protected] In 1784, Immanuel Kant wrote an essay response to the question “what is enlightenment?” that was posed previous year by Reverend Johann Friedrich Zellner in the monthly magazine Berlinische Monatsschrift. According to him, enlightenment was human being’s ‘emancipation from its self-incurred immaturity’1. Kant’s description of enlightenment provides us a starting point for a deeper analysis of his other political writings, moral principles, and their relationship to Critical Theory. Therefore, this paper seeks to locate Kantian ‘good will’ in his political philosophy that would lead to ‘perpetual peace’. Then, building upon Andrew Linklater’s works on ‘cosmopolitan harm conventions’2, ‘civilising processes’3, and ‘emancipation’4 will argue that emancipatory International Relations (IR) and Security Studies are essentially Kantian. Emancipatory project of Critical Security Studies (CSS) can thus be linked to Kant’s cosmopolitanism and articles of perpetual peace that, in a sense, depicts the elaborate intricacies of Kantian philosophy in IR that goes beyond the simplistic view of ‘democratic/liberal peace thesis/theory’. Kant’s political philosophy is essentially a continuation or a macro-projection of his moral philosophy. In this vein, understanding political notions such as ‘perpetual peace’ need a brief introduction through his moral philosophy and particularly the ‘categorical imperative’. In the Groundwork for Metaphysics of Morals, Kant describes the ‘categorical imperative’5 through a two-dimensional formulation: “Act only on that maxim by which you can at the same time will that it should become a universal law” and “[a]ct as though the maxim of your action were to become by your will a universal law of nature”6.
    [Show full text]