1 Abstract. Rationality's Demands on Belief Alexander Liam Worsnip
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
Abstract. Rationality’s Demands on Belief Alexander Liam Worsnip 2015 It is common in the literature on practical rationality to distinguish between “structural” or “coherence” requirements of rationality on one hand, and substantive reasons on the other. When it comes to epistemology, however, this distinction is often overlooked, and its significance has not yet been fully appreciated. My dissertation is the first systematic attempt to remedy this. I show that coherence requirements have a distinctive and important role to play in epistemology, one that is not reducible to responding to evidence (reasons), and that must be theorized in its own right. Most radically, I argue that there is a core notion of rational belief, worth caring about and theorizing, that involves only conformity to coherence requirements, and on which – contrary to what most epistemologists either explicitly or implicitly assume – rationality does not require responding to one’s evidence. Though this can strike observers as a merely terminological stance, I show that this reaction is too quick, by arguing that there are cases of conflict between coherence requirements and responding to reasons – that is, where one cannot both satisfy the coherence requirements and respond to all of one’s reasons. As such, there is no single “umbrella” notion of rationality that covers both conformity to coherence requirements and responding to reasons. As well as trying to illuminate the nature and form of coherence requirements, I show that coherence requirements are of real epistemological significance, helping us to make progress in extant debates about higher-order evidence, doxastic voluntarism, deductive constraints, and (more briefly) conditionalization and peer disagreement. I argue that understanding the relevant norms in these areas as coherence requirements, rather than as claims about reasons, can help to resolve a number of problematic confusions and impasses in these debates. 1 Rationality’s Demands on Belief A Dissertation Presented to the Faculty of the Graduate School of Yale University in Candidacy for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy by Alexander Liam Worsnip Dissertation Directors: Keith DeRose and Tamar Gendler May 2015 2 © 2015 by Alexander Liam Worsnip All rights reserved. 3 Summary Table of Contents Detailed Table of Contents (including Tables & Figures) 5 Acknowledgments 7 Introduction 11 Chapter 1 Rational Belief without Evidence-Responsiveness 51 Chapter 2 Rationality as Coherence Defended 101 Chapter 3 Narrow-Scoping for Wide-Scopers 163 Chapter 4 Believing at Will as a Failure of Coherence 225 Chapter 5 Coherence and Deductive Constraints on Belief 266 Conclusion 304 References 317 4 Detailed Table of Contents Acknowledgments 7 Introduction 11 0.1 A chasm 11 0.2 Disambiguation? 14 0.3 Substantive reasons versus coherence requirements – a more 20 detailed first pass at the distinction 0.4 What the coherentist view is not 26 0.5 Domains of rationality and domains of philosophy 32 0.6 Evidence, reasons, and ‘ought’ 34 0.7 The epistemological context of this dissertation 38 0.8 The plan for the dissertation 44 1 Rational Belief without Evidence-Responsiveness 51 1.1 A puzzle 51 1.2 A bit more on evidential support 56 1.3 (ILC) explicated and defended 57 1.4 (PIF) defended 71 1.5 Does (ILC) still have force in cases of iterative failure? 88 1.6 What kind of conflict? 91 1.7 The disambiguating response revisited 96 2 Rationality as Coherence Defended 101 2.1 The interest and importance of coherence requirements 101 2.2 The normativity of coherence requirements 111 2.3 The centrality of coherence to the ordinary concept of rationality 117 2.4 Attempts to vindicate the asymmetry 127 2.5 An error-theory for the asymmetry 138 2.6 Modified reasons-responsiveness views? 143 3 Narrow-Scoping for Wide-Scopers 163 3.1 Introduction 163 3.2 Wide-scoping vs. narrow-scoping about the fundamental 168 requirements of rationality 3.3 Wide-scope semantics 175 3.4 An alternative: contextualism 179 3.5 Contextualism vs. wide-scope semantics 185 3.6 Extending contextualism to (talk about) rationality 195 3.7 Further puzzles resolved 205 5 3.8 Detachment rules 217 4 Believing at Will as a Failure of Coherence 225 4.1 Introduction 225 4.2 What is it that’s difficult? 228 4.3 Is believing at will impossible? Some possible counterexamples 233 4.4 An explanation in terms of substantive norms? 237 4.5 An explanation in terms of coherence requirements? 243 4.6 Explaining the cases 252 4.7 The difficulty of transparent incoherence 259 5 Coherence and Deductive Constraints on Belief 266 5.1 Introduction 266 5.2 Deductive closure and the preface paradox challenge 267 5.3 Ways of formulating the challenge to closure 270 5.4 A new way of formulating the challenge 274 5.5 Defending weak fallibilism 278 5.6 Defending belief-credence coherence 288 5.7 Living without closure in the theory of belief 293 5.8 Consistency without closure? 298 5.9 Other deductive constraints 301 Conclusion 304 References 317 Tables & Figures Table 1: our puzzle 52 Figure 1: safety and KK failure 78 6 Acknowledgments This dissertation was written with the help of many people. First and foremost, I must thank my dissertation committee: my co-advisors, Keith DeRose and Tamar Gendler, and my other committee members, Steve Darwall, Bruno Whittle, and (as an external committee member) Ralph Wedgwood. I was lucky to, perhaps unusually, have a committee where every single member, in different ways, was generous with their time, and ultimately made a big contribution to the project and to my intellectual development more broadly. The final dissertation reflects the philosophical diversity of this group, which collectively spans a wide range of philosophical subfields and methodological approaches, and is, I think, all the better for that. Moreover, every member of the committee supported me in other important ways, offering crucial advice, encouragement and big-picture guidance as I shaped the project and, more recently, braved the academic job market. I also learnt a huge amount about teaching both from Keith (as his TA for Epistemology in Spring 2012) and from Steve (as his co-instructor for Rationality in Fall 2013). Both teaching experiences were accompanied by highly stimulating weekly discussions of the material we were covering, and much else besides. And both experiences had a profound effect on this dissertation, helping me to focus the project and to master crucial literature in a deep way by learning how to communicate it to undergraduates. One of the best things about pursuing my PhD at Yale was the opportunity to get wonderful feedback on my work from many other faculty members who were not formally on my committee. I must single out Dan Greco, Josh Knobe, and Zoltán Szabó in particular for going well beyond the call of duty in providing invaluable help with my work during the time I was at Yale. I also learnt a great deal from classes, discussions and exchanges with a number of other current or former Yale faculty members, including Facundo Alonso, George 7 Bealer, Michael Della Rocca, Paul Franks, Verity Harte, Shelly Kagan, Raul Saucedo, Sun-Joo Shin, Sam Shpall, Matt Smith, and Ken Winkler. Just as important was the opportunity to share and discuss ideas with my fellow Yale graduate students, past and present. For friendship, support and philosophical discussion, I’m especially grateful to Julia Borcherding, Julianne Chung, Eric Guindon, Jessica Keiser, Justin Khoo, Mark Maxwell, Jessie Munton, Aaron Norby, Jonathan Phillips, John Pittard, Daniel Putnam, Alex Silverman, Kelley Schiffman, Evan Rodriguez, Jonathan Vertanen, and Yuan Yuan. I must single out Julianne and John for their influence on this dissertation specifically. As fellow epistemologists and wonderful friends, they both helped to shape my thinking and philosophical development profoundly. Before coming to Yale I was both an undergraduate and a BPhil student at Oxford. I was lucky enough to have some wonderful philosophy teachers there, many of whose influence will be evident: in particular, Louise Braddock, John Broome, Roger Crisp, Terry Irwin, Ralph Walker, Ralph Wedgwood, and Dawn Wilson. Ralph Wedgwood deserves special thanks. As mentioned above, he ultimately served as an external member of my dissertation committee. He has been involved with my work and career for a greater sustained period of time than anyone else, having taught me in my very first term as a BPhil student, as I tried – often ineffectively – to get a feel for contemporary epistemology for the first time. I hope his patience with me then paid off, and feel privileged to now count him as a colleague and friend. Several other people read and provided very helpful feedback on versions of one or more chapters of the dissertation. For this, profound thanks to Daniel Fogal, Maria Lasonen- Aarnio, Ram Neta, and Daniel Whiting. An article that overlaps parts of chapter 2, especially sections 2.3-2.5, is forthcoming in Philosophical Quarterly, and a shortened version of chapter 3 8 is forthcoming in Synthese. Thanks to the anonymous referees for both articles for helpful written comments. Some of this material was presented at conferences or colloquia, where I received valuable comments and criticisms. An earlier version of chapter 1 was presented at the London School of Economics and at the St Louis Annual Conference on Reasons and Rationality. Chapter 4 was recently presented at the University of California, San Diego, the University of Pittsburgh, and the University of North Carolina, Chapel Hill. An earlier version of parts of chapter 5 were presented at a meeting of the Joint Session of the Aristotelian Society and the Mind Association at the University of Cambridge. I’m grateful to the audiences at all of these places, especially to my future colleagues at UNC.