Part I., Thales to Plato. by John Burnet. London: Macmillan and Co., 1914

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Part I., Thales to Plato. by John Burnet. London: Macmillan and Co., 1914 The Classical Review http://journals.cambridge.org/CAR Additional services for The Classical Review: Email alerts: Click here Subscriptions: Click here Commercial reprints: Click here Terms of use : Click here Burnet's Greek Philosophy Greek Philosophy: Part I., Thales to Plato. By John Burnet. London: Macmillan and Co., 1914. 10s. net. A. C. Pearson The Classical Review / Volume 29 / Issue 05 / August 1915, pp 141 - 143 DOI: 10.1017/S0009840X00048587, Published online: 27 October 2009 Link to this article: http://journals.cambridge.org/abstract_S0009840X00048587 How to cite this article: A. C. Pearson (1915). The Classical Review, 29, pp 141-143 doi:10.1017/ S0009840X00048587 Request Permissions : Click here Downloaded from http://journals.cambridge.org/CAR, IP address: 130.88.90.140 on 30 Mar 2015 THE CLASSICAL REVIEW 141 REVIEWS BURNET'S GREEK PHILOSOPHY. Greek Philosophy: Part I., Thales to accordingly obliged to meet the inevit- Plato. By JOHN BURNET. London : able difficulty arising out of the incon- Macmillan and Co., 1914. 10s. net. sistency of their doctrine with the ideal system expounded in the Phaedo and THIS is a book of first-rate importance. Republic. To put it briefly, what are In the course of 350 pages Professor we to make of the criticism of the Burnet provides his readers with a Parmenides and of the ontology of the succinct account of the progress of Philebus ? Or again, what is the Greek philosophy up to and including significance of Aristotle's references to the final development of the Platonic the ideal numbers ? Whereas Jackson system. It is not so much a general found the solution in a revised Platon- history of the various philosophical ism, Burnet (as those who are ac- schools aiming at the inclusion of all quainted with his edition of the Phaedo the chief points of doctrine, as a are aware) sees in those of Plato's summary appreciation of what each writings, which are usually accounted thinker contributed to the common most characteristic, very little1 that is stock. It is probably superfluous to not to be regarded as the actual teach- commend the author's complete control ing of Socrates. In other words, the of his material, his thorough indepen- Platonic Socrates is not to be separated dence of judgement, and the admirable from Socrates as he really was. clearness of style whereby, notwith- This startling conclusion, which is standing the obscurity of much of the developed in Book II., is so subversive subject-matter, he never allows us to of established opinion that it is not miss the track of his argument. likely to pass unchallenged. But The volume is divided into three Professor Burnet goes even further Books. The first deals with the pre- than has been indicated above in his Socratics ending with Leucippus, the reconstruction of the figure of Socrates. second with the Sophists, Socrates, Thus it is held that the theory of ideas and Democritus, and the third, which originated with the Pythagoreans is half as long again as either of the (p. 91), and that Socrates, who was in others, with Plato. It is unnecessary fact at the head of a Pythagorean to speak of the first Book, which is society at Athens (pp. 147, 152), in- mainly a resume of the 1908 edition of herited it from them (p. 156 f.). The Early Greek Philosophy. On the other oracle given to Chaerephon marked a hand, Book III. is entirely new, and dividing-point in Socrates' life; whereas will be eagerly read; though it should the earlier part was occupied with re- be observed that the author apologizes ligious and scientific study and parti- in his Preface for being obliged to cularly with his theory of the ' forms,' state conclusions without .discussing the later was almost entirely devoted their grounds, and hopes to remedy to the prosecution of the mission the defect on another occasion. The whereby he set himself to convict his greater part consists of an analytical fellow-citizens of ignorance (p. 144). exposition of the philosophical results The difference between the respective obtained in the dialogues Theaetetus, Par- menides, Sophist, Politicus, Laws, Phile- 1 Professor Burnet does not venture to main- bus, and Timaeus. The enumeration is tain that Socrates is never employed to advocate Platonic doctrine; a notable instance in the Re- enough to show that Professor Burnet public is discussed on p. 232. But the attempts is in sympathy with the movement to account for the appearance of Socrates as pioneered by Professor Henry Jackson, protagonist in the Theaetetus and the Philebus which sought to vindicate the import- (pp. 235, 237, 248, 324) are not without a suspi- cion of special pleading, or of what is elsewhere ance of the later dialogues as the ulti- (p. 150) deprecated as 'picking and choosing mate expression of Platonism. He is whatever we please out of Plato.' 142 THE CLASSICAL REVIEW portraits in the Clouds and the Memor- represent him as advocating in his own abilia is explained as partly due to the person the views of each particular fact that Xenophon only knew Socrates adherent. This was a convention which when he was already an old man everyone understood, and the procedure (p. 147). Even apart from this, the attributed to Plato was exactly parallel credibility of Xenophon is very severely to that adopted by Aeschines, Antis- assailed: his acquaintance with Socrates thenes, and Phaedo. was slight, and his motive was that of The main issue cannot, of course, be the professional romance-writer. On adequately discussed within the limits the other hand, it is incredible that in of a review; but a few observations on a dialogue designed to record the con- the treatment of the evidence may not versation of his teacher's last hours Plato be out of place. Much of it is difficult used Socrates merely as a mask for his to appraise; but I am afraid that, in own personality. spite of his candour, Professor Burnet In belabouring the inadequacy of has not always avoided the advocate's Xenophon, Professor Burnet is engaged bias. Verbal points are sometimes in flogging a dead horse. Everyone pressed which are without substance. admits that for its life-like representa- Thus it is argued that the use by tion of Socrates both as man and as Polyxenus of the terms i^roxn and philosopher the value of Plato's testi- fjue-Tovaia in his statement of the rpirot mony is incomparable. But the ques- avdpairo'i shows that the objection was tion still remains whether the very not directed against Plato, who never poverty of Xenophon's philosophical employs these words (p. 259, n. 2). insight has not made him a trustworthy But surely the Platonic fierexeiv and witness concerning the general scope fieOegi? are a sufficient justification for and outline of Socratic teaching. It Polyxenus' terminology. When Aris- does not help matters to argue that totle (de gen. et corr. B 6 335b 10) quotes Xenophon was an associate of Socrates' ' Socrates in the Phaedo' as the author old age ; for on the same principle we of the doctrine of /te'tfeft?, Professor should have expected Plato to be chary Burnet strangely insists (p. 166 n.) in his references to the ideal theory, that the theory is not attributed to which ex hypothesi belonged chiefly to Plato, but to ' Socrates in the Phaedo.' the earlier period. A good deal of It would be at least equally cogent to stress is laid on the contention that observe that it is attributed to ' Socrates the Platonic Socrates should not be in the Phaedo' rather than to Socrates. treated as a fictitious character, and But these are small matters. In general, that if Plato did not mean what he I doubt if sufficient weight has been said his procedure was no less myster- given to the consensus of later opinion ious than inexcusable (pp. 150, 155, that Plato originated the theory of 179 : cf. Phaedo, pp. x-xii). But there ideas. The consequent depreciation of are other circumstances to be con- Aristotle is perhaps the least satisfac- sidered before we can refuse to admit tory feature of the book. When the that even in the Phaedo Socrates may question under discussion is the inter- have posed as the mouthpiece of pretation pf the Platonic documents, Platonism. We have seen that it is it is misleading to describe the evidence impossible to get rid of ' the Platonic of Aristotle—our best independent wit- Socrates' altogether; and we must ness—as being merely ' hearsay and not forget the character of the public inference' employed ' to discredit first- for whose benefit the dialogues were hand testimony' (p. 157, n. 4). A great published. In a limited circle much deal necessarily turns on what Aristotle may be taken for granted. The Socratic meant by saying that Socrates did not schools after the death of the master make universals xmpuna, whereas Plato vied with each other in claiming to be did {Met. A 6. g8yh 8, M 4. io78b 32). his true successors; and the various He is understood by Professor Burnet leaders, in order to base their teaching (pp. 165, 316) to have been referring to on Socrates' authority, made it a the Kowtovla of the forms with the practice in their published writings to particulars as expounded by Socrates THE CLASSICAL REVIEW 143 in the Phaedo and Republic. The reason- other. In Book M precisely the same ing fails to convince when we remem- influences are attributed to those who ber that it was Plato, who, according first propounded the theory of ideas.
Recommended publications
  • Matter and Minds: Examining Embodied Souls in Plato's Timaeus
    Matter and Minds: Examining Embodied Souls in Plato’s Timaeus and Ancient Philosophy By Emily Claire Kotow A thesis submitted to the Graduate Program in Philosophy in conformity with the requirements for the Master of Arts Queen’s University Kingston, Ontario, Canada September, 2018 Copyright © Emily Claire Kotow, 2018 Abstract With the rise of Platonism influenced by Plotinus and Descartes, philosophers have largely overlooked the fact that Plato directly acknowledges that there is a practical and valuable role for the body. The Timaeus clearly demonstrates that Plato took the idea of embodied minds seriously, not just as an afterthought of the immortal soul. Ultimately this research demonstrates that Plato did not fundamentally have a problem with the mind-body relationship. In offering an argument for Plato’s positive ideas of embodied minds and the necessity thereof, I will also demonstrate, through a historical comparative, why I think the emphasis on mind rather than on embodied mind might have occurred. ii Acknowledgments I would like to thank Dr. Jon Miller and the Philosophy Department of Queen’s University for allowing me to pursue my interests freely -a great privilege that few are fortunate enough to experience. iii Table of Contents Abstract………………………………….………………………………….…………………………………. ii Acknowledgments………………………………….………………………………….………………….. iii Table of Contents………………………………….………………………………….…………………….iv Introduction………………………………….………………………………….……………………………5 Chapter One: Plato’s Embodied Soul.……………………………….……………………………12 i. Plato and
    [Show full text]
  • Anaximander and the Problem of the Earth's Immobility
    Binghamton University The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB) The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter 12-28-1953 Anaximander and the Problem of the Earth's Immobility John Robinson Windham College Follow this and additional works at: https://orb.binghamton.edu/sagp Recommended Citation Robinson, John, "Anaximander and the Problem of the Earth's Immobility" (1953). The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter. 263. https://orb.binghamton.edu/sagp/263 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB). It has been accepted for inclusion in The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter by an authorized administrator of The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB). For more information, please contact [email protected]. JOHN ROBINSON Windham College Anaximander and the Problem of the Earth’s Immobility* N the course of his review of the reasons given by his predecessors for the earth’s immobility, Aristotle states that “some” attribute it I neither to the action of the whirl nor to the air beneath’s hindering its falling : These are the causes with which most thinkers busy themselves. But there are some who say, like Anaximander among the ancients, that it stays where it is because of its “indifference” (όμοιότητα). For what is stationed at the center, and is equably related to the extremes, has no reason to go one way rather than another—either up or down or sideways. And since it is impossible for it to move simultaneously in opposite directions, it necessarily stays where it is.1 The ascription of this curious view to Anaximander appears to have occasioned little uneasiness among modern commentators.
    [Show full text]
  • Parmenides B6.1–2 Without a Modal Fallacy
    Aporia vol. 21 no. 1—2011 Parmenides B6.1–2 without a Modal Fallacy MICHAEL J. HANSEN n all accounts, Parmenides makes a marvelous argument in the Way of Truth. However, there is no clear consensus among inter- Opreters about how to read it. The only noncontroversial point in interpreting the work seems to be that in it, Parmenides did something pro- found to philosophy. Despite this collective obligation to acknowledge Par- menides’ unique innovation (whatever it may be), it has become popular to read Parmenides as relying on a modal fallacy to make his argument. This would be an embarrassing mistake for such an influential work, especially given the argument’s deductive appearance. In this paper, I will outline the modal fallacy that Parmenides is accused of and argue for an interpretation that is free of the fallacy. I. The Alleged Modal Fallacy The critical fragment we must examine to decide the question is B6.1–2, in which the fallacy is supposed to occur: crhV toV levgein te noei`n t' ejoVn e!mmenai e!sti gaVr ei^nai, mhdeVn d' oujk e!otin . (Graham 214) Michael J. Hansen is a senior majoring in philosophy at Brigham Young University. He is interested in ancient philosophy, the philosophy of mind, epistemology, and metaphysics. In the fall, he will be pursuing a PhD in philosophy at the University of California–Los Angeles. This essay placed first in the 2011 David H. Yarn Philosophical Essay Contest. 2 MICHAEL J. HANSEN As usual, Parmenides’ language admits of many permissible translations for interpreters to quibble over, but this fragment is exceptionally difficult to render.
    [Show full text]
  • Commentary on Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics
    PML9_Aristotle_2006 Page i Friday, February 17, 2006 10:53 AM The Peter Martyr Library Volume Nine Commentary on Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics PML9_Aristotle_2006 Page ii Friday, February 17, 2006 10:53 AM Habent sua fata libelli EDITORS OF THE PETER MARTYR LIBRARY, SERIES ONE GENERAL EDITORS John Patrick Donnelly, S.J., Frank A James III, Joseph C. McLelland EDITORIAL COMMITTEE W. J. Torrance Kirby, William J. Klempa EDITORIAL BOARD IRENA BACKUS JOHN MCINTYRE Institut d’histoire de la Réformation University of Edinburgh Université de Genève MICHAEL PERCIVAL-MAXWELL PETER S. BIETENHOLZ McGill University, Montreal University of Saskatchewan H. WAYNE PIPKIN FRITZ BÜSSER Associated Mennonite Institut für Schweizer Biblical Seminaries Reformationsgeschichte, Zurich JILL RAITT EMIDIO CAMPI University of Missouri, Columbia Institut für Schweizer Reformationsgeschichte, Zurich ROBERT V. SCHNUCKER University of Northern Iowa RICHARD C. GAMBLE Reformed Theological Seminary DAN SHUTE The Presbyterian College, Montreal TIMOTHY GEORGE Beeson Divinity School JOHN TEDESCHI University of Wisconsin–Madison ROBERT M. KINGDON Institute for Research in the Humanities THOMAS F. TORRANCE University of Wisconsin–Madison University of Edinburgh DIARMAID MACCULLOUGH JOHN VISSERS St. Cross College, Oxford University The Presbyterian College, Montreal ALISTER E. MCGRATH CESARE VASOLI Wycliffe Hall, Oxford University Università de Firenze The Peter Martyr Library Volume Nine COMMENTARY ON Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics Peter Martyr Vermigli Edited by Emidio Campi and Joseph C. McLelland with introduction and annotations by Joseph C. McLelland VOLUME LXXIII SIXTEENTH CENTURY ESSAYS & STUDIES KIRKSVILLE, MISSOURI USA ◆ 2006 Title Page PML9_NicoEth_Prelim Page iv Wednesday, February 22, 2006 12:54 PM Copyright 2006 by Truman State University Press, Kirksville, Missouri All rights reserved.
    [Show full text]
  • Arethas of Caesarea and the Scholia On
    Ryan Bailey ARETHAS OF CAESAREA AND THE SCHOLIA ON PHILOSTRATUS’ VITA APOLLONII IN LAUR. 69.33 MA Thesis in Medieval Studies Central European University CEU eTD Collection Budapest May 2012 ARETHAS OF CAESAREA AND THE SCHOLIA ON PHILOSTRATUS’ VITA APOLLONII IN LAUR. 69.33 by Ryan Bailey (USA) Thesis submitted to the Department of Medieval Studies, Central European University, Budapest, in partial fulfillment of the requirements of the Master of Arts degree in Medieval Studies. Accepted in conformance with the standards of the CEU. ____________________________________________ Chair, Examination Committee ____________________________________________ Thesis Supervisor ____________________________________________ Examiner ____________________________________________ CEU eTD Collection Examiner Budapest May 2012 ii ARETHAS OF CAESAREA AND THE SCHOLIA ON PHILOSTRATUS’ VITA APOLLONII IN LAUR. 69.33 by Ryan Bailey (USA) Thesis submitted to the Department of Medieval Studies, Central European University, Budapest, in partial fulfillment of the requirements of the Master of Arts degree in Medieval Studies. Accepted in conformance with the standards of the CEU. ____________________________________________ External Reader CEU eTD Collection Budapest May 2012 iii ARETHAS OF CAESAREA AND THE SCHOLIA ON PHILOSTRATUS’ VITA APOLLONII IN LAUR. 69.33 by Ryan Bailey (USA) Thesis submitted to the Department of Medieval Studies, Central European University, Budapest, in partial fulfillment of the requirements of the Master of Arts degree in Medieval Studies. Accepted in conformance with the standards of the CEU. ________________________ Supervisor ____________________________________________ External Supervisor CEU eTD Collection Budapest May 2012 iv I, the undersigned, Ryan Bailey , candidate for the MA degree in Medieval Studies, declare herewith that the present thesis is exclusively my own work, based on my research and only such external information as properly credited in notes and bibliography.
    [Show full text]
  • 162 Aristotle on Practical Inference, the Explanation of Action, And
    Aristotle on Practical the Inference, Explanation of Action, and Akrasia GERASIMOS SANTAS n his edition of the Nicomachean Ethics John Burnet added two as relevant to Aristotle's discussion of appendices particularly akrasia (weakness). The first appendix, De Anima, I I I , 10, contains Aristotle's discussion of how practical reason and want combine to cause movement for the sake of something and how explanations of action can be constructed in terms of these two elements; in the other appendix, De Motu 7, Aristotle casts explanations of actions in the form of practical inferences. The relevance of these passages to Aris- totle's discussion of akrasia is beyond dispute: Aristotle explicitly employs practical inferences to represent the motivations of the akrates (weak man), and he clearly regards the behavior of the akrates as a case of movement for the sake of something, a case of action. Bumet's appendices suggest what seems to me the only sound strategy for unraveling and understanding Aristotle's explanation of akrasia. We must place this explanation within Aristotle's general theory of the explanation of action and the role of practical inference in such explanation. Akrasia is a difficult case with problems peculiar to it, but all the same it is a case of movement for the sake of something, and in explaining it Aristotle follows his paradigm of the explanation of action. In this paper I wish to take full advantage of this strategy in an attempt to reconstruct in detail and take a fresh look at Aristotle's account of akrasia. The dividends of this strategy will show them- selves, I hope, as I try along the way to resolve some of the textual and philosophical difficulties in Aristotle's account, difficulties traditionally 1 and recently raised by commentators.
    [Show full text]
  • The Fragments of the Poem of Parmenides
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by D-Scholarship@Pitt RESTORING PARMENIDES’ POEM: ESSAYS TOWARD A NEW ARRANGEMENT OF THE FRAGMENTS BASED ON A REASSESSMENT OF THE ORIGINAL SOURCES by Christopher John Kurfess B.A., St. John’s College, 1995 M.A., St. John’s College, 1996 M.A., University of Hawai‘i at Mānoa, 2000 Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of The Dietrich School of Arts and Sciences in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy University of Pittsburgh 2012 UNVERSITY OF PITTSBURGH The Dietrich School of Arts and Sciences This dissertation was presented by Christopher J. Kurfess It was defended on November 8, 2012 and approved by Dr. Andrew M. Miller, Professor, Department of Classics Dr. John Poulakos, Associate Professor, Department of Communication Dr. Mae J. Smethurst, Professor, Department of Classics Dissertation Supervisor: Dr. Edwin D. Floyd, Professor, Department of Classics ii Copyright © by Christopher J. Kurfess 2012 iii RESTORING PARMENIDES’ POEM Christopher J. Kurfess, Ph.D. University of Pittsburgh, 2012 The history of philosophy proper, claimed Hegel, began with the poem of the Presocratic Greek philosopher Parmenides. Today, that poem is extant only in fragmentary form, the various fragments surviving as quotations, translations or paraphrases in the works of better-preserved authors of antiquity. These range from Plato, writing within a century after Parmenides’ death, to the sixth-century C.E. commentator Simplicius of Cilicia, the latest figure known to have had access to the complete poem. Since the Renaissance, students of Parmenides have relied on collections of fragments compiled by classical scholars, and since the turn of the twentieth century, Hermann Diels’ Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker, through a number of editions, has remained the standard collection for Presocratic material generally and for the arrangement of Parmenides’ fragments in particular.
    [Show full text]
  • An Introduction to Early Greek Philosophy: the Chief Fragments and Ancient Testimony, with Connecting Commentary
    Book Reviews An Introduction to Early Greek Philosophy: The Chief Fragments and Ancient Testimony, with Connecting Commentary. By John Mansley Robinson. (Boston: Houghton Mifflin Company, 1968. Pp. x+342. $4.25. Paper.) This is a book that fills a long-standing need and does it well. In the past, the teacher of a survey course in the history of ancient philosophy who wished to cover the pre-Socratics more fully than is done in one of the several anthologies of Greek philosophy had awkward options. The most up-to-date and authoritative of the text- books, G. S. Kirk and J. E. Raven's The Presocratic Philosophers, is too forbidding for a course at the sophomore-junior level. John Burnet's classic, Early Greek Philo- sophy, still unsurpassed in the quality of translation, puts one-sided emphasis on the scientific character of early Greek philosophy. Besides, neither Kirk-Raven nor Burner cover the Sophists (Burnet not even Democritus). Kathleen Freeman's Ancilla to the Pre-Socratic Philosophers (a translation of the B sections in Diels-Kranz, Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker) has the virtue that it gives the student a forceful and graphic impression of the scantiness of actual fragments; but the student is likely to feel more bewildered than challenged. As for the anthologies devoted specifically to the pre- Socratic.s, Milton C. Nahm's Selections from Early Greek Philosophy is badly dated, and PhiLip Wheelwright's The Presocratics takes excessive liberties with translation. Robinson's book now affords an excellent choice. The selection of primary source materials for the whole sequence from Ionians to Sophists is adequate to generous.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotle's Theory of Incontinence Roy A
    ARISTOTLE'S THEORY OF INCONTINENCE BY ROY A. CLOUSER One of the better known theses in the history of practical ethics is Socrates' theory that no one ever commits an act knowing it to be bad. Both Plato (Protagoras 352 B C, 358 ff.) and Xenophon (Memorabilia III, 9, 5) represent Socrates as holding that if a man knows what is best he will do it; only when he ignorantly mistakes something bad for what is good does he do the bad thing. In the Nicomachean Ethics Aristotle also attri- butes this view to Socrates and takes strong exception to it. Now despite Aristotle's declared opposition to this view, a number of commentators have interpreted his treatment of the issue to be actually the same as or at least compatible with that of Socrates. My purpose here will be to suggest that such interpretations are without sufficient textual basis. Accordingly I will not be concerned with questions of dating, compilation, and authorship connected with the Nicomachean ethics, but will restrict my remarks strictly to an exegesis of the text as it stands. Referring to the commission of an act while knowing that it is wrong as "incontenence", Aristotle remarks: "Now we may ask how a man who judges rightly can behave incontin- ently. That he should behave so when he has knowledge, some say is impossible; for it would be strange - so Socrates thought - if when knowledge was in a man something else could master it and drag it about like a slave." (1145 b 22-25). Aristotle goes on to say that this position of Socrates' contradicts observed facts.
    [Show full text]
  • Greek Philosophy Macmillan and Co., Limited London Bombay Calcutta - Madras Melbourne the Macmillan Company New York Boston * Chicago Dallas San Francisco
    of flijiiosopijp GREEK PHILOSOPHY MACMILLAN AND CO., LIMITED LONDON BOMBAY CALCUTTA - MADRAS MELBOURNE THE MACMILLAN COMPANY NEW YORK BOSTON * CHICAGO DALLAS SAN FRANCISCO THE MACMILLAN CO. OF CANADA, LTD. TORONTO GREEK PHILOSOPHY PART I THALES TO PLATO BY JOHN BURNET MACMILLAN AND CO., LIMITED ST. MARTIN'S STREET, LONDON 1924 COPYRIGHT First Edition 1914. Reprinted 1920, 1924. PRINTED IN GREAT BRITAIN PREFACE THE preparation of this volume was undertaken some the Lexicon years ago, but was interrupted by my work on Platonicum, which has proved a more formidable task than was at first anticipated. I have to thank the editor of this series and the publishers for their generous indulgence in the circumstances. It is unfortunate in some respects that I have been in a form obliged to deal with certain parts of the subject which does not admit of detailed argument and still less Greek of controversy. The second edition of my Early Philosophy (referred to as E. Gr. Phf} makes this in large measure unnecessary in Book L, but there are certain parts of Book III. where I have had to state my conclusions baldly in the hope that I may have a later opportunity for the of discussing their grounds. My chief aim present has been to assist students who wish to acquire a firsthand of knowledge of what Plato actually says in the dialogues some- Jiis maturity. So long as they are content to know Platonism thing of the Republic and the earlier dialogues, must be a sealed book to them. I have not thought it well to present Greek names in a Latin dress.
    [Show full text]
  • Classical Studies Departmental Library Booklist
    Page 1 of 81 Department of Classical Studies Library Listing Call Number ISBN # Title Edition Author Author 2 Author 3 Publisher Year Quantity 0 584100051 The origins of alchemy in Graeco-Roman Egypt Jack Lindsay, 1900- London, Frederick Muller Limited 1970 0 500275866 The Mycenaeans Revised edition Lord William Taylour, London, Thames & Hudson 1990 M. Tulli Ciceronis oratio Philippica secunda : with introduction and 6280.A32P2 Stereotyped edition Marcus Tullius Cicero A. G. Peskett, ed. London, Cambridge University Press 1896 notes by A.G. Peskett A258.A75 1923 A practical introduction to Greek prose composition New Impression Thomas Kerchever Evelyn Abbott London : Longmans, Green, and Co. 1923 Gaius Valerius London : Heinemann ; New York : G. P. A6264.A2 Catullus, Tibullus, and Pervigilium Veneris F. W. Cornish 1931 Catullus, Tibullus Putnam's Sons Lucretius on matter and man. Extracts from books I, II, IV & V of the De scientific appendices AC1.E8 A. S. Cox N. A. M. Wallis London, G. Bell & Sons Ltd. 1967 rerum natura. by R.I. Gedye AM1.M76 1981 3 59810118X Museums of the world Third, revised edition Judy Benson, ed. Barbara Fischer, ed. [et al] München ; New York : K.G. Saur 1981 AM101.B87 T73 1971 0 002118343 Treasures of the British Museum: with an introduction Sir John Wolfenden London, Collins 1971 AS121.H47 Vol. 104 & Dublin : Hodges, Figgis & Co. Ltd. ; ISSN: 0018-1750 Hermathena : a Dublin University review No. CIV, Spring 1967 Trinity College Dublin 1967 105 1967 London : The Academic Press Ltd. AS121.H47 Vol. 110 - Dublin : Hodges, Figgis & Co. Ltd. ; ISSN: 0018-1750 Hermathena : a Dublin University review No.
    [Show full text]
  • Background: Parmenides and Plato
    POEM OF PARMENIDES English translation : John Burnet (1892) I The steeds that bear me carried me as far as ever my heart Desired, since they brought me and set me on the renowned Way of the goddess, who with her own hands conducts the man who knows through all things. On what way was I borne along; for on it did the wise steeds carry me, drawing my car, and maidens showed the way. And the axle, glowing in the socket - for it was urged round by the whirling wheels at each end - gave forth a sound as of a pipe, when the daughters of the Sun, hasting to convey me into the light, threw back their veils from off their faces and left the abode of Night. There are the gates of the ways of Night and Day, fitted above with a lintel and below with a threshold of stone. They themselves, high in the air, are closed by mighty doors, and Avenging Justice keeps the keys that open them. Her did the maidens entreat with gentle words and skilfully persuade to unfasten without demur the bolted bars from the gates. Then, when the doors were thrown back, they disclosed a widepening, when their brazen hinges swung backwards in the sockets fastened with rivets and nails. Straight through them, on the broad way, did the maidens guide the horses and the car, and the goddess greeted me kindly, and took my right hand in hers, and spake to me these words: - Welcome, noble youth, that comest to my abode on the car that bears thee tended by immortal charioteers ! It is no ill chance, but justice and right that has sent thee forth to travel on this way.
    [Show full text]