Ethics 18 Notes 04

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Ethics 18 Notes 04 BARRY STOCKER (Dr) Faculty of Science and Letters Assistant Professor Department of Humanities and Social Science ([email protected]) https://barrystockerac.wordpress.com ETHICS. SPRING 2018 İTB 219E NOTES: WEEK FOUR Lucius Annaeus Seneca the Younger (1BCE-65CE). Seneca was born in Cordoba, a major Roman centre in southern Spain. His father (Lucius Annaeus Seneca the Elder) was a member of the lower Roman aristocracy (known as knights or equestrians, the senators were the upper aristocracy) who moved to Cordoba and was himself a well known rhetorician (public speaker and debater, thinker about speech and argument). He sent the younger Seneca to be educated in Rome where he rose to become tutor to the future emperor Nero and then adviser when Nero became Emperor. Before he became teacher to Nero (reigned 54-68CE), Seneca had some experience of the dangers of being close to power in the Roman Empire, when he was exiled to Corsica by the Emperor Claudius (reigned 41-54CE) due to accusations from the first wife of Claudius of an affair with a relative of the Emperor. He was recalled to Rome after Claudius had married his second wife, the mother of Nero. He had problems before then with the Emperor Caligula (37-41CE), who was famously cruel and paranoiac. Seneca did well at first from his association with Nero, and was also able to become very rich, partly as a major money lender of the Empire. It has been suggested that his demands for repayment and interest had a negative affect on the economy of Britannia (Roman England and Wales), contributing to the revolt of Queen Boudica. Nero’s increasingly unbalanced behaviour led Seneca to retire from state service and lead a private scholarly life. However, a conspiracy against Nero led to a purge of Nero’s enemies real, and imagined; and Seneca was forced to commit suicide. Nero’s irrationality led to a military uprising and he committed suicide himself to avoid execution. Seneca wrote philosophy in the form of literature in essays and letters (sometimes referred to as dialogues). He also wrote tragic plays which are not often staged, but are often read and influenced later dramatists including Shakespeare. His nephew Lucan was also a major literary figure, one of the major Roman poets. ‘ON TRANQUILITY OF MIND’. Seneca’s moral ideas were Stoic in nature, but also refer to the Cynics and Epicureans. Very little survives from the early Greek Stoics, so we will study Stoicism through Seneca. The Stoic School was founded by Zeno (334-262 BCE) of Citium (Larnaka in Cyprus). Zeno moved to Athens and the school was named after the Stoa (porch) in the colonnade in the Agora (market place) of Athens. Zeno’s less well known successor as head of the School was Cleanthes (died 232 BCE) of Assos (Aegean Anatolia). Cleanthes’ successor was a major Stoic philosopher, Chryssipus (born in Anatolia around what is now Adana, then moved to Athens) who wrote huge numbers of books, none of which have survived. What can be inferred from references in ancient texts is that the Stoics had a view of ethics based on behaving rationally and following nature. They also developed philosophies of the physical universe, logic, and signs in nature and speech. That Seneca was a major figure in the Roman state, as well as in philosophy, shows the influence Stoicism had on educated Romans. This is confirmed by the visit the Emperor Hadrian (117-138) made to the school of the Greek Stoic philosopher Epictetus (his Discourses is one of the major Stoic classics) who was a tutor in Rome before founding his school in Greece, and even more so by the Stoic Meditations (written in Greek, still widely read) of the Emperor Marcus Aurelius (161-180). Seneca presents his philosophy in ‘On Tranquility of Mind’ through a dialogue with his friend Serenus, who lacks such tranquility. The dialogue just consists of a short discourse from Serenus, followed by a long reply from Seneca. Serenus outlines the ideal of a simple life. Serenus’ idea of a simple life is to have only a few slaves who are dressed simply and to only own silver inherited within the family. This idea of a simple life is that of an aristocrat who avoids ostentatious luxury. The life of politics can be part of the life which brings tranquility as well as the simple country life mentioned by Serenus. Seneca also refers to the merits of an isolated contemplative life in the countryside. The danger of the contemplative life is that the mind is easily bored and needs new ideas all the time. In an isolated life this can lead to unhealthy obsessive desires for power and revenge disturbing the gains of a contemplative life. The same problem of boredom appears in the city with !2 the kind of individual who is rushing round the city and wants to seem part of all important aspects of its life, but is not in reality accepted by any group in the city and has no influence. Boredom arises from no activity, but also from too much of the wrong kind of activity. The goal should be to concentrate on limited tasks and not lose yourself in endless varied activities.Seneca refers to the danger of revealing the self, when leading the kind of life that means putting on a mask. Seneca refers to very showy kind of people. Seneca refers to the three founders of Stoicism mentioned above and the importance of following them. He also mentions Diogenes, meaning Diogenes (404-323BCE) of Sinope (Sinop, Black Sea coast of Anatolia). Diogenes is the most important representative of Cynic philosophy. Cynic comes from the Greek word of dog (Kynos), and the school had this label because they believed it was admirable to live without property or social manners.What Seneca mentions about Diogenes is that he got rid of all his property.This protected him from influences beyond his control, and suffering from bad fortune. In having no property, or social status The important thing is to recognise that we come from nature, that our life and everything we have, is something that nature can take from us at any moment; or a cruel Emperor, as Seneca mentions in a reference to Caligula (under his proper name of Gaius, Caligula was a nickname). Tranquility of mind requires us to be ready to lose everything including life, and that enables us to live rationally and without boredom. He was thinking of the way that they all placed justice and morality above political authority and admired the person who resists the bad ruler, though not violently. Tranquillity of mind does not depend simply on philosophical ideas and having the right intentions. We need variety Seneca thinks, though he gives priority to private contemplation. Rest, holidays, travel, changes of activity prevent is from becoming restless and bored. Serenus reports that when he looks into himself, he sees some vices on the surface. Some are more hidden, and some are completely hidden but will come back. This kind of introspection is not as obvious in Seneca’s time as now, there was less sense of an inner self of an infinite consciousness hidden from introspection without great effort, and maybe not even then. The emergence of this way of thinking about the self has ethical implications, how can we master our vices, following virtue and reason as all the ancient ethicists hoped. Serenus finds the vices which have apparently disappeared the most dangerous, because it is difficult to know when they will return and strike. Serenus thinks of this in terms of the danger of a country being invaded. Serenus thinks of the state of mind in which he is afraid of the return of vices, as irritable and argumentative, in between illness and health. Serenus also emphasises the in between nature of his state of mind. Serenus expects Seneca to reply that virtues take habit to grow and that it takes effort time to acquire virtues, and overcome vices. Serenus puts this in terms of achieving something admired by others. In particular he mentions eloquence/rhetoric, and important skill for the antique aristocracy. Over time we may end up using eloquence for bad purposes, an important fear in antiquity. Serenus expressed the supposed preference of the old Roman aristocracy for simplicity. However, he says that when he sets himself up in the countryside according to the life of a virtuous old style landowner, his thoughts turn to greater luxury. Serenus says he resorts to political interests but just feels the same negative state of mind and returns to county matters. When he retreats into himself, Serenus says his thoughts become over excited and are expressed in exaggerated language in order to impress others. Serenus finishes by saying that his condition is not a danger to others, but only to himself. He says that he is afflict by sickness rather than a storm at sea. Seneca starts his reply by comparing Serenus’ condition with someone who has overcome a long and dangerous illness, but still has fever and pain. Even when the symptoms disappear, they feel anxious and are very ready to complain to a doctor if they feel hot. These are not people whose bodies failed to heal, they are people who are not used to health. Seneca returns to the model of the sea, suggesting that a calm sea after a storm still has ripples. Radical cures in which we threaten and block ourselves are not the answer. The solution is self-confidence, and belief that we are on the right path.
Recommended publications
  • Commentary on Englert Martha Nussbaum I Admire Englert's
    Commentary on Englert Martha Nussbaum I admire Englert's paper. I find its major conclusions entirely convincing: (1) the analysis of the difference between Epicurean and Stoic attitudes to suicide; (2) the account of the original Stoic position; (3) the argument that Seneca is an orthodox Stoic about suicide; and (4) the very interesting claims about the role of dif- ferent sorts of freedom in Seneca's arguments. Although I am persuaded by his analysis, I am inclined to be somewhat more critical of the Stoic position than he seems inclined to be: for I think that in a crucial way it is internally incoherent. In what follows, therefore, I want to focus on a problem in the Stoic account itself, with respect to the ambivalence the suicide theory reveals toward the importance of externals. I shall do this by focusing on one line of argument leading to suicide, in Seneca's De Ira.l 1. The Stoics famously hold that only virtue is worth choosing for its own sake. And virtue all by itself suffices for a complete- ly fulfilled and fulfilling human life, that is, for eudaimonia. Virtue is something unaffected by external contingency—both, apparently, as to its acquisition and as to its maintenance once acquired? Items that are not fully under the control of the 1. My interpretation of this work is developed at greater length in Nussbaum 1994. My general account of Stoic virtue theory and its relationship to the call for the extirpation of passion is in chapter 10, my detailed analysis of the argu- ments about anger in the De Ira in chapter 11.
    [Show full text]
  • The Hymn of Cleanthes Greek Text Translated Into English
    UC-NRLF 557 C29 ^ 033 TDt. 3 + 1921 3• MAIN ^ ft (9 -- " EXTS FOR STUDENTS, No. 26 THE YMN OF CLEANTHES GREEK TEXT TRANSLATED INTO ENGLISH WITH BRIEF INTRODUCTION AND NOTES BY E. H. BLAKENEY, M.A. ce 6d. net. HELPS FOR STUDENTS OF HISTORY. 1. EPISCOPAL REGISTERS OF ENGLAND AND WALES. By R. C. Fowler, B.A., F.S.A. 6d. net. 2. MUNICIPAL RECORDS. By F. J. C. Hearnsuaw, M.A. Gd. net. 3. MEDIEVAL RECKONINGS OF TIME. ' By Reginald L. Poole, LL.D., Litt.D. 6d. net. % 4. THE PUBLIC RECORD OFFICE. By Charles Johnson. 6d. net. 5. THE CARE OF DOCUMENTS. By Charles Johnson. 6d.net. 6. THE LOGIC OF HISTORY. By C. G. Cramp. 8d.net. 7. DOCUMENTS IN THE PUBUC RECORD OFFICE, DUBLIN. By B. H. Murray, Litt.D. 8d. net. 8. THE FRENCH WARS OF RELIGION. By Arthur A. TiUey» M.A. 6d. net. By Sir A. W. WARD, Litt.D., F.B.A. 9. THE PERIOD OF CONGRESSES, I. Introductory. 8d.net. 10. THE PERIOD OF CONGRESSES, II. Vienna and the Second Peace of Paris. Is. net. 11. THE PERIOD OF CONGRESSES, IH. Aix-la-ChapeUe to Verona. Is. net. (Nos. 9, 10, and 11 in one volume, cloth, 3s. Gd. net.) 12. SECURITIES OF PEACE. A Retrospect (1848-1914). Paper, 2s. ; cloth, 3s. net. 13. THE FRENCH RENAISSANCE. By Arthur A. TiUey, M.A* 8d. net. 14. HINTS ON THE STUDY OF ENGUSH ECONOMIC HISTORY. By W. Cunningham, D.D., F.B.A., F.S.A. 8d. net. 1 5. PARISH HISTORY AND RECORDS.
    [Show full text]
  • The Fragments of Zeno and Cleanthes, but Having an Important
    ,1(70 THE FRAGMENTS OF ZENO AND CLEANTHES. ftonton: C. J. CLAY AND SONS, CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS WAREHOUSE, AVE MARIA LANE. ambriDse: DEIGHTON, BELL, AND CO. ltip>ifl: F. A. BROCKHAUS. #tto Hork: MACMILLAX AND CO. THE FRAGMENTS OF ZENO AND CLEANTHES WITH INTRODUCTION AND EXPLANATORY NOTES. AX ESSAY WHICH OBTAINED THE HARE PRIZE IX THE YEAR 1889. BY A. C. PEARSON, M.A. LATE SCHOLAR OF CHRIST S COLLEGE, CAMBRIDGE. LONDON: C. J. CLAY AND SONS, CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS WAREHOUSE. 1891 [All Rights reserved.] Cambridge : PBIXTKIi BY C. J. CLAY, M.A. AND SONS, AT THK UNIVERSITY PRKSS. PREFACE. S dissertation is published in accordance with thr conditions attached to the Hare Prize, and appears nearly in its original form. For many reasons, however, I should have desired to subject the work to a more under the searching revision than has been practicable circumstances. Indeed, error is especially difficult t<> avoid in dealing with a large body of scattered authorities, a the majority of which can only be consulted in public- library. to be for The obligations, which require acknowledged of Zeno and the present collection of the fragments former are Cleanthes, are both special and general. The Philo- soon disposed of. In the Neue Jahrbticher fur Wellmann an lofjie for 1878, p. 435 foil., published article on Zeno of Citium, which was the first serious of Zeno from that attempt to discriminate the teaching of Wellmann were of the Stoa in general. The omissions of the supplied and the first complete collection fragments of Cleanthes was made by Wachsmuth in two Gottingen I programs published in 187-i LS75 (Commentationes s et II de Zenone Citiensi et Cleaitt/ie Assio).
    [Show full text]
  • Cleanthes Or Posidonius? the Basis of Stoic Physics
    CLEANTHES OR POSIDONIUS? THE BASIS OF STOIe PHYSICS BY FRIEDRICH SOLMSEN MEDEDELINGEN DER KONINKLIJKE NEDERLANDSE AKADEMIE VAN WETENSCHAPPEN, AFD. LETTERKUNDE NIEUWE REEKS. DEEL 24, No. 9 1961 N. V. NOORD-HOLLANDSCHE UITGEVERS MAATSCHAPPIJ AMSTERDAM AANGEBODEN IN DE VERGADERING VAN II SEPTEMBER 1961 The first thesis àf Stoic theology to be proved in Book 11 of Cicero's De natura deorum is esse deos 1). The proofs are of the most diverse kind. Some are dialectical in the sense of operating with lY~o~a, others are severely rational with an emphasis on syllogistic stringency, and still others may be classed as "physical" inasmuch as they are drawn from a consideration df the Cosmos and a theory regarding the basic substance or power at work in it. The chapters embodying these proofs have often been anal~ed and there has been a considerable amount of discussion about the source or sources from which Cicero derived these proofs 2). We wish here to concentrate on a relatively small section in this first part of Book 11 and to examine once more the question of its source. The arguments of this section (11, 23-32 mundum) are distinctly of the "physical" type 3); all of them lead us to recognize the significance of one particular vis, the vis caloris. From this concept we arrive in the end by a brief and simple step at the Stoic idea of the deity. In the first two paragraphs (23f.) the vis caloris is Been to be the agent of growth in all plants and animals 4); physiologioal observations here presented acquaint us with the manifestations and the effects of this power.
    [Show full text]
  • The Stoic Argument from Oikeiōsis
    Created on 2 December 2015 at 9.14 hours page 143 THESTOICARGUMENT FROM OIKEIŌSIS JACOBKLEIN . Introduction S Stoic accounts of oikeiōsis—appropriation, as I will translate it—are marked by two features: they begin with the ap- parently descriptive claim that the complex, seemingly purposeful behaviour all animals display in relation to their environment depends on a sophisticated capacity for self-perception. They con- clude, on the other hand, with the normative thesis that the human good consists in a life regulated by reason or, as the Stoics some- times describe it, in a life lived according to nature. This account is central to three of the fullest surviving presentations of Stoic ethics, and sources report that the Stoics appealed to it to defend their conception of the human good in general and their account of justice in particular. Since Pohlenz, most commentators have regarded the oikeiōsis doctrine as substantially Stoic in origin and important, one way or another, to Stoic ethical theory. But they © Jacob Klein I am especially grateful to Tad Brennan and Charles Brittain for extensive discus- sion, detailed criticism, and encouragement at crucial points. For insightful written comments I thank Victor Caston, Gail Fine, Brad Inwood, Terry Irwin, Nate Jezzi, Anthony Long, Martha Nussbaum, and an anonymous referee for this journal. I have benefited from (and greatly enjoyed) discussions with Margaret Graver, Lar- kin Philpot, Gretchen Reydams-Schils, Timothy Roche, and Maura Tumulty. Er- rors and shortcomings are my own. On the translation of oikeiōsis and its cognates see nn. and below. Diogenes Laertius (. – = LS A= SVF iii.
    [Show full text]
  • Katja Vogt Stoic Virtue&Happiness.Pages
    Katja Maria Vogt, katjavogt.com, Columbia University "1 The Virtues and Happiness in Stoic Ethics, for ed. Chris Bobonich, Cambridge Companion to Ancient Ethics The Virtues and Happiness in Stoic Ethics1 ! ! The Stoics hold that virtue is knowledge, and that knowledge is one: the good state of the rational soul. Unlike the rest of us, a person who is in this state of mind is happy. Today and throughout much of antiquity, Stoic ethics is compared to Platonic and Aristotelian views. The Stoics’ immediate interlocutors, however, are skeptics.2 With them the Stoics discuss how hard it is to think straight, to arrive at carefully considered views and stable insights. The skeptics regularly suspend judgment, assessing disputes as unresolved. The questions of what is good and bad and how to live appear to them difficult and deserving of extensive study.3 The Stoics largely agree with the skeptics: these questions appear to them to be in need of further investigation. The Stoic approach is to ask what a person would be like who has the answers: how she would think, feel, and act. ! A brief disclaimer. “The Stoics” as I speak of them never existed. Instead, there were individual philosophers. Stoic philosophy begins with Zeno (334/3-262/1 BCE), who spent more than twenty years in Plato’s Academy, developing his views in conversation with the then emerging Academic skepticism (Zeno was roughly 20-30 years older than 1 I am grateful to Jens Haas, Sam McVane, and Nandi Theunissen for comments. 2 On the closeness of skeptic and Stoic philosophy, cf.
    [Show full text]
  • Seneca-Letters.Pdf
    CLARENDON LATER ANCIENT PHILOSOPHERS Series editors: Jonathan Barnes, Universite´ de Paris IV—Sorbonne and A. A. Long, University of California, Berkeley SENECA SELECTED PHILOSOPHICAL LETTERS Seneca’s Letters to Lucilius are a rich source of information about ancient Stoicism, an influential work for early modern philosophers, and a fascinating philosophical document in their own right. This selection of the letters aims to include those which are of greatest philosophical interest, especially those which highlight the debates between Stoics and Platonists or Aristotelians in the first century AD, and the issue, still important today, of how technical philosophical enquiry is related to the various purposes for which philosophy is practised. In addition to examining the philosophical content of each letter, Brad Inwood’s commentary discusses the literary and historical background of the letters and to their relationship with other prose works by Seneca. Seneca is the earliest Stoic author for whom we have access to a large number of complete works, and these works were highly influential in later centuries. He was also a politically influential advisor to the Roman emperor Nero and a celebrated author of prose and verse. His philosophical acuity and independence of mind make his works exciting and challenging for the modern reader. Brad Inwood is Professor of Classics and Philosophy at the University of Toronto. PUBLISHEDINTHESERIES Alcinous: The Handbook of Platonism John Dillon Epictetus: Discourses, Book Robert Dobbin Galen: On the Therapeutic Method, Books I and II R. J. Hankinson Porphyry: Introduction Jonathan Barnes Seneca: Selected Philosophical Letters Brad Inwood Sextus Empiricus: Against the Ethicists Richard Bett Sextus Empiricus: Against the Grammarians David Blank SENECA SELECTED PHILOSOPHICAL LETTERS Translated with an Introduction and Commentary by BRAD INWOOD 1 1 Great Clarendon Street, Oxford Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford.
    [Show full text]
  • The Hymn of Cleanthes
    T E X T S F O R S T U D E N T S N o 2 6 . ' G E N E R AL E DI R CAROL I N E A S KE E L B . L 1 r TO S : . J. , H W HI TE D D . P W H TN Y D D D C . L . J. , . J. I E , . TH E HYM N O F CL E AN TH E S G RE E K TE X T TRANSLATE D INTO E NGLISH WITH BRIE F I NTR O D U CTI O N AN D N OTE S E H BL AKE N E Y M A . , . L ON DON S O C I E T Y F O R P R O M O T I N G C H R I S T I A N K N O W L E D G E N E W YOR K : THE M ACM I L L AN COM PAN Y The Hymn to Zeus is a spl endid attempt to b ring into harmony the author o f nature wi he tra itiona Zeus and ivin e rovi en th t d l , d p d ce his il T ere is n o attem t to re i with w l . h p disc d t or ho ox b ut rat er t o ur f it and use i s t d y, h p i y t e ements of trut for a er ur ose l h high p p .
    [Show full text]
  • Cleanthes' Hymn to Zeus
    Studien und Texte zu Antike und Christentum Studies and Texts in Antiquity and Christianity Herausgeber/Editor: CHRISTOPH MARKSCHIES (Berlin) Beirat/ Advisory Board HUBERT CANCIK (Berlin) • GIOVANNI CASADIO (Salerno) SUSANNA ELM (Berkeley) • JOHANNES HAHN (Münster) JÖRG RÜPKE (Erfurt) 33 Johan C. Thorn Cleanthes' Hymn to Zeus Text, Translation, and Commentary Mohr Siebeck JOHAN C.THOM, born 1954; studied Classics at the Universities of Stellenbosch (BA 1974) and Pretoria (MA 1980); New Testament and Early Christian Literature at the University of Chicago (PhD 1990); teaches Greek Language and Literature at the University of Stellenbosch, Professor of Classics since 1997; recipient of an Alexan- der von Humboldt Fellowship (Tübingen, 1995) and a Visiting Membership of the Institute for Advanced Study (Princeton, 2001-2002). ISBN 3-16-149174-2 ISBN-13 978-3-16-149174-0 ISSN 1436-3003 (Studien und Texte zu Antike und Christentum) Die Deutsche Nationalbibliothek lists this publication in the Deutsche Nationalbiblio- graphie; detailed bibliographic data is available on the Internet at http://iinb.d-nb.dc. Unrevised Paperback Edition 2006. © 2005 by Mohr Siebeck, Tübingen, Germany. This book may not be reproduced, in whole or in part, in any form (beyond that permitted by copyright law) without the publisher's written permission. This applies particularly to reproductions, translations, microfilms and storage and processing in electronic systems. The book was typeset by Martin Fischer in Tübingen using Bembo typeface, printed by Guide-Druck in Tübingen on non-aging paper and bound by Buchbinderei Held in Rottenburg. Printed in Germany. For Sjarlene Preface Although the Hymn to Zeus is often cited as one of the most important docu- ments of early Stoic philosophy — indeed the only text to survive more or less intact - it has not yet received a detailed treatment in a monograph by itself.
    [Show full text]
  • Virtue Ethics" and the Problem of Advising Fools1
    Work in progress, for presentation at Lewis & Clark College, Nov. 2010. Please do not quote without permission. COMMENTS WELCOME "VIRTUE ETHICS" AND THE PROBLEM OF ADVISING FOOLS1 ERIC BROWN Department of Philosophy Washington University in St. Louis [email protected] ABSTRACT: "Virtue ethics" tells us to do what the virtuous person would do in our circumstances. But if we are not virtuous—if we are "fools"—then the virtuous person would not be in our circumstances. What, then, can virtue theory say to advise a fool about what to do? I quickly suggest reasons to be pessimistic about recent approaches to this problem, and then I turn to the ancients' eudaimonism for a fresh alternative. The ancient Socratics, including especially the Stoics, counsel not causally promoting one's virtue or trying to follow "v-rules" but approximating virtue. I argue that Stoic psychopathology offers considerable help in making sense of how fools might approximate virtue and how advisers might use Socratic eudaimonism's conception of virtue to guide fools to the best action in their circumstances. 1. The Problem of Advising Fools Some people believe that ancient Greek and Roman philosophy provides a plausible alternative to modern moral philosophy. Instead of thinking that one should act in accordance with the right moral principles or that one should act so as to promote the best consequences, these reactionaries suggest that one should act as a virtuous person would act in one's circumstances (see, e.g., Hursthouse 1999). But there are problems with this formula, several of which are rooted in the difference between virtuous persons and the rest of us.
    [Show full text]
  • Zeno of Citium's Philosophy of Stoicism Miles Mcavoy
    Parkland College A with Honors Projects Honors Program 2016 Zeno of Citium's Philosophy of Stoicism Miles McAvoy Recommended Citation McAvoy, Miles, "Zeno of Citium's Philosophy of Stoicism" (2016). A with Honors Projects. 170. http://spark.parkland.edu/ah/170 Open access to this Essay is brought to you by Parkland College's institutional repository, SPARK: Scholarship at Parkland. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Myles McAvoy Ethics Honor Project Philosophy 105 Professor Greg Whitlock 23 February 2016 Zeno of Citium’s Philosophy of Stoicism Zeno of Citium, the founding philosopher of Ancient Greek Stoicism, has lost most of his story to time, leaving his teachings to live on in only a few fragments of what was rumored to be hundreds of treatises. Faithfully, the majority of Stoicism has survived the ages through the translations of fellow philosophers, Stoic and contemporary alike. Zeno the Stoic was born a Greek citizen of Citium, Cyprus in 335 B.C, son to Mnaseas, a successful merchant of the Mediterranean and Aegean Seas. Little is known of Zeno’s childhood, instead his history most commonly begins at the age of thirty, notably transcribed by Diogenes Laërtius within his compendium, Lives and Opinions of Eminent Philosophers. Zeno is reliably described within as a lean man with thick legs, regarded appropriately as being both flabby and delicate; he was a man of simple pleasures and commonly described as leading an ascetic lifestyle prior even to his philosophical teachings, “they say he was fond of eating green figs and of basking in the sun… [declining] most invitations to dinner” (Laërtius).
    [Show full text]
  • On Stoic Cosmopolitanism: a Response to Nussbaum's Patriotism And
    ON STOIC COSMOPOLITANISM: A RESPONSE TO NUSSBAUM’S PATRIOTISM AND COSMOPOLITANISM Leonidas Konstantakos Florida International University ABSTRACT: Martha Nussbaum gives a timely and interesting exhortation of Stoic ideals in Patriotism and Cosmopolitanism, but any implementation of these ancient ideals may have very serious consequences, as they certainly did in antiquity. Material consequences (loosely speaking) are not the purpose of a Stoic sage’s actions. Yet if prudence is to be the virtue for us that it was to our philosophical ancestors then, would-be Stoics are obligated to be very careful in making decisions for a cosmopolitan worldview, especially if we are to approach our future based on ideals over which even the ancients argued. KEYWORDS: Nussbaum. Cosmopolitanism. Stoicism. Stoic sage. PROMETEUS - Ano 8 - Número 17 – Janeiro-Junho/2015 - E-ISSN: 2176-5960 You desire to LIVE “according to Nature”? Oh, you noble Stoics, what fraud of words! -Nietzsche Martha Nussbaum gives a timely and interesting exhortation of Stoic ideals in Patriotism and Cosmopolitanism, but any implementation of these ancient ideals may have very serious consequences, as they certainly did in antiquity. Material consequences (loosely speaking) are not the purpose of a Stoic sage’s actions. Yet if prudence is to be the virtue for us that it was to our philosophical ancestors then, would-be Stoics are obligated to be very careful in making decisions for a cosmopolitan worldview, especially if we are to approach our future based on ideals over which even the ancients argued. Nussbaum writes: [The Stoics held that] we should not allow differences of nationality or class or ethnic membership or even gender to erect barriers between us and our fellow human beings.
    [Show full text]