Michael Ruse SOCIOBIOLOGY and REDUCTIONISM It Is Frequently

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Michael Ruse SOCIOBIOLOGY and REDUCTIONISM It Is Frequently Michael Ruse SOCIOBIOLOGY AND REDUCTIONISM It is frequently said that sociobiology is reductionistic or. more precisely. since much that is said about sociobiology is critical. it is frequently said that sociobiology is unduly reductionistic (Lewontin. 1977; Lewontin et al. J 984). In this discussion, I want to explore the precise meaning of such a charge as this, and whether or not it is justified. I hasten to add, at once, that I am not concerned here with either defending or attacking sociobiology per se. I and others have had much to say about this topic elsewhere -- some would say: "Too much to say about this topic elsewhere." Rather, I want to do what perhaps should have been done long ago.! want to provide a conceptual analysis of the way or ways in which one might speak of sociobiology in the context of reductionism. I shall begin by characterizing sociobiology very briefly. Then I shall move on to an even briefer discussion of the various senses in which the term "reductionism" is commonly used. After that, it will be possible to put the two concepts together and to see what results. SOCIOBIOLOGY Sociobiology is the study of organisms. most particularly animals. in their social relationships, from an evolutionary perspective (Wilson, 1975; Ruse. 1979). Although the name is new, as a subject it goes back to the founding classic of evolutionary theory, Charles Darwin's On the Origin of Species (1859). In that work. Darwin argued that all organisms. living and dead. are the product of a slow. gradual law-bound process of evolution. fuelled by a mechanism which he labelled "natural selection". Darwin argued that many more organisms are born than can possibly survive and reproduce. and that those which are successful in life's struggle the "fitter" -- are. as it were. naturally picked out from the breeding pool. for future generations. Given enough time. this natural selecting of 45 P. Hoyningen-HueM and F. M. Wuketits (eds.), Reductionism and Systems Theory in the Life Sciences. 45-83. @ 1989 by Kluwer Academic Publishers. 46 MICHAEL RUSE the successful leads to full-blown evolutionary change. What was crucial to Darwin, and continues to be so for his followers, is that selection does not simply lead to alteration, but promotes adaptation or proper functioning. Organisms work. They have features and characteristics which aid their attempts to succeed in the struggle for existence. They have eyes, fins, teeth, hair, feathers, leaves, roots, branches -- all of these things are adaptations, helping their possessors in life's struggles (Ruse, 1979b). In the Origin, Darwin was quite explicit in his intention to apply his theory to behaviour. What an organism does Is just as much part of Its nature as its anatomy. But, Darwin wanted to go beyond mere behavior to social interactions, particularly between animals of the same species. Darwin argued that, although life is a struggle, this does not necessarily always imply hand-to-hand all-out conflict. -- "Nature red in tooth and claw", as the poet Tennyson had expressed it. Darwin argued that cooperation between organisms can, under certain circumstances. be just as much a product of evolutionary process as can any other characterist.ic. Furthermore, Darwin backed up this belief by discussing in some length the paradigmatic example of sociality in the organic world, namely the so-called SOCial insects (part.icularly the hymenoptera, the wasps, ants and bees). Darwin claimed that the nature of the sterile workers in the hymenoptera must be just as much a consequence of the selective process, as any other feature that we may encounter. In the one hundred or more years since the Origin, evolutionary studies, particularly neo-Darwinian studies, have exploded outwards and upwards with great success. However, for a number of reasons, until recently the study of social behavior by evolutionists lagged far behind. The chief reason. of course, was the most obvious, namely that behavior is very, very much more difficult to study than other aspects of organisms. It is much easier to tell something about the eye colour of a fruit fly than about its mating habits. Thus, nat.urally. evolutionists tended to concentrate on more readily discernible aspects of organisms, leaving behavior (including social behavior) until later. Backing up this reason for the neglect of behavior were strong Ideological waves coming from the newly-growing social sciences. For fairly straight-forward reasons, workers in such fields as psychology and sociology felt very tense about the idea that biology might have anything to contribute to their areas of inquiry. And so there grew up a strong bias in favour of non-biological approaches to the understanding of social behavior (even including, indeed especially Including, studies of the social behavior of non-human animals). There were, nevertheless, some who looked at aspects of behavior from an evolutionary perspective. Most notably, in the years before and after the last War, the so-called "ethologists" looked at various questions to do with the interaction SOCIOBIOLOGY AN REDUCTIONISM 47 between or~anisms. particularly social interactions between organisms of the same species (Lorenz. 1952: Tinbergen. 1953a. b). However. t.his W:lS but a harbinger of what was to come, for some two decades ago (at the beginning of the 1960's) the whole study of the evolution of social behavior suddenly broke wide open. New ideas were introduced. new experimental results were gathered. new long-term naturalistic observations of animals in the wild were launched. From being the ugly duckling of the evolutionary family. the study of social behavior suddenly became a very proud and magnificent young swan indeed. In fact. it even gathered into itself a whole new name, namely "sociobiology". (A good Introduction is Barash. 1982.) INDIVIDUAL SELEC'rION Sociobiologists are orthodox Darwinians. That is to say. in today's context, they believe that the major evolutionary motive force is natural selection. and that this works ultimately on the units of heredity. These units -- the "genes" -- are carried by org:lnisms, within populations, and are transmitted through reproduction from one generation to another. All new variation within populations. on which natural selection must work ultlm:ltely, comes about through random changes ("mutations") caused at the level of the genes. There is. therefore, no overall direction or purpose to evolutionary change. What works, succeeds (WllJlams, 1966). What distinguishes sociobiologists most strongly from their ethological and other predecessors (although, incidentally, not from Charles Darwin himself) is the extent to which they take an IndivIdualistic stance towards natural selection (Ruse, 1979a, 1980; Brandon and Burian, 1984). What does this mean? Consider for a moment the way in which natural selection might be presumed to act, and ask yourself the favourite question of lawyers, namely cui bono (who gains)? When a new adaptation is produced by selection, for whose benefit does the adaptation exist :lnd function? Is the end worth of an adaptation directed towards the actual individual possessor of that adaptation, that is to say, the Individual organism; or is the end worth of the adaptation directed towards the good of the organism's group, where "group", in most contexts, would be interpreted as the organism's interbreeding group (I.e., the organism's species)? With some reservations and clarifications to be noted later, sociobiology's most distinctive characterizing feature is the extent to which It opts firmly for the Individualistic solution (Dawkins, 1976). It is the claim of today's Darwinian students of social behavior that such behavior is caused by natural selectIon working at the level of the Individual and not at the level of the group. Mutual 48 MICHAEL RUSE aid. cooperation or. as sociobiologists like to call it. "altruism". must be understood as something which benefits the individual actors. It does not exist for the overall good of the species. In taking such a stand as this. sociobiologists separate themselves firmly from ethologists. like the Nobel Prize winner KonTad Lorenz. In his well-known book. On Aggnsslon (1966). Lorenz argued that the reason why animals never fight to kill is that such all-out combat would be harmful to the species. Sociobiologists challenge this interpretation. absolutely. They argue that any restrained aggression or like behavior must be understood in terms of individual benefits alone. In the particular case of restrained aggression. it is argued that although it might benefit the winner to kill the loser. all too often we ourselves are losers. Therefore. it is in our own interests that aggression be restrained (Maynard Smith. 1972. 1974). Given that they take so individualistic a stance about selection. sociobiologists have found it necessaTY to devise various special models or mechanisms to account for particular facets of social behavior. It is here that they feel that they have scored their gTeatest triumphs. Amongst the various models which have been proposed we might. by way of illustration. mention the two which are most widely used. First. there is "kin selection". Here It Is pointed out that the key to reproductive success lies In passing on one's own units of heredity. that Is to say. in maintaining and perhaps increasing the proportion of one's own genes in future generations. However. obviously. one does not pass on one's own genes literally, but rather copies of such genes. But. remember that relatives will share genes. (By fairly elementary considerations one can show. for instance. that siblings are 50 % related. with corresponding diminution as the circle of relatedness widens.) What this all means. therefore, Is that inasmuch as one's relatives reproduce. one is oneself reproducing vicariously! If. for instance. my sister has children then. indirectly. she is poring my genes (or rather.
Recommended publications
  • Evolutionary Epistemology in James' Pragmatism J
    35 THE ORIGIN OF AN INQUIRY: EVOLUTIONARY EPISTEMOLOGY IN JAMES' PRAGMATISM J. Ellis Perry IV University of Massachusetts at Dartmouth "Much struck." That was Darwin's way of saying that something he observed fascinated him, arrested his attention, surprised or puzzled him. The words "much struck" riddle the pages of bothhis Voyage ofthe Beagle and his The Origin of Species, and their appearance should alert the reader that Darwin was saying something important. Most of the time, the reader caninfer that something Darwin had observed was at variance with what he had expected, and that his fai th in some alleged law or general principle hadbeen shaken, and this happened repeat­ edly throughout his five year sojourn on the H.M.S. Beagle. The "irritation" of his doubting the theretofore necessary truths of natu­ ral history was Darwin's stimulus to inquiry, to creative and thor­ oughly original abductions. "The influence of Darwinupon philosophy resides inhis ha ving conquered the phenomena of life for the principle of transi tion, and thereby freed the new logic for application to mind and morals and life" (Dewey p. 1). While it would be an odd fellow who would disagree with the claim of Dewey and others that the American pragmatist philosophers were to no small extent influenced by the Darwinian corpus,! few have been willing to make the case for Darwin's influence on the pragmatic philosophy of William James. Philip Wiener, in his well known work, reports that Thanks to Professor Perry's remarks in his definitive work on James, "the influence of Darwin was both early and profound, and its effects crop up in unex­ pected quarters." Perry is a senior at the University of Massachusetts at Dartmoltth.
    [Show full text]
  • Neither Logical Empiricism Nor Vitalism, but Organicism: What the Philosophy of Biology Was
    Neither Logical Empiricism nor Vitalism, but Organicism: What the Philosophy of Biology Was By: Daniel Nicholson & Richard Gawne Like a slow-burning story of triumph, the canonical narrative of the history of contemporary philosophy of biology tells the tale of a subfield emerging out of the smoldering ashes of logical empiricist philosophy of science, and the wreckage of an equally futile vitalistic program that preceded it. Most logical empiricists scoffed at the life sciences, and those who did deem it worthwhile to explore the biological realm produced nothing of value. The logical empiricists failed because their project was a prescriptive enterprise whose primary mandate was to bring increased rigour to biology by importing methodological protocols from the physical sciences. Vitalists of the early twentieth century were not stricken with physics-envy, but the animating forces and other metaphysical phantasms they conjured into existence to ward off the threat of reductionism were at least as ill-conceived as anything produced by the logical empiricists. Practitioners associated with the aforementioned schools failed to seriously engage with the science that allegedly inspired their musings, and as a consequence, the philosophy of biology languished in a state of futility for much of the twentieth century. Things began to change sometime in the late 1960s and early 1970s, when the textbooks by Michael Ruse (1973) and David Hull (1974), together with a series of articles by Ken Schaffner (1967; 1969a; 1969b) and Bill Wimsatt (1970; 1972a; 1972b), found their way into print. These efforts are regularly identified as the first significant contributions to modern philosophy of biology.
    [Show full text]
  • The Philosophy of Biology Edited by David L
    Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-85128-2 - The Cambridge Companion to the Philosophy of Biology Edited by David L. Hull and Michael Ruse Frontmatter More information the cambridge companion to THE PHILOSOPHY OF BIOLOGY The philosophy of biology is one of the most exciting new areas in the field of philosophy and one that is attracting much attention from working scientists. This Companion, edited by two of the founders of the field, includes newly commissioned essays by senior scholars and by up-and- coming younger scholars who collectively examine the main areas of the subject – the nature of evolutionary theory, classification, teleology and function, ecology, and the prob- lematic relationship between biology and religion, among other topics. Up-to-date and comprehensive in its coverage, this unique volume will be of interest not only to professional philosophers but also to students in the humanities and researchers in the life sciences and related areas of inquiry. David L. Hull is an emeritus professor of philosophy at Northwestern University. The author of numerous books and articles on topics in systematics, evolutionary theory, philosophy of biology, and naturalized epistemology, he is a recipient of a Guggenheim Foundation fellowship and is a Fellow of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences. Michael Ruse is professor of philosophy at Florida State University. He is the author of many books on evolutionary biology, including Can a Darwinian Be a Christian? and Darwinism and Its Discontents, both published by Cam- bridge University Press. A Fellow of the Royal Society of Canada and the American Association for the Advancement of Science, he has appeared on television and radio, and he contributes regularly to popular media such as the New York Times, the Washington Post, and Playboy magazine.
    [Show full text]
  • DANIEL DENNETT and the SCIENCE of RELIGION Richard F
    DANIEL DENNETT AND THE SCIENCE OF RELIGION Richard F. Green Department of Mathematics and Statistics University of Minnesota-Duluth Duluth, MN 55812 ABSTRACT Daniel Dennett (2006) recently published a book, “Breaking the Spell: Religion as a Natural Phenomenon,” which advocates the scientific study of religion. Dennett is a philosopher with wide-ranging interests including evolution and cognitive psychology. This talk is basically a review of Dennett’s religion book, but it will include comments about other work about religion, some mentioned by Dennett and some not. I will begin by describing my personal interest in religion and philosophy, including some recent reading. Then I will comment about the study of religion, including the scientific study of religion. Then I will describe some of Dennett’s ideas about religion. I will conclude by trying outlining the ideas that should be considered in order to understand religion. This talk is mostly about ideas, particularly religious beliefs, but not so much churches, creeds or religious practices. These other aspects of religion are important, and are the subject of study by a number of disciplines. I will mention some of the ways that people have studied religion, mainly to provide context for the particular ideas that I want to emphasize. I share Dennett’s reticence about defining religion. I will offer several definitions of religion, but religion is probably better defined by example than by attempting to specify its essence. A particular example of a religion is Christianity, even more particularly, Roman Catholicism. MOTIVATION My interest in philosophy and religion I. Beginnings I read a few books about religion and philosophy when I was in high school and imagined that college would be full of people arguing about religion and philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • The Biological Sciences Can Act As a Ground for Ethics” in Ayala, Francisco and Arp, Robert, Contemporary Debates in Philosophy of Biology
    1 This chapter to be published as: Ruse, Michael (2009). “The Biological Sciences Can Act as a Ground for Ethics” in Ayala, Francisco and Arp, Robert, Contemporary Debates in Philosophy of Biology. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell. The Biological Sciences Can Act as a Ground for Ethics Michael Ruse Ethics is an illusion put in place by natural selection to make us good cooperators. – Michael Ruse and Edward O. Wilson (1985) This paper is interested in the relationship between evolutionary thinking and moral behavior and commitments, ethics. There is a traditional way of forging or conceiving of the relationship. This is traditional evolutionary ethics, known as Social Darwinism. Many think that this position is morally pernicious, a re- description of the worst aspects of modern, laissez-faire capitalism in fancy biological language. It is argued that, in fact, there is much more to be said for Social Darwinism than many think. In respects, it could be and was an enlightened position to take; but it flounders on the matter of justification. Universally, the appeal is to progress—evolution is progressive and, hence, morally we should aid its success. I argue, however, that this progressive nature of evolution is far from obvious and, hence, traditional social Darwinism fails. There is another way to do things. This is to argue that the search for justification is mistaken. Ethics just is. It is an adaptation for humans living socially and has exactly the same status as other adaptations, like hands and teeth and genitalia. As such, ethics is something with no standing beyond what it is.
    [Show full text]
  • Evolution, Creationism, and Intelligent Design Kent Greenwalt
    Notre Dame Journal of Law, Ethics & Public Policy Volume 17 Article 2 Issue 2 Symposium on Religion in the Public Square 1-1-2012 Establishing Religious Ideas: Evolution, Creationism, and Intelligent Design Kent Greenwalt Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarship.law.nd.edu/ndjlepp Recommended Citation Kent Greenwalt, Establishing Religious Ideas: Evolution, Creationism, and Intelligent Design, 17 Notre Dame J.L. Ethics & Pub. Pol'y 321 (2003). Available at: http://scholarship.law.nd.edu/ndjlepp/vol17/iss2/2 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Notre Dame Journal of Law, Ethics & Public Policy at NDLScholarship. It has been accepted for inclusion in Notre Dame Journal of Law, Ethics & Public Policy by an authorized administrator of NDLScholarship. For more information, please contact [email protected]. ARTICLES ESTABLISHING RELIGIOUS IDEAS: EVOLUTION, CREATIONISM, AND INTELLIGENT DESIGN KENT GREENAWALT* I. INTRODUCTION The enduring conflict between evolutionary theorists and creationists has focused on America's public schools. If these schools had no need to teach about the origins of life, each side might content itself with promoting its favored worldview and declaring its opponents narrow-minded and dogmatic. But edu- cators have to decide what to teach, and because the Supreme Court has declared that public schools may not teach religious propositions as true, the First Amendment is crucially implicated. On close examination, many of the controversial constitu- tional issues turn out to be relatively straightforward, but others, posed mainly by the way schools teach evolution and by what they say about "intelligent design" theory, push us to deep questions about the nature of science courses and what counts as teaching religious propositions.
    [Show full text]
  • CONSCIOUSNESS 'THE Sour
    ( Fall 1995 Vol.15, No.4 HMMM... CONSCIOUSNESS 'THE sour. ABE ARTIFICIAL IIITELLIGENCE Exclusive Interviews with Cognitive Scientists Patricia Smith Churchland and Daniel C. Dennett BERTRAND RUSSELL Also: The Disneyfication of America Situation Ethics in Medicine 74957 Reactionar Black Nationalism FALL 1995, VOL. 15, NO. 4 ISSN 0272-0701 !ee WTI : Contents Editor: Paul Kurtz Executive Editor: Timothy J. Madigan Managing Editor: Andrea Szalanski 3 LETTERS TO THE EDITOR Senior Editors: Vern Bullough, Thomas W. Flynn, R. Joseph Hoffmann, Gerald Larue, Gordon Stein 5 EDITORIALS Contributing Editors: Robert S. Alley, Joe E. Barnhart, David Berman, Notes from the Editor: Pro Ecclesia et Commercia, Paul Kurtz I H. James Birx, Jo Ann Boydston, Bonnie Bullough, Reactionary Black Nationalism: Authoritarianism in the Name of Paul Edwards, Albert Ellis, Roy P. Fairfield, Charles W. Faulkner, Antony Flew, Levi Fragell, Adolf Freedom, Norm R. Allen, Jr. / The Founding Fathers Were Not Grünbaum, Marvin Kohl, Jean Kotkin, Thelma Lavine, Tibor Machan, Ronald A. Lindsay, Michael Christian, Steven Morris I Religious Right to Bolt GOP?, Skipp Martin, Delos B. McKown, Lee Nisbet, John Novak, Porteous I Humanist Potpourri, Warren Allen Smith Skipp Porteous, Howard Radest, Robert Rimmer, Michael Rockier, Svetozar Stojanovic, Thomas Szasz, Roh Tielman 16 NEWS AND VIEWS V. M. Torkunde, Richard Taylor, Associate Editors: Molleen Matsumura, Lois Porter 19 CONSCIOUSNESS REVISITED Editorial Associates: 19 FI Interview: A Conversation with Daniel Dennett Doris Doyle, Thomas Franczyk, Roger Greeley, James Martin-Diaz, Steven L. Mitchell, Warren 22 FI Interview: The Neurophilosophy of Patricia Smith Churchland Allen Smith 25 Neurological Bases of Modern Humanism José Delgado Cartoonist: Don Addis 29 Revisiting 'New Conceptions of the Mind' Noel W Smith CODESH.
    [Show full text]
  • Organism and Mechanism
    ORGANISM AND MECHANISM A Critique of Mechanistic Thinking in Biology Submitted by Daniel James Nicholson to the University of Exeter as a thesis for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy In September 2010 This thesis is available for Library use on the understanding that it is copyright material and that no quotation from the thesis may be published without proper acknowledgement. I certify that all material in this thesis which is not my own work has been identified and that no material has previously been submitted and approved for the award of a degree by this or any other University. Signature: ………………………………………………………….. ABSTRACT In this thesis I present a critical examination of the role played by mechanistic ideas in shaping our understanding of living systems. I draw on a combination of historical, philosophical, and scientific resources to uncover a number of problems which I take to result from the adoption of mechanistic thinking in biology. I provide an analysis of the historical development of the conflict between mechanistic and vitalistic conceptions of life since the seventeenth century, and I argue that the basic terms of this conflict remain central to current disputes over the nature of the organism as well as the question of how far the theories, concepts, and methods of physics, chemistry, and engineering can ultimately take us in the explanation of life. I offer a detailed critique of the machine conception of the organism, which constitutes the central unifying idea of mechanistic biology. I argue that this notion, despite its undeniable heuristic value, is fundamentally inadequate as a theory of the organism due to a number of basic differences between organisms and machines.
    [Show full text]
  • By Michael Ruse Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA, 1999, 296 Pp., $27.50
    "Mystery of Mysteries: Is Evolution a Social Construction?" by Michael Ruse Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA, 1999, 296 pp., $27.50 Unedited version of review published in: Chemical & Engineering News, 1999, 77 (9 August), 40-1. The title of this book suggests a rather ambitious undertaking, and on that score we are certainly not disappointed. Philosopher and zoologist Michael Ruse takes note of the ongoing debates known as the “Science Wars” and identifies, as the central issue, a fundamental controversy about the nature of science. Namely, is science objective knowledge about the real world? Or is it a subjective reflection of our culture? He then sets himself the goal of resolving this controversy by exploring the history of evolutionary biology. Ruse’s strategy is to distinguish between, and assess the relative influence of, two classes of values that drive the scientist: epistemic and nonepistemic. Among the former are the norms and criteria that philosophers offer as characteristic of science, such as consistency and coherence, predictive power, and fertility; while the latter include religious and cultural beliefs, desire for rewards and status, etc. Ruse examines ten notable figures in the development of evolution as a respectable scientific field, some historical — Erasmus and Charles Darwin, Julian Huxley, Theodosius Dobzhansky — and some contemporary — Richard Dawkins, Stephen Jay Gould, Richard Lewontin, Edward O. Wilson, Geoffrey Parker, and (recently deceased) J. John Sepkoski. For each case, he attempts to tease apart the different motivations and methodologies that underlie their respective contributions. By the end, Ruse believes he has amassed evidence for several conclusions. First, epistemic values unquestionably play an important role, and furthermore, one whose importance increases over time.
    [Show full text]
  • Michael Ruse, DARWINISM and ITS DISCONTENTS
    Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers Volume 26 Issue 4 Article 11 10-1-2009 Michael Ruse, DARWINISM AND ITS DISCONTENTS Angus Menuge Follow this and additional works at: https://place.asburyseminary.edu/faithandphilosophy Recommended Citation Menuge, Angus (2009) "Michael Ruse, DARWINISM AND ITS DISCONTENTS," Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers: Vol. 26 : Iss. 4 , Article 11. DOI: 10.5840/faithphil200926444 Available at: https://place.asburyseminary.edu/faithandphilosophy/vol26/iss4/11 This Book Review is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative exchange. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers by an authorized editor of ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative exchange. 464 Faith and Philosophy Darwinism and its Discontents, by Michael Ruse. Cambridge University Press, 2006. 290 pages + references + index. Cloth $30.00. ANGUS MENUGE, Concordia University Wisconsin In an earlier work—Can a Darwinian be a Christian?—Ruse argued that someone fully committed to Darwinism could consistently embrace much of the Christian faith. While Ruse expected a mixed response, he was sur- prised that some agreed with his thesis but could not see “how any right- thinking person could be a Darwinian” (p. ix). Ruse presents the current volume as a “prequel” to the earlier work, giving the strongest possible reasons to embrace a thoroughgoing Darwinism. By “thoroughgoing,” I mean that Ruse, like Daniel Dennett, is a reductionist philosopher who believes that the Darwinian perspective is a universal acid, transforming our understanding of everything.
    [Show full text]
  • RELIGION and SCIENCE: Two Peas in a Pod Or Fruits of Different Vines?1
    d RELIGION AND SCIENCE: Two Peas in a Pod or 1 Fruits of Different Vines? James W. Dow This essay deals with the difference between religion and sci­ ence. Émile Durkheim and other nineteenth century social philosophers thought that science was a child of religion and that the two belonged to the same family of collective repre­ sentations. I would like to offer an opposing opinion from the point of view of cultural anthropology. The more you look at religion and science, the more it appears that science is differ­ ent from religion. Science is something new, but religion is as old as the hills. Religion is built into the human brain, but sci­ ence is not. Yet, scientific ideas without question can be called beliefs when they are acquired from others. Like religion, sci­ ence offers a model of reality developed by a cultural group. When scientific ideas are acquired by imitation from the group, they seem to be similar to religious beliefs. However, there is a big difference in the way that the ideas are con­ structed before they are shared by the group. Cultures can pro­ duce various systems of knowledge each with their different ideas of what it true. This essay elaborates the position stated by Stephen J. Gould (1997): religion and science are different systems of knowledge. 1 An earlier version was presented at the Department of Sociology and An­ thropology Brown­Bag Series, Oakland University, on March 30, 2006 131 Often regarded as the founder of sociology, Émile Durkheim (1912) promoted the idea that religion and sci­ ence were similar.
    [Show full text]
  • Bertrand Russell Society Fall 2014
    The Bertrand Russell Society Fall 2014 Bulletin Inside this issue … Our columnists; Feature articles by Doubleday, Klement, Pigden, Turcon, and Berumen; And much more. Number 150 ISSN 1547-0334 Information for New and Renewing Members embership in the Society is $45 per year for individuals and $25 for students and those with limited incomes. Add $10.00 for cou- ples. A lifetime membership is $1,000. In addition to the BRS Bulletin, membership includes a subscription to the scholarly journal, M Russell: The Journal of Bertrand Russell Studies (published semi-annually by McMaster University), as well as other Society privi- leges, such as participation in the on-line BRS Forum, the BRS email list, access to a host of Russell-related resources, and eligibility to at- tend the Annual Meeting. Renewal dues should be paid by or on January 1st of each year. One’s membership status can be determined by going to russell.mcmaster.ca/brsmembers.htm. There one will also find convenient links to join or renew via PayPal and our information form. New and renewing members can also send a check or money order via traditional post to the treasurer (make it out to The Bertrand Russell Society). Send it to Michael Berumen, Treasurer, Bertrand Russell Society, 37155 Dickerson Run, Windsor, CO 80550. If a new member, please tell us a little about yourself beyond just your name (interests in Russell, profession, etc.). Include your postal address and email address, as well as your member status (i.e., regular, couple, student, limited income). If a renewing member, please let us know of any relevant changes in your contact information.
    [Show full text]