CONSCIOUSNESS 'THE Sour

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

CONSCIOUSNESS 'THE Sour ( Fall 1995 Vol.15, No.4 HMMM... CONSCIOUSNESS 'THE sour. ABE ARTIFICIAL IIITELLIGENCE Exclusive Interviews with Cognitive Scientists Patricia Smith Churchland and Daniel C. Dennett BERTRAND RUSSELL Also: The Disneyfication of America Situation Ethics in Medicine 74957 Reactionar Black Nationalism FALL 1995, VOL. 15, NO. 4 ISSN 0272-0701 !ee WTI : Contents Editor: Paul Kurtz Executive Editor: Timothy J. Madigan Managing Editor: Andrea Szalanski 3 LETTERS TO THE EDITOR Senior Editors: Vern Bullough, Thomas W. Flynn, R. Joseph Hoffmann, Gerald Larue, Gordon Stein 5 EDITORIALS Contributing Editors: Robert S. Alley, Joe E. Barnhart, David Berman, Notes from the Editor: Pro Ecclesia et Commercia, Paul Kurtz I H. James Birx, Jo Ann Boydston, Bonnie Bullough, Reactionary Black Nationalism: Authoritarianism in the Name of Paul Edwards, Albert Ellis, Roy P. Fairfield, Charles W. Faulkner, Antony Flew, Levi Fragell, Adolf Freedom, Norm R. Allen, Jr. / The Founding Fathers Were Not Grünbaum, Marvin Kohl, Jean Kotkin, Thelma Lavine, Tibor Machan, Ronald A. Lindsay, Michael Christian, Steven Morris I Religious Right to Bolt GOP?, Skipp Martin, Delos B. McKown, Lee Nisbet, John Novak, Porteous I Humanist Potpourri, Warren Allen Smith Skipp Porteous, Howard Radest, Robert Rimmer, Michael Rockier, Svetozar Stojanovic, Thomas Szasz, Roh Tielman 16 NEWS AND VIEWS V. M. Torkunde, Richard Taylor, Associate Editors: Molleen Matsumura, Lois Porter 19 CONSCIOUSNESS REVISITED Editorial Associates: 19 FI Interview: A Conversation with Daniel Dennett Doris Doyle, Thomas Franczyk, Roger Greeley, James Martin-Diaz, Steven L. Mitchell, Warren 22 FI Interview: The Neurophilosophy of Patricia Smith Churchland Allen Smith 25 Neurological Bases of Modern Humanism José Delgado Cartoonist: Don Addis 29 Revisiting 'New Conceptions of the Mind' Noel W Smith CODESH. Inc.: Chairman: Paul Kurtz 33 Consciousness, Math, and Aristotle Adam Carley President: Timothy J. Madigan Executive Director: Matt Cherry Chief Development Officer: James Kimberly 35 BERTRAND RUSSELL REMEMBERED Public Relations Director: Norm R. Allen, Jr. 35 Introduction Timothy J. Madigan President, Academy of Humanism: Paul Kurtz Executive Director, Secular Organizations fbr 36 Russell vs. Dewey on Religion Michael J. Rockler Sobriety: James Christopher 38 Why I Am Not a Russellian John M. Novak Chief Data Officer: Richard Seymour 39 Bertrand Russell's Intellectual Odyssey . Gladys Garner Leithauser Fulfilbnent Manager: Michael Cione 41 Russell and the Contemplation of Philosophy Typesetting: Paul E. Loynes, Sr. John Shosky Graphic Designer: Jacqueline Cooke 42 Russell and the Happy Life Marvin Kohl Audio Technician: Vance Vigrass 43 Russell at Century's End Alan Ryan staff:. 45 Onto the Past! What the 1990s Georgeia Locurcio, Anthony Nigro, Ranjit Sandhu Mean to Bertrand Russell Nicholas Griffin Executive Direcuir Emeritus: Jean Millholland FREE INQUIRY (ISSN 0272-0701) is published quarterly by the Council for Democratic and Secular Humanism HUMANISM AND MEDICAL ETHICS (CODESH, Inc.), a nonprofit corporation, 3965 Rensch Road, Amherst, NY 14228-2713. Phone (716) 636-7571. 47 Joseph Fletcher's Situation Ethics, Once Again Richard Taylor Fax (716) 636-1733. Copyright ©1995 by CODESH, Inc. 50 God and the Patent Office Richard J. Goss Second-class postage paid at Amherst, N.Y., and at addi- tional mailing offices. National distribution by International Periodicals Distributors, Solana Beach, 52 REVIEWS California. FREE INQUIRY is available from University Microfilms and is indexed in Philosophers' Index. The Acid Test of Evolution, H. James Birx / Quite A Life, John R. Printed in the United States. Lenz / Crossing the Bleak Threshold, Thomas W Flynn / Psychoanalysis Subscription rates: $28.51) for one year, $47.50 for two Takes Its Lumps, Michael Ruse \ Sayings of the Skeptics, James A. years, $64.50 for three years. $6.95 for single issues. Naught / Arguing for God, Address subscription orders, changes of address, and Michael Martin / Books in Brief advertising to FREE INQUIRY, P.O. Box 664, Amherst, NY 14226-0664. VIEWPOINT Manuscripts, letters, and editorial inquiries should be 59 Church/State Separation in Germany— addressed to The Editor, FREE INQUIRY, P.O. Box 664, Amherst, NY 14226-0664. Editorial submissions must For Now This Wall Stays Up Edmund D. Cohen be on disk (PC: 3-1/2" or 5-1/4"; Mac: 3-1/2" only) and accompanied by a double-spaced hardcopy and a stamped, self-addressed envelope. Acceptable file for- 65 IN THE NAME OF GOD mats include any PC or Mac word processor, RTF, and ASCII. Opinions expressed do not necessarily reflect the Cover photo of Patricia Churchland by Union-Tribune/Roni Galgano views of the editors or publisher. Postmaster: Send address changes to FREE INQUIRY, P.O. Box 664, Cover photo of Daniel C. Dennett by Susan Dennett Amherst, NY 14226-0664. A moment's thought is surely suffi- cient to show that these lines express a Letters to the Editor grotesque falsehood rather than a pro- found truth. If such a piece of nonsense is to be an important or indeed any kind of tenet of humanism, then count me out. Is There a Need for Fantasy? to anthropomorphize). Religion then is an incidental develop- Professor Antony Flew Kenneth Marsalek's article on "Human- ment resulting from a misunderstanding Reading, England ism, Science Fiction, and Fairy Tales" (FI, of cause and effect, not an escape valve Summer 1995) gave an excellent presenta- for a too-inquisitive mind. tion of the role of science fiction in the As for Hans Vaihinger's idea It is true, as Edythe McGovern points out development of the imagination. I often ("Vaihinger and the 'As If" by Rollo in "Secular Humanism in Literature" (FI, find science fiction a source of inspira- Handy) that cultivation of religion will Summer 1995), that humanist values can tion, and was glad to find some references eventually give way to true knowledge, I be found in literature, and not only in to intriguing SF works that I haven't read would no more believe such a thing than those writers who openly express their yet. Bart Kosko's discussion ("The Future to imagine that communism can result opposition to traditional religion, like of God") of the role of gods in science fic- from the formation of a bureaucratic and Shelley, Twain, Whitman, Shaw, et al., tion was also intriguing... totalitarian state! but also in writers like Shakespeare, who Mike Jolley seem to accept traditional beliefs. But so Gary McGath New Orleans, La. can religious readers can find their val- Hooksett, N.H. ues in Shelley, Twain, Whitman, Hemingway, Stevens, etc., (not only While formal history and geography sum because) we tend to find what we are The idea that we need religious supersti- up definitions of events and places of the looking for, but because of the very tion to save us from "senseless" meta- past, legends are a part of mythology. nature of literature. physics makes very little sense ("Fantasy, They are not a representation of facts We enjoy literature for much the same Religion, and Missing Teeth," by because the facts in a legend are dis- reason that we enjoy music or any art: for Timothy J. Madigan). In the first place, torted, beautified, or amplified by imagi- its ability to give us an experience that we how do we know in advance which ques- nation or partiality. They are most often cannot have in any other way. At its best, tions to ask? What's the essential differ- an exaggeration or a misinterpretation for this literary experience is more likely to ence between asking "What is the mean- adaptation to popular taste. Sometimes challenge our beliefs than to reinforce ing of life?" as opposed to "What causes they are lies. them. That is why most good readers do thunder?" Both questions must originally Many legends have an European back- not judge literature by standards of moral have been considered answerable. Had ground with a supernatural component. correctness but how deeply the writer can our forefathers simply dismissed the lat- Legends are not really adapted for chil- involve us in the feelings of the charac- ter as a "senseless" question, we'd still be dren, who ignore their place in a context ters. The important point about a novel or without an explanation not only for thun- of culture, and some may mislead or a play or a poem is not whether its author der, but for any phenomena we now frighten them. Without knowledge of their is a humanist or a Christian but whether explain by assigning to it a naturalistic background, legends rather betray poor the work gives us an experience that goes cause. education and deter from historical truth. beyond the ideas and feelings that we Our consciousness, or self-conscious- Legends most often stand by themselves already have, what, in the words of T. S. ness, or ability to self-reflect, or if you while, to have a meaning, there is an order Eliot, "was not in existence before the will our metaphysical capacity, is a char- into which events are to be related. work was created." acteristic that possesses survival value in and of itself, according to a recent book Andrée Spuhler Lawrence Hyman by Richard Leakey (The Origin of Winter Park, Fla. Ridgewood, N.J. Humankind). After discussing work in pri- matology that would shed light on the ori- gin of human consciousness, he concludes In her "Secular Humanism and Literature" Opus Dei Postscript as follows: "Consciousness is a social tool (FI, Summer 1995) Edythe McGovern for understanding the behavior of others tells us that if John Keats "had written I believe that Opus Dei, if anything, is by modeling it on one's own feeling." In nothing except 'Ode on a Grecian Urn' he even a more fanatic organization than addition, he says that "It is a simple and would have given us an important tenet of revealed in FREE INQUIRY ("Opus Dei and natural extrapolation to impute these humanism in its closing lines, `Beauty is Other Secret Societies," FI, Fall 1994).
Recommended publications
  • Human Values Annual Review
    University Center for Human Values 304 Marx Hall Princeton, New Jersey 08544 The University Center for Human Values supports teaching, research, and discussion of ethics and human values throughout the curriculum and across the disciplines at Princeton University. Additional information about the University Center for Human Values can be found at http://uchv.princeton.edu or by calling (609) 258-4798. Human Values Annual Review 2011 “As someone with interests in both meta-level philosophy debates and more applied issues in normative ethics and political theory, the values and public life (VPL) program was a way for me to integrate these areas. The VPL program also afforded wonderful opportunities to attend lectures on the applied and academic areas of values—something that doesn’t often come together in certificate programs.” Shivani Radhakrishnan ’11, Philosophy Introducing a new Undergraduate Certifi cate Program in SOCIETY INDIVIDUALITY PLURALITY COMMUNITY CITIZEN NATION IDENTITY ETHICS MODERNITY RESPONSIBILITY CASUISTRY OBLIGATION CONSEQUENTIALISM LAW EQUALITY RIGHT WRONG DUTY SUPEREROGATORY RULES FAIRNESS UTILITY RECIPROCITY RULES EQUALITY JUSTICE COMPASSION CASUISTRY NATURAL LAW IMPERATIVE OBLIGATION SENTIMENTS FREEDOM DEMOCRACY SOCIETY INDIVIDUALITY COMMUNITY CITIZE NATION IDENTITY ETHICS MODERNITY RESPONSIBILITY CASUISTRY OBLIGATION CONSEQUENTIALISM LAW EQUALITY RIGHT WRONG DUTY SUPEREROGATORY RULES FAIRNESS UTILITY RECIPROCITY RULES FAIRNES EQUALITY JUSTICE COMPASSION CASUISTRY IMPERATIVE OBLIGATION SENTIMENTS FREEDOM DEMOCRACY
    [Show full text]
  • Maintaining Meaningful Expressions of Romantic Love in a Material World
    Reconciling Eros and Neuroscience: Maintaining Meaningful Expressions of Romantic Love in a Material World by ANDREW J. PELLITIERI* Boston University Abstract Many people currently working in the sciences of the mind believe terms such as “love” will soon be rendered philosophically obsolete. This belief results from a common assumption that such terms are irreconcilable with the naturalistic worldview that most modern scientists might require. Some philosophers reject the meaning of the terms, claiming that as science progresses words like ‘love’ and ‘happiness’ will be replaced completely by language that is more descriptive of the material phenomena taking place. This paper attempts to defend these meaningful concepts in philosophy of mind without appealing to concepts a materialist could not accept. Introduction hilosophy engages the meaning of the word “love” in a myriad of complex discourses ranging from ancient musings on happiness, Pto modern work in the philosophy of mind. The eliminative and reductive forms of materialism threaten to reduce the importance of our everyday language and devalue the meaning we attach to words like “love,” in the name of scientific progress. Faced with this threat, some philosophers, such as Owen Flanagan, have attempted to defend meaningful words and concepts important to the contemporary philosopher, while simultaneously promoting widespread acceptance of materialism. While I believe that the available work is useful, I think * [email protected]. Received 1/2011, revised December 2011. © the author. Arché Undergraduate Journal of Philosophy, Volume V, Issue 1: Winter 2012. pp. 60-82 RECONCILING EROS AND NEUROSCIENCE 61 more needs to be said about the functional role of words like “love” in the script of progressing neuroscience, and further the important implications this yields for our current mode of practical reasoning.
    [Show full text]
  • Evolutionary Epistemology in James' Pragmatism J
    35 THE ORIGIN OF AN INQUIRY: EVOLUTIONARY EPISTEMOLOGY IN JAMES' PRAGMATISM J. Ellis Perry IV University of Massachusetts at Dartmouth "Much struck." That was Darwin's way of saying that something he observed fascinated him, arrested his attention, surprised or puzzled him. The words "much struck" riddle the pages of bothhis Voyage ofthe Beagle and his The Origin of Species, and their appearance should alert the reader that Darwin was saying something important. Most of the time, the reader caninfer that something Darwin had observed was at variance with what he had expected, and that his fai th in some alleged law or general principle hadbeen shaken, and this happened repeat­ edly throughout his five year sojourn on the H.M.S. Beagle. The "irritation" of his doubting the theretofore necessary truths of natu­ ral history was Darwin's stimulus to inquiry, to creative and thor­ oughly original abductions. "The influence of Darwinupon philosophy resides inhis ha ving conquered the phenomena of life for the principle of transi tion, and thereby freed the new logic for application to mind and morals and life" (Dewey p. 1). While it would be an odd fellow who would disagree with the claim of Dewey and others that the American pragmatist philosophers were to no small extent influenced by the Darwinian corpus,! few have been willing to make the case for Darwin's influence on the pragmatic philosophy of William James. Philip Wiener, in his well known work, reports that Thanks to Professor Perry's remarks in his definitive work on James, "the influence of Darwin was both early and profound, and its effects crop up in unex­ pected quarters." Perry is a senior at the University of Massachusetts at Dartmoltth.
    [Show full text]
  • Differentiating Neuroethics from Neurophilosophy
    Differentiating Neuroethics From Neurophilosophy A review of Scientific and Philosophical Perspectives in Neuroethics by James J. Giordano and Bert Gordijn (Eds.) New York, NY: Cambridge University Press, 2010. 388 pp. ISBN 978-0-521-70303-1. $50.00 Reviewed by Amir Raz Hillel Braude Neuroethics is about gaps: the gap between neuroscience and ethics, the one between science and philosophy, and, most of all, the “hard gap” between mind and brain. The hybrid term neuroethics, put into public circulation by the late William Safire (2002), attempts to address these lacunae through an emergent discipline that draws equally from neuroscience and philosophy. What, however, distinguishes neuroethics from its sister discipline—neurophilosophy? Contrary to traditional “armchair” philosophy, neurophilosophers such as Paul and Patricia Churchland argue that philosophy needs to take account of empirical neuroscience data regarding the mind–brain relation. Similarly, neuropsychologists and neuroscientists should be amenable to philosophical insights and the conceptual rigor of the philosophical method. Joshua Greene’s neuroimaging studies of participants making moral decisions provide a good example of this symbiotic relation between neuroscience and philosophy (Greene, Sommerville, Nystrom, Darley, & Cohen, 2001). A number of possible answers to the distinction between neuroethics and neurophilosophy emerge from Scientific and Philosophical Perspectives in Neuroethics, edited by James J. Giordano and Bert Gordijn. First, neuroethics emerges from the discipline of bioethics and, as such, specifically deals with ethical issues related to neuroscience. As Neil Levy says in his preface to the book, “Techniques and technologies stemming from the science of the mind raise . profound questions about what it means to be human, and pose greater challenges to moral thought” (p.
    [Show full text]
  • A Contextual Examination of Three Historical Stages of Atheism and the Legality of an American Freedom from Religion
    ABSTRACT Rejecting the Definitive: A Contextual Examination of Three Historical Stages of Atheism and the Legality of an American Freedom from Religion Ethan Gjerset Quillen, B.A., M.A., M.A. Mentor: T. Michael Parrish, Ph.D. The trouble with “definitions” is they leave no room for evolution. When a word is concretely defined, it is done so in a particular time and place. Contextual interpretations permit a better understanding of certain heavy words; Atheism as a prime example. In the post-modern world Atheism has become more accepted and popular, especially as a reaction to global terrorism. However, the current definition of Atheism is terribly inaccurate. It cannot be stated properly that pagan Atheism is the same as New Atheism. By interpreting the Atheisms from four stages in the term‟s history a clearer picture of its meaning will come out, hopefully alleviating the stereotypical biases weighed upon it. In the interpretation of the Atheisms from Pagan Antiquity, the Enlightenment, the New Atheist Movement, and the American Judicial and Civil Religious system, a defense of the theory of elastic contextual interpretations, rather than concrete definitions, shall be made. Rejecting the Definitive: A Contextual Examination of Three Historical Stages of Atheism and the Legality of an American Freedom from Religion by Ethan Gjerset Quillen, B.A., M.A. A Thesis Approved by the J.M. Dawson Institute of Church-State Studies ___________________________________ Robyn L. Driskell, Ph.D., Interim Chairperson Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of Baylor University in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Master of Arts Approved by the Thesis Committee ___________________________________ T.
    [Show full text]
  • Daniel Dennett's Science of the Soul
    Daniel Dennett’s Science of the Soul - The New Yorker 3/20/17, 9:38 AM P!FI"S MARCH 27, 2017 I#UE DANIEL DENNE$’S SCIENCE OF THE SOUL A philosopher’s lifelong quest to understand the making of the mind. By Joshua Rothman Daniel Dennett’s naturalistic account of consciousness draws some people in and puts others off. “There ain’t no magic here,” he says. “Just stage magic.” PHOTOGRAPH BY IRINA ROZOVSKY FOR THE NEW YORKER our billion years ago, Earth was a lifeless place. Nothing struggled, F thought, or wanted. Slowly, that changed. Seawater leached chemicals from rocks; near thermal vents, those chemicals jostled and combined. Some hit upon the trick of making copies of themselves that, in turn, made more copies. The replicating chains were caught in oily bubbles, which protected them and made replication easier; eventually, they began to venture out into the open sea. A new level of order had been achieved on Earth. Life had begun. The tree of life grew, its branches stretching toward complexity. Organisms developed systems, subsystems, and sub-subsystems, layered in ever-deepening regression. They used these systems to anticipate their future and to change it. When they looked within, some found that they had selves—constellations of memories, ideas, and purposes that emerged from the systems inside. They experienced being alive and had thoughts about that experience. They developed language and used it to know themselves; they began to ask how they had been made. This, to a !rst approximation, is the secular story of our creation.
    [Show full text]
  • A Naturalistic Perspective on Intentionality. Interview with Daniel Dennett
    Mind & Society, 6, 2002, Vol. 3, pp. 1-12 2002, Rosenberg & Sellier, Fondazione Rosselli A naturalistic perspective on intentionality. Interview with Daniel Dennett by Marco Mirolli Marco Mirolli You describe yourself as a philosopher of mind and you reject the exhortations to get more involved in the abstract problems of ontology and of philosophy of science in general, even if the problems of the philosophy of mind and those of philosophy of science are deeply mutually dependent. I think this is an important issue because, while you say that your philosophy presupposes only the standard scientific ontology and epistemology 1, it seems to me that what you really presuppose is rather a Quinean view of ontology and epistemology, which is not so standard, even if it may well be the one we should accept. Daniel Dennett Well, maybe so, let's see. Certainly I have seen almost no reason to adopt any other ontology than Quine's; and when I look at the work in the phi- losophy of science and more particularly at the work in science, I do not find any ground yet for abandoning a Quinean view of ontology for something fancier. It could happen, but I haven't seen any reason for doing this; so if you want to say that I am vulnerable on this, that's really true. I have stated that I don't see any of the complexities of science or philosophy of mind raising ontological issues that are more sophisticated than those a Quinean ontology could handle; but I may be wrong.
    [Show full text]
  • At NALC's Doorstep
    Volume 134/Number 2 February 2021 In this issue President’s Message 1 Branch Election Notices 81 Special issue LETTER CARRIER POLITICAL FUND The monthly journal of the NATIONAL ASSOCIATION OF LETTER CARRIERS ANARCHY at NALC’s doorstep— PAGE 1 { InstallInstall thethe freefree NALCNALC MemberMember AppApp forfor youryour iPhoneiPhone oror AndroidAndroid smartphonesmartphone As technology increases our ability to communicate, NALC must stay ahead of the curve. We’ve now taken the next step with the NALC Member App for iPhone and Android smartphones. The app was de- veloped with the needs of letter carriers in mind. The app’s features include: • Workplace resources, including the National • Instantaneous NALC news with Agreement, JCAM, MRS and CCA resources personalized push notifications • Interactive Non-Scheduled Days calendar and social media access • Legislative tools, including bill tracker, • Much more individualized congressional representatives and PAC information GoGo to to the the App App Store Store oror GoogleGoogle Play Play and and search search forfor “NALC “NALC Member Member App”App” toto install install for for free free President’s Message Anarchy on NALC’s doorstep have always taken great These developments have left our nation shaken. Our polit- pride in the NALC’s head- ical divisions are raw, and there now is great uncertainty about quarters, the Vincent R. the future. This will certainly complicate our efforts to advance Sombrotto Building. It sits our legislative agenda in the now-restored U.S. Capitol. But kitty-corner to the United there is reason for hope. IStates Capitol, a magnificent First, we should take solace in the fact that the attack on our and inspiring structure that has democracy utterly failed.
    [Show full text]
  • Orme) Wilberforce (Albert) Raymond Blackburn (Alexander Bell
    Copyrights sought (Albert) Basil (Orme) Wilberforce (Albert) Raymond Blackburn (Alexander Bell) Filson Young (Alexander) Forbes Hendry (Alexander) Frederick Whyte (Alfred Hubert) Roy Fedden (Alfred) Alistair Cooke (Alfred) Guy Garrod (Alfred) James Hawkey (Archibald) Berkeley Milne (Archibald) David Stirling (Archibald) Havergal Downes-Shaw (Arthur) Berriedale Keith (Arthur) Beverley Baxter (Arthur) Cecil Tyrrell Beck (Arthur) Clive Morrison-Bell (Arthur) Hugh (Elsdale) Molson (Arthur) Mervyn Stockwood (Arthur) Paul Boissier, Harrow Heraldry Committee & Harrow School (Arthur) Trevor Dawson (Arwyn) Lynn Ungoed-Thomas (Basil Arthur) John Peto (Basil) Kingsley Martin (Basil) Kingsley Martin (Basil) Kingsley Martin & New Statesman (Borlasse Elward) Wyndham Childs (Cecil Frederick) Nevil Macready (Cecil George) Graham Hayman (Charles Edward) Howard Vincent (Charles Henry) Collins Baker (Charles) Alexander Harris (Charles) Cyril Clarke (Charles) Edgar Wood (Charles) Edward Troup (Charles) Frederick (Howard) Gough (Charles) Michael Duff (Charles) Philip Fothergill (Charles) Philip Fothergill, Liberal National Organisation, N-E Warwickshire Liberal Association & Rt Hon Charles Albert McCurdy (Charles) Vernon (Oldfield) Bartlett (Charles) Vernon (Oldfield) Bartlett & World Review of Reviews (Claude) Nigel (Byam) Davies (Claude) Nigel (Byam) Davies (Colin) Mark Patrick (Crwfurd) Wilfrid Griffin Eady (Cyril) Berkeley Ormerod (Cyril) Desmond Keeling (Cyril) George Toogood (Cyril) Kenneth Bird (David) Euan Wallace (Davies) Evan Bedford (Denis Duncan)
    [Show full text]
  • Neither Logical Empiricism Nor Vitalism, but Organicism: What the Philosophy of Biology Was
    Neither Logical Empiricism nor Vitalism, but Organicism: What the Philosophy of Biology Was By: Daniel Nicholson & Richard Gawne Like a slow-burning story of triumph, the canonical narrative of the history of contemporary philosophy of biology tells the tale of a subfield emerging out of the smoldering ashes of logical empiricist philosophy of science, and the wreckage of an equally futile vitalistic program that preceded it. Most logical empiricists scoffed at the life sciences, and those who did deem it worthwhile to explore the biological realm produced nothing of value. The logical empiricists failed because their project was a prescriptive enterprise whose primary mandate was to bring increased rigour to biology by importing methodological protocols from the physical sciences. Vitalists of the early twentieth century were not stricken with physics-envy, but the animating forces and other metaphysical phantasms they conjured into existence to ward off the threat of reductionism were at least as ill-conceived as anything produced by the logical empiricists. Practitioners associated with the aforementioned schools failed to seriously engage with the science that allegedly inspired their musings, and as a consequence, the philosophy of biology languished in a state of futility for much of the twentieth century. Things began to change sometime in the late 1960s and early 1970s, when the textbooks by Michael Ruse (1973) and David Hull (1974), together with a series of articles by Ken Schaffner (1967; 1969a; 1969b) and Bill Wimsatt (1970; 1972a; 1972b), found their way into print. These efforts are regularly identified as the first significant contributions to modern philosophy of biology.
    [Show full text]
  • The Philosophy of Biology Edited by David L
    Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-85128-2 - The Cambridge Companion to the Philosophy of Biology Edited by David L. Hull and Michael Ruse Frontmatter More information the cambridge companion to THE PHILOSOPHY OF BIOLOGY The philosophy of biology is one of the most exciting new areas in the field of philosophy and one that is attracting much attention from working scientists. This Companion, edited by two of the founders of the field, includes newly commissioned essays by senior scholars and by up-and- coming younger scholars who collectively examine the main areas of the subject – the nature of evolutionary theory, classification, teleology and function, ecology, and the prob- lematic relationship between biology and religion, among other topics. Up-to-date and comprehensive in its coverage, this unique volume will be of interest not only to professional philosophers but also to students in the humanities and researchers in the life sciences and related areas of inquiry. David L. Hull is an emeritus professor of philosophy at Northwestern University. The author of numerous books and articles on topics in systematics, evolutionary theory, philosophy of biology, and naturalized epistemology, he is a recipient of a Guggenheim Foundation fellowship and is a Fellow of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences. Michael Ruse is professor of philosophy at Florida State University. He is the author of many books on evolutionary biology, including Can a Darwinian Be a Christian? and Darwinism and Its Discontents, both published by Cam- bridge University Press. A Fellow of the Royal Society of Canada and the American Association for the Advancement of Science, he has appeared on television and radio, and he contributes regularly to popular media such as the New York Times, the Washington Post, and Playboy magazine.
    [Show full text]
  • Synthetic Philosophy
    UvA-DARE (Digital Academic Repository) Synthetic Philosophy Schliesser, E. DOI 10.1007/s10539-019-9673-3 Publication date 2019 Document Version Final published version Published in Biology and Philosophy License CC BY Link to publication Citation for published version (APA): Schliesser, E. (2019). Synthetic Philosophy. Biology and Philosophy, 34(2), [19]. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-019-9673-3 General rights It is not permitted to download or to forward/distribute the text or part of it without the consent of the author(s) and/or copyright holder(s), other than for strictly personal, individual use, unless the work is under an open content license (like Creative Commons). Disclaimer/Complaints regulations If you believe that digital publication of certain material infringes any of your rights or (privacy) interests, please let the Library know, stating your reasons. In case of a legitimate complaint, the Library will make the material inaccessible and/or remove it from the website. Please Ask the Library: https://uba.uva.nl/en/contact, or a letter to: Library of the University of Amsterdam, Secretariat, Singel 425, 1012 WP Amsterdam, The Netherlands. You will be contacted as soon as possible. UvA-DARE is a service provided by the library of the University of Amsterdam (https://dare.uva.nl) Download date:25 Sep 2021 Biology & Philosophy (2019) 34:19 https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-019-9673-3 REVIEW ESSAY Synthetic philosophy Eric Schliesser1 Received: 4 November 2018 / Accepted: 11 February 2019 © The Author(s) 2019 Abstract In this essay, I discuss Dennett’s From Bacteria to Bach and Back: The Evolution of Minds (hereafter From Bacteria) and Godfrey Smith’s Other Minds: The Octopus and The Evolution of Intelligent Life (hereafter Other Minds) from a methodologi- cal perspective.
    [Show full text]