Introduction to Probability Ariel Yadin Lecture 7 1

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Introduction to Probability Ariel Yadin Lecture 7 1 Introduction to Probability Ariel Yadin Lecture 7 1. Independence Revisited *** Dec. 6 *** 1.1. Some reminders. Let (Ω; F; P) be a probability space. Given a collection of subsets K ⊂ F, recall that the σ-algebra generated by K, is \ σ(K) = fG : G is a σ-algebra ; K ⊂ Gg ; and this σ-algebra is the smallest σ-algebra containing K. σ(K) can be thought of as all possible information that can be generated by the sets in K. Recall that a collection of events (An)n are mutually independent if for any finite number of these events A1;:::;An we have that P(A1 \···\ An) = P(A1) ··· P(An): We can also define the independence of families of events: Definition 7.1. Let (Ω; F; P) be a probability space. Let (Kn)n be a collection of families of events in F. Then, (Kn)n are mutually independent if for any finite number of families from this collection, K1;:::; Kn and any events A1 2 K1;A2 2 K2;:::;An 2 Kn, we have that P(A1 \···\ An) = P(A1) ··· P(An): For example, we would like to think that (An) are mutually independent, if all the information from each event in the sequence is independent from the information from the other events in the sequence. This is the content of the next proposition. Proposition 7.2. Let (An) be a sequence of events on a probability space (Ω; F; P). Then, (An) are mutually independent if and only if the σ-algebras (σ(An))n are mutually independent. It is not difficult to prove this by induction: Proof. By induction on n we show that (σ(A1); : : : ; σ(An); fAn+1g ;:::) are mutually indepen- dent. The base n = 0 is just the assumption. 1 2 So assume that (σ(A1); : : : ; σ(An−1); fAng ; fAn+1g ;:::) are mutually independent. Let n1 < n2 < : : : < nk < nk+1 < : : : < nm be a finite number of indices such that nk < n < nk+1. Let Bj 2 σ(Anj ) for j = 1; : : : ; k, and Bj = Anj for j = k + 1; : : : ; m. Let B 2 σ(An). If B = ; then P(B1 \···\ Bn \ B) = 0 = P(B1) ··· P(Bn) · P(B). If B = Ω then P(B1 \···\ Bn \ B) = P(B1 \···\ Bn) = P(B1) ··· P(Bn), by the induction hypotheses. If B = An then this also holds c by the induction hypotheses. So we only have to deal with the case B = An. In this case, for X = B1 \···\ Bn, P(X \ B) = P(X n (X \ An)) = P(X) − P(X \ An) = P(X)(1 − P(An)) = P(X) P(B); where we have used the induction hypotheses to say that X and An are independent. Since this holds for any choice a a finite number of events, we have the induction step. ut However, we will take a more windy road to get stronger results... (Corollary 7.8) 2. π-systems and Independence Definition 7.3. Let K be a family of subsets of Ω. • We say that K is a π-system if ; 2 K and K is closed under intersections; that is, for all A; B 2 K, A \ B 2 K. • We say that K is a Dynkin system (or λ-system) if K is closed under set complements and countable disjoint unions; that is, for any A 2 K and any sequence (An) in K of c S pairwise disjoint subsets, we have that A 2 K and n An 2 K. The main goal now is to show that probability measures are uniquely defined once they are defined on a π-system. This is the content of Theorem 7.7. Proposition 7.4. If F is Dynkin system on Ω and F is also a π-system on Ω, then F is a σ−algebra. Proof. Since F is a Dynkin system, it is closed under complements, and Ω = ;c 2 F. Let (An) be a sequence of subsets in F. Set B1 = A1, C1 = ;, and for n > 1, n−1 [ Cn = Aj and Bn = An n Cn: j=1 3 Tn−1 c c Since F is a π-system and closed under complements, Cn = ( j=1 Aj) 2 F, and so Bn = c An \ Cn 2 F. Since (Bn) is a sequence of pairwise disjoint sets, and since F is a Dynkin system, [ [ An = Bn 2 F: n n ut Proposition 7.5. If (Dα)α is a collection of Dynkin systems (not necessarily countable). Then T *** leave as ex- D = α Dα is a Dynkin system. ercise *** Proof. Since ; 2 Dα for all α, we have that ; 2 D. c c If A 2 D, then A 2 Dα for all α. So A 2 Dα for all α, and thus A 2 D. If (An)n is a countable sequence of pairwise disjoint sets in D, then An 2 Dα for all α and all S S n. Thus, for any α, n An 2 Dα. So n An 2 D. ut Lemma 7.6 (Dynkin's Lemma). If a Dynkin system D contains a π-system K, then σ(K) ⊂ D. Proof. Let \ F = fD0 : D0 is a Dynkin system containing Kg : So F is a Dynkin system and K ⊂ F ⊂ D. We will show that F is a σ−algebra, so σ(K) ⊂ F ⊂ D. Suppose we know that F is closed under intersections (which is Claim 3 below). Since ; 2 K ⊂ F, we will then have that F is a π-system. Being both a Dynkin system and a π−system, F is a σ−algebra. Thus, to show that F is a σ−algebra, it suffices to show that F is closed under intersections. Note that F is closed under complements (because all Dynkin systems are). Claim 1. If A ⊂ B are subsets in F, then B n A 2 F. Proof. If A; B 2 F, then since F is a Dynkin system, also Bc 2 F. Since A ⊂ B, we have that A; Bc are disjoint, so A [ Bc 2 F and so B n A = (Ac \ B) = (A [ Bc)c 2 F. ut Claim 2. For any K 2 K, if A 2 F then A \ K 2 F. Proof. Let E = fA : A \ K 2 Fg. Let A 2 E and (An) be a sequence of pairwise disjoint subsets in E. Since K 2 F and A \ K 2 F, by Claim 1 we have that Ac \ K = K n (A \ K) 2 F. So Ac 2 E. 4 Since (An \ K)n is a sequence of pairwise disjoint subsets in F, we get that [ \ [ An K = (An \ K) 2 F: n n So we conclude that E is a Dynkin system. Since K is closed under intersections, E contains K. Thus, by definition F ⊂ E. So for any A 2 F we have that A 2 E, and A \ K 2 F. ut Claim 3. For any B 2 F, if A 2 F then A \ B 2 F. Proof. Let E = fA : A \ B 2 Fg. Let A 2 E and (An) be a sequence of pairwise disjoint subsets in E. Since B 2 F and A \ B 2 F, by Claim 1 we have that Ac \ B = B n (A \ B) 2 F. So Ac 2 E. Since (An \ B)n is a sequence of pairwise disjoint subsets in F, we get that [ \ [ An B = (An \ B) 2 F: n n So we conclude that E is a Dynkin system. By Claim 2, K is contained in E. So by definition, F ⊂ E. ut Since F is closed under intersections, this completes the proof. ut The next theorem tells us that a probability measure on (Ω; F) is determined by it's values on a π-system generating F. Theorem 7.7 (Uniqueness of Extension). Let K be a π−system on Ω, and let F = σ(K) be the σ−algebra generated by K. Let P; Q be two probability measures on (Ω; F), such that for all A 2 K, P (A) = Q(A). Then, P (B) = Q(B) for any B 2 F. Proof. Let D = fA 2 F : P (A) = Q(A)g. So K ⊂ D. We will show that D is a Dynkin system, and since it contains K, the by Dynkin's Lemma it must contain F = σ(K). Of course P (Ω) = 1 = Q(Ω), so Ω 2 D. If A 2 D, then P (Ac) = 1 − P (A) = 1 − Q(A) = Q(Ac), so Ac 2 D. Let (An) be a sequence of pairwise disjoint sets in D. Then, [ X X [ P ( An) = P (An) = Q(An) = Q( An): n n n n S So n An 2 D. ut 5 Corollary 7.8. Let (Ω; F; P) be a probability space. Let (Πn)n be a sequence of π-systems, and let Fn = σ(Πn). Then, (Πn)n are mutually independent if and only if (Fn)n are mutually independent. Proof. We will prove by induction on n that for any n ≥ 0, the collection (F1; F2;:::; Fn; Πn+1; Πn+2;:::; ) are mutually independent. For n = 0 this is the assumption. For n > 1, let n1 < n2 < : : : < nk < nk+1 < : : : < nm be a finite number of indices such that nk < n < nk+1. Let Aj 2 Fnj ; j = 1; : : : ; k and Aj 2 Πnj ; j = k + 1; : : : ; m. For any A 2 Fn, if P(A1 \···\ Am) = 0 then A is independent of A1 \···\ Am. So assume that P(A1 \···\ Am) > 0.
Recommended publications
  • Set Theory, Including the Axiom of Choice) Plus the Negation of CH
    ANNALS OF ~,IATltEMATICAL LOGIC - Volume 2, No. 2 (1970) pp. 143--178 INTERNAL COHEN EXTENSIONS D.A.MARTIN and R.M.SOLOVAY ;Tte RockeJ~'ller University and University (.~t CatiJbrnia. Berkeley Received 2 l)ecemt)er 1969 Introduction Cohen [ !, 2] has shown that tile continuum hypothesis (CH) cannot be proved in Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory. Levy and Solovay [9] have subsequently shown that CH cannot be proved even if one assumes the existence of a measurable cardinal. Their argument in tact shows that no large cardinal axiom of the kind present;y being considered by set theorists can yield a proof of CH (or of its negation, of course). Indeed, many set theorists - including the authors - suspect that C1t is false. But if we reject CH we admit Gurselves to be in a state of ignorance about a great many questions which CH resolves. While CH is a power- full assertion, its negation is in many ways quite weak. Sierpinski [ 1 5 ] deduces propcsitions there called C l - C82 from CH. We know of none of these propositions which is decided by the negation of CH and only one of them (C78) which is decided if one assumes in addition that a measurable cardinal exists. Among the many simple questions easily decided by CH and which cannot be decided in ZF (Zerme!o-Fraenkel set theory, including the axiom of choice) plus the negation of CH are tile following: Is every set of real numbers of cardinality less than tha't of the continuum of Lebesgue measure zero'? Is 2 ~0 < 2 ~ 1 ? Is there a non-trivial measure defined on all sets of real numbers? CIhis third question could be decided in ZF + not CH only in the unlikely event t Tile second author received support from a Sloan Foundation fellowship and tile National Science Foundation Grant (GP-8746).
    [Show full text]
  • Lecture Notes
    MEASURE THEORY AND STOCHASTIC PROCESSES Lecture Notes José Melo, Susana Cruz Faculdade de Engenharia da Universidade do Porto Programa Doutoral em Engenharia Electrotécnica e de Computadores March 2011 Contents 1 Probability Space3 1 Sample space Ω .....................................4 2 σ-eld F .........................................4 3 Probability Measure P .................................6 3.1 Measure µ ....................................6 3.2 Probability Measure P .............................7 4 Learning Objectives..................................7 5 Appendix........................................8 2 Chapter 1 Probability Space Let's consider the experience of throwing a dart on a circular target with radius r (assuming the dart always hits the target), divided in 4 dierent areas as illustrated in Figure 1.1. 4 3 2 1 Figure 1.1: Circular Target The circles that bound the regions 1, 2, 3, and 4, have radius of, respectively, r , r , 3r , and . 4 2 4 r Therefore, the probability that a dart lands in each region is: 1 , 3 , 5 , P (1) = 16 P (2) = 16 P (3) = 16 7 . P (4) = 16 For this kind of problems, the theory of discrete probability spaces suces. However, when it comes to problems involving either an innitely repeated operation or an innitely ne op- eration, this mathematical framework does not apply. This motivates the introduction of a measure-theoretic probability approach to correctly describe those cases. We dene the proba- bility space (Ω; F;P ), where Ω is the sample space, F is the event space, and P is the probability 3 measure. Each of them will be described in the following subsections. 1 Sample space Ω The sample space Ω is the set of all the possible results or outcomes ! of an experiment or observation.
    [Show full text]
  • Borel Structure in Groups and Their Dualso
    BOREL STRUCTURE IN GROUPS AND THEIR DUALSO GEORGE W. MACKEY Introduction. In the past decade or so much work has been done toward extending the classical theory of finite dimensional representations of com- pact groups to a theory of (not necessarily finite dimensional) unitary repre- sentations of locally compact groups. Among the obstacles interfering with various aspects of this program is the lack of a suitable natural topology in the "dual object"; that is in the set of equivalence classes of irreducible representations. One can introduce natural topologies but none of them seem to have reasonable properties except in extremely special cases. When the group is abelian for example the dual object itself is a locally compact abelian group. This paper is based on the observation that for certain purposes one can dispense with a topology in the dual object in favor of a "weaker struc- ture" and that there is a wide class of groups for which this weaker structure has very regular properties. If .S is any topological space one defines a Borel (or Baire) subset of 5 to be a member of the smallest family of subsets of 5 which includes the open sets and is closed with respect to the formation of complements and countable unions. The structure defined in 5 by its Borel sets we may call the Borel structure of 5. It is weaker than the topological structure in the sense that any one-to-one transformation of S onto 5 which preserves the topological structure also preserves the Borel structure whereas the converse is usually false.
    [Show full text]
  • Dynkin (Λ-) and Π-Systems; Monotone Classes of Sets, and of Functions – with Some Examples of Application (Mainly of a Probabilistic flavor)
    Dynkin (λ-) and π-systems; monotone classes of sets, and of functions { with some examples of application (mainly of a probabilistic flavor) Matija Vidmar February 7, 2018 1 Dynkin and π-systems Some basic notation: Throughout, for measurable spaces (A; A) and (B; B), (i) A=B will denote the class of A=B-measurable maps, and (ii) when A = B, A_B := σA(A[B) will be the smallest σ-field on A containing both A and B (this notation has obvious extensions to arbitrary families of σ-fields on a given space). Furthermore, for a measure µ on F, µf := µ(f) := R fdµ will signify + − the integral of an f 2 F=B[−∞;1] against µ (assuming µf ^ µf < 1). Finally, for a probability space (Ω; F; P) and a sub-σ-field G of F, PGf := PG(f) := EP[fjG] will denote the conditional + − expectation of an f 2 F=B[−∞;1] under P w.r.t. G (assuming Pf ^ Pf < 1; in particular, for F 2 F, PG(F ) := P(F jG) = EP[1F jG] will be the conditional probability of F under P given G). We consider first Dynkin and π-systems. Definition 1. Let Ω be a set, D ⊂ 2Ω a collection of its subsets. Then D is called a Dynkin system, or a λ-system, on Ω, if (i) Ω 2 D, (ii) fA; Bg ⊂ D and A ⊂ B, implies BnA 2 D, and (iii) whenever (Ai)i2N is a sequence in D, and Ai ⊂ Ai+1 for all i 2 N, then [i2NAi 2 D.
    [Show full text]
  • Problem Set 1 This Problem Set Is Due on Friday, September 25
    MA 2210 Fall 2015 - Problem set 1 This problem set is due on Friday, September 25. All parts (#) count 10 points. Solve the problems in order and please turn in for full marks (140 points) • Problems 1, 2, 6, 8, 9 in full • Problem 3, either #1 or #2 (not both) • Either Problem 4 or Problem 5 (not both) • Problem 7, either #1 or #2 (not both) 1. Let D be the dyadic grid on R and m denote the Lebesgue outer measure on R, namely for A ⊂ R ( ¥ ¥ ) [ m(A) = inf ∑ `(Ij) : A ⊂ Ij; Ij 2 D 8 j : j=1 j=1 −n #1 Let n 2 Z. Prove that m does not change if we restrict to intervals with `(Ij) ≤ 2 , namely ( ¥ ¥ ) (n) (n) [ −n m(A) = m (A); m (A) := inf ∑ `(Ij) : A ⊂ Ij; Ij 2 D 8 j;`(Ij) ≤ 2 : j=1 j=1 N −n #2 Let t 2 R be of the form t = ∑n=−N kn2 for suitable integers N;k−N;:::;kN. Prove that m is invariant under translations by t, namely m(A) = m(A +t) 8A ⊂ R: −n −m Hints. For #2, reduce to the case t = 2 for some n. Then use #1 and that Dm = fI 2 D : `(I) = 2 g is invariant under translation by 2−n whenever m ≥ n. d d 2. Let O be the collection of all open cubes I ⊂ R and define the outer measure on R given by ( ¥ ¥ ) [ n(A) = inf ∑ jRnj : A ⊂ R j; R j 2 O 8 j n=0 n=0 where jRj is the Euclidean volume of the cube R.
    [Show full text]
  • STAT 571 Assignment 1 Solutions 1. If Ω Is a Set and C a Collection Of
    STAT 571 Assignment 1 solutions 1. If Ω is a set and a collection of subsets of Ω, let be the intersection of all σ-algebras that contain . ProveC that is the σ-algebra generatedA by . C A C Solution: Let α α A be the collection of all σ-algebras that contain , and fA j 2 g C set = α. We first show that is a σ-algebra. There are three things to A \ A A α A prove. 2 (a) For every α A, α is a σ-algebra, so Ω α, and hence Ω α A α = . 2 A 2 A 2 \ 2 A A (b) If B , then B α for every α A. Since α is a σ-algebra, we have c 2 A 2 A 2 A c B α. But this is true for every α A, so we have B . 2 A 2 2 A (c) If B1;B2;::: are sets in , then B1;B2;::: belong to α for each α A. A A 2 Since α is a σ-algebra, we have 1 Bn α. But this is true for every A [n=1 2 A α A, so we have 1 Bn . 2 [n=1 2 A Thus is a σ-algebra that contains , and it must be the smallest one since α for everyA α A. C A ⊆ A 2 2. Prove that the set of rational numbers Q is a Borel set in R. Solution: For every x R, the set x is the complement of an open set, and hence Borel.
    [Show full text]
  • (Measure Theory for Dummies) UWEE Technical Report Number UWEETR-2006-0008
    A Measure Theory Tutorial (Measure Theory for Dummies) Maya R. Gupta {gupta}@ee.washington.edu Dept of EE, University of Washington Seattle WA, 98195-2500 UWEE Technical Report Number UWEETR-2006-0008 May 2006 Department of Electrical Engineering University of Washington Box 352500 Seattle, Washington 98195-2500 PHN: (206) 543-2150 FAX: (206) 543-3842 URL: http://www.ee.washington.edu A Measure Theory Tutorial (Measure Theory for Dummies) Maya R. Gupta {gupta}@ee.washington.edu Dept of EE, University of Washington Seattle WA, 98195-2500 University of Washington, Dept. of EE, UWEETR-2006-0008 May 2006 Abstract This tutorial is an informal introduction to measure theory for people who are interested in reading papers that use measure theory. The tutorial assumes one has had at least a year of college-level calculus, some graduate level exposure to random processes, and familiarity with terms like “closed” and “open.” The focus is on the terms and ideas relevant to applied probability and information theory. There are no proofs and no exercises. Measure theory is a bit like grammar, many people communicate clearly without worrying about all the details, but the details do exist and for good reasons. There are a number of great texts that do measure theory justice. This is not one of them. Rather this is a hack way to get the basic ideas down so you can read through research papers and follow what’s going on. Hopefully, you’ll get curious and excited enough about the details to check out some of the references for a deeper understanding.
    [Show full text]
  • Dynkin Systems and Regularity of Finite Borel Measures Homework 10
    Math 105, Spring 2012 Professor Mariusz Wodzicki Dynkin systems and regularity of finite Borel measures Homework 10 due April 13, 2012 1. Let p 2 X be a point of a topological space. Show that the set fpg ⊆ X is closed if and only if for any point q 6= p, there exists a neighborhood N 3 q such that p 2/ N . Derive from this that X is a T1 -space if and only if every singleton subset is closed. Let C , D ⊆ P(X) be arbitrary families of subsets of a set X. We define the family D:C as D:C ˜ fE ⊆ X j C \ E 2 D for every C 2 C g. 2. The Exchange Property Show that, for any families B, C , D ⊆ P(X), one has B ⊆ D:C if and only if C ⊆ D:B. Dynkin systems1 We say that a family of subsets D ⊆ P(X) of a set X is a Dynkin system (or a Dynkin class), if it satisfies the following three conditions: c (D1) if D 2 D , then D 2 D ; S (D2) if fDigi2I is a countable family of disjoint members of D , then i2I Di 2 D ; (D3) X 2 D . 3. Show that any Dynkin system satisfies also: 0 0 0 (D4) if D, D 2 D and D ⊆ D, then D n D 2 D . T 4. Show that the intersection, i2I Di , of any family of Dynkin systems fDigi2I on a set X is a Dynkin system on X. It follows that, for any family F ⊆ P(X), there exists a smallest Dynkin system containing F , namely the intersection of all Dynkin systems containing F .
    [Show full text]
  • THE DYNKIN SYSTEM GENERATED by BALLS in Rd CONTAINS ALL BOREL SETS Let X Be a Nonempty Set and S ⊂ 2 X. Following [B, P. 8] We
    PROCEEDINGS OF THE AMERICAN MATHEMATICAL SOCIETY Volume 128, Number 2, Pages 433{437 S 0002-9939(99)05507-0 Article electronically published on September 23, 1999 THE DYNKIN SYSTEM GENERATED BY BALLS IN Rd CONTAINS ALL BOREL SETS MIROSLAV ZELENY´ (Communicated by Frederick W. Gehring) Abstract. We show that for every d N each Borel subset of the space Rd with the Euclidean metric can be generated2 from closed balls by complements and countable disjoint unions. Let X be a nonempty set and 2X. Following [B, p. 8] we say that is a Dynkin system if S⊂ S (D1) X ; (D2) A ∈S X A ; ∈S⇒ \ ∈S (D3) if A are pairwise disjoint, then ∞ A . n ∈S n=1 n ∈S Some authors use the name -class instead of Dynkin system. The smallest Dynkin σ S system containing a system 2Xis denoted by ( ). Let P be a metric space. The system of all closed ballsT⊂ in P (of all Borel subsetsD T of P , respectively) will be denoted by Balls(P ) (Borel(P ), respectively). We will deal with the problem of whether (?) (Balls(P )) = Borel(P ): D One motivation for such a problem comes from measure theory. Let µ and ν be finite Radon measures on a metric space P having the same values on each ball. Is it true that µ = ν?If (Balls(P )) = Borel(P ), then obviously µ = ν.IfPis a Banach space, then µ =Dν again (Preiss, Tiˇser [PT]). But Preiss and Keleti ([PK]) showed recently that (?) is false in infinite-dimensional Hilbert spaces. We prove the following result.
    [Show full text]
  • Probability Measures on Metric Spaces
    Probability measures on metric spaces Onno van Gaans These are some loose notes supporting the first sessions of the seminar Stochastic Evolution Equations organized by Dr. Jan van Neerven at the Delft University of Technology during Winter 2002/2003. They contain less information than the common textbooks on the topic of the title. Their purpose is to present a brief selection of the theory that provides a basis for later study of stochastic evolution equations in Banach spaces. The notes aim at an audience that feels more at ease in analysis than in probability theory. The main focus is on Prokhorov's theorem, which serves both as an important tool for future use and as an illustration of techniques that play a role in the theory. The field of measures on topological spaces has the luxury of several excellent textbooks. The main source that has been used to prepare these notes is the book by Parthasarathy [6]. A clear exposition is also available in one of Bour- baki's volumes [2] and in [9, Section 3.2]. The theory on the Prokhorov metric is taken from Billingsley [1]. The additional references for standard facts on general measure theory and general topology have been Halmos [4] and Kelley [5]. Contents 1 Borel sets 2 2 Borel probability measures 3 3 Weak convergence of measures 6 4 The Prokhorov metric 9 5 Prokhorov's theorem 13 6 Riesz representation theorem 18 7 Riesz representation for non-compact spaces 21 8 Integrable functions on metric spaces 24 9 More properties of the space of probability measures 26 1 The distribution of a random variable in a Banach space X will be a probability measure on X.
    [Show full text]
  • Descriptive Set Theory
    Descriptive Set Theory David Marker Fall 2002 Contents I Classical Descriptive Set Theory 2 1 Polish Spaces 2 2 Borel Sets 14 3 E®ective Descriptive Set Theory: The Arithmetic Hierarchy 27 4 Analytic Sets 34 5 Coanalytic Sets 43 6 Determinacy 54 7 Hyperarithmetic Sets 62 II Borel Equivalence Relations 73 1 8 ¦1-Equivalence Relations 73 9 Tame Borel Equivalence Relations 82 10 Countable Borel Equivalence Relations 87 11 Hyper¯nite Equivalence Relations 92 1 These are informal notes for a course in Descriptive Set Theory given at the University of Illinois at Chicago in Fall 2002. While I hope to give a fairly broad survey of the subject we will be concentrating on problems about group actions, particularly those motivated by Vaught's conjecture. Kechris' Classical Descriptive Set Theory is the main reference for these notes. Notation: If A is a set, A<! is the set of all ¯nite sequences from A. Suppose <! σ = (a0; : : : ; am) 2 A and b 2 A. Then σ b is the sequence (a0; : : : ; am; b). We let ; denote the empty sequence. If σ 2 A<!, then jσj is the length of σ. If f : N ! A, then fjn is the sequence (f(0); : : :b; f(n ¡ 1)). If X is any set, P(X), the power set of X is the set of all subsets X. If X is a metric space, x 2 X and ² > 0, then B²(x) = fy 2 X : d(x; y) < ²g is the open ball of radius ² around x. Part I Classical Descriptive Set Theory 1 Polish Spaces De¯nition 1.1 Let X be a topological space.
    [Show full text]
  • Measure and Integration
    ¦ Measure and Integration Man is the measure of all things. — Pythagoras Lebesgue is the measure of almost all things. — Anonymous ¦.G Motivation We shall give a few reasons why it is worth bothering with measure the- ory and the Lebesgue integral. To this end, we stress the importance of measure theory in three different areas. ¦.G.G We want a powerful integral At the end of the previous chapter we encountered a neat application of Banach’s fixed point theorem to solve ordinary differential equations. An essential ingredient in the argument was the observation in Lemma 2.77 that the operation of differentiation could be replaced by integration. Note that differentiation is an operation that destroys regularity, while in- tegration yields further regularity. It is a consequence of the fundamental theorem of calculus that the indefinite integral of a continuous function is a continuously differentiable function. So far we used the elementary notion of the Riemann integral. Let us quickly recall the definition of the Riemann integral on a bounded interval. Definition 3.1. Let [a, b] with −¥ < a < b < ¥ be a compact in- terval. A partition of [a, b] is a finite sequence p := (t0,..., tN) such that a = t0 < t1 < ··· < tN = b. The mesh size of p is jpj := max1≤k≤Njtk − tk−1j. Given a partition p of [a, b], an associated vector of sample points (frequently also called tags) is a vector x = (x1,..., xN) such that xk 2 [tk−1, tk]. Given a function f : [a, b] ! R and a tagged 51 3 Measure and Integration partition (p, x) of [a, b], the Riemann sum S( f , p, x) is defined by N S( f , p, x) := ∑ f (xk)(tk − tk−1).
    [Show full text]