A What Is Existence?

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

A What Is Existence? A What is Existence? 1 Holes David Lewis and Stephanie Lewis 2 On What There Is W. V. O. Quine 3 Beyond Being and Nonbeing R. M. Chisholm Introduction Ontology is the part of metaphysics concerned with the question, “What is there?,” when that question is taken in the broadest or most unrestricted sense possible. As Peter van Inwagen points out in the introduction to this book (“What is metaphysics?”), sometimes the question “Is there any such-and-such?” means merely, “Restricting our attention for the moment to just things that are so-and-sos, is there a such-and-such among them?” When we ask, for example, “Is there any beer?,” we usually mean merely “Restricting our attention to just beverages in the fridge (or in the restaurant, or available for purchase in the county, etc.), is there any beer?” If the last beer has been taken from the fridge at a party, and someone asks, “Is there any beer?,” it is a poor joke to say “Yes” and then explain that there is plenty in the grocery store (which is closed, by the way). The metaphysician interested in ontology wants to know what the world is like in its entirety, ignoring nothing. She wants a complete catalogue of “the furniture of the world,” but at a very high level of abstraction. Ontology is one of the oldest parts of philosophy; it has a central place in Plato’s philosophy, for instance; and Platonistic ontological views are defended by philosophers even today. Quine, however, says that “Plato’s beard” (his cata- logue of “what there is”) needs shaving – meaning that Plato’s ontology is too rich; it is full of entities that Quine fi nds it hard to accept as real. For instance, Plato says there are universals – features, properties, or attributes that can be D2 ccmp01.inddmp01.indd 1199 77/6/2007/6/2007 33:40:47:40:47 PPMM 20 METAPHYSICS: THE BIG QUESTIONS attributed to many individuals (whiteness, triangularity, courage, etc.). Quine, on the other hand, is a “nominalist,” admitting that there are words that can be used to describe many things but denying that there is any single thing present in all the objects truly described by one such word. For example, on Quine’s view, many things can truly be described as red, but there need be no extra thing – “redness” – that somehow unites them or is part of them all. In van Inwagen’s “Introduction: What is metaphysics?,” Quine’s “On What There Is,” and the charming dialogue about “Holes” by David and Stephanie Lewis, we fi nd contemporary philosophers wrestling with the ancient questions of ontology, but using some more recent tools – such as the notions of “exis- tential quantifi cation,” and the technique for eliminating “singular terms” known as “Russell’s Theory of Defi nite Descriptions”. Phrases of “existential quantifi ca- tion” are simply expressions like “There is a . ,” “There are some . ,” “There exists a . ,” “There exist some . .” – phrases that can be completed in ever so many ways to affi rm the being or existence of different kinds of thing. State- ments express “existential commitment” to so-and-sos if they begin with these sorts of phrases and then go on to describe a thing or things that are so-and- so. Van Inwagen, Quine, and the Lewises all share the view that the way to do ontology is to consider all the things one believes to be true, and then to see what statements of existential commitment seem to follow, as a matter of logic, from these beliefs. They all also agree that appearances can be deceiving; that a statement apparently committing someone to the existence of so-and-sos can be regarded as innocent, a mere manner of speaking, if one can readily provide a “paraphrase” of the statement that does not even appear to imply that there are so-and-sos. Van Inwagen, the Lewises, and Quine do not see an important difference between saying that there is a certain kind of thing, and saying that there exists a certain kind of thing; both signal existential commitment to things of that kind. But some philosophers – like Quine’s fi ctitious “Wyman,” and the Austrian phi- losopher Alexius Meinong (described by Chisholm in Ch. 3) – think that the difference between “there is . .” and “there exists . .” is an important one; that what there is includes more than what exists, and “existence” and “being” come apart. Wyman (and Meinong) say that the things that have being but not existence are ones that merely “subsist” (Meinong using the German word “bestehen”). Quine’s Wyman takes an extreme view about singular terms – that is, names (“Bill Clinton,” “Pegasus”) and descriptive phrases that can serve as the subject in a sentence with a singular verb (“Zimmerman’s favorite book,” “the present king of France”): If a singular term can be meaningfully used in a sentence, then there must be something answering to the term; it must at least subsist. So, Wyman claims not only that there are “ideal entities” such as universals and numbers, but also that there are mythical beasts, such as Pegasus. Meinong’s position (as described by Chisholm) is a little more complicated. Like Wyman, he says that there are “ideal entities” like universals and numbers – they subsist, although they do not exist – and he reserves existence for concrete D2 entities in space and time (in Ch. 4, Russell uses “exist” and “subsist” in the ccmp01.inddmp01.indd 2200 77/6/2007/6/2007 33:40:47:40:47 PPMM A WHAT IS EXISTENCE? 21 same way). Unlike Wyman, however, Meinong denies that Pegasus, golden mountains, and other merely possible objects either exist or subsist. In other words, there are no such things; they have no “Sein,” no being, whatsoever. So far, then, Meinong agrees with Quine. We can, however, talk meaningfully about these merely possible “objects,” ascribing this or that feature. For instance, we can truly say, of Pegasus, that he has wings; and, of the present king of France, that he is French. Meinong used the word “Sosein” (“so-being” or “being thus- and-so”) to describe the characteristics truly ascribable to an object, whether or not there is such a thing. This led to the principle (fi rst formulated in these terms by his student, Ernst Mally, but propounded by Meinong) of the “independence of the Sosein of an object from its Sein”: an object can be thus-and-so despite the fact that there is no such object. Pegasus can be winged, though there is no Pegasus. (It should be pointed out that Chisholm does not explicitly endorse Meinong’s theory; he merely defends it from the charge of absurdity, and makes what he takes to be a strong case for it. Chisholm’s own views about the nature of exis- tence, and the way to pursue ontology, were more like those represented here by van Inwagen, the Lewises, and Quine.) Suggestions for further reading Alston, William P., “Ontological Commitments,” in Laurence and Macdonald (eds.), Contemporary Readings in the Foundations of Metaphysics (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1998) pp. 46–54. Aune, Bruce, Metaphysics: The Elements (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota, 1985) chs. 1 and 2. Dorr, Cian, “There are No Abstract Objects,” in Hawthorne, Sider, and Zimmerman (eds.), Contemporary Debates in Metaphysics (Malden, Mass.: Blackwell, 2007). Eklund, Matti “The Picture of Reality as an Amorphous Lump,” in Hawthorne, Sider, and Zimmerman (eds.), Contemporary Debates in Metaphysics (Malden, Mass.: Blackwell, 2007). Haack, Susan, “Quantifi ers,” in Laurence and Macdonald (eds.), Contemporary Readings in the Foundations of Metaphysics (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1998) pp. 55–68. Hirsch, Eli, “Ontological Arguments: Interpretive Charity and Quantifi er Variance,” in Hawthorne, Sider, and Zimmerman (eds.), Contemporary Debates in Metaphysics (Malden, Mass.: Blackwell, 2007). Lambert, Karel, Meinong and the Principle of Independence: Its Place in Meinong’s Theory of Objects, Its Signifi cance in Contemporary Philosophical Logic (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1983). Parsons, Terence, Nonexistent Objects (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1980), Intro- duction, and chs. 1 and 2. Russell, Bertrand, Introduction to Mathematical Philosophy (London: George Allen and Unwin, 1919), chs. 15 and 16. van Inwagen, Peter, “Meta-ontology,” Erkenntnis 48 (1998), pp. 233–50; reprinted in van Inwagen, Ontology, Identity, and Modality (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001), pp. 13–31. D2 ccmp01.inddmp01.indd 2211 77/6/2007/6/2007 33:40:47:40:47 PPMM 22 DAVID LEWIS AND STEPHANIE LEWIS 1 Holes David Lewis and Stephanie Lewis Argle: I believe in nothing but concrete material objects. Bargle: There are many of your opinions I applaud; but one of your less pleasing characteristics is your fondness for the doctrines of nominalism and mate- rialism. Every time you get started on any such topic, I know we are in for a long argument. Where shall we start this time: numbers, colors, lengths, sets, force-fi elds, sensations, or what? Argle: Fictions all! I’ve thought hard about every one of them. Bargle: A long evening’s work. Before we start, let me fi nd you a snack. Will you have some crackers and cheese? Argle: Thank you. What splendid Gruyère! Bargle: You know, there are remarkably many holes in this piece. Argle: There are. Bargle: Got you! Bargle: You admit there are many holes in that piece of cheese. Therefore, there are some holes in it. Therefore, there are some holes. In other words, holes exist. But holes are not made of matter; to the contrary, they result from the absence of matter. Argle: I did say that there are holes in the cheese; but that is not to imply that there are holes.
Recommended publications
  • Steps Toward a Computational Metaphysics∗ Ideal for the Exposition of Philosophical Theories
    Branden Fitelson & Edward N. Zalta 2 one. Since ancient times the axiomatic method has been important to philosophers both as an example of successful systematization in specific sciences (e.g., optics, acoustics and mathematics) as well as a possible Steps Toward a Computational Metaphysics∗ ideal for the exposition of philosophical theories. While the history of the application of the axiomatic method in philosophy is complex (Man- Branden Fitelson cosu 1996, 232, note 39), there is no doubt that Spinoza 1677 is the best known example of this tendency. Leibniz went a step further by including University of California–Berkeley a computational component, as can be seen from the following:1 and characteristica universalis Edward N. Zalta If we had it [a ], we should be able to reason in metaphysics and morals in much the same way as in Stanford University geometry and analysis. (Russell 1900, 169) If controversies were to arise, there would be no more need of dis- putation between two philosophers than between two accountants. Abstract For it would suffice to take their pencils in their hands, to sit down In this paper, the authors describe their initial investigations to their slates, and to say to each other . : Let us calculate. in computational metaphysics. Our method is to implement ax- (Russell 1900, 170) iomatic metaphysics in an automated reasoning system. In this paper, we describe what we have discovered when the theory of ab- Notice that the Latin word Russell translates as ‘accountants’ is ‘Com- prover9 stract objects is implemented in (a first-order automated putistas’, and the Latin word translated as ‘slates’ is ‘abacos’.
    [Show full text]
  • Existence As a Real Property
    Francesco Berto Existence as a Real Property The Ontology of Meinongianism For Graham Priest, Long-distance teacher Prologue: Much Ado About Nothing Some philosophers think that something’s having intuitive content is very inconclusive evidence in favor of it. I think it is very heavy evidence in favor of anything, myself. I really don’t know, in a way, what more conclusive evidence one can have about anything, ultimately speaking. –Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity 1 In an episode of The Today Show of some years ago, Gene Shalit – NBC’s film and book critic, famous for his wits – reviews several books sharing the feature of bearing entertaining titles. The highpoint of the monologue comes with Nonexistent Objects, by the UCLA philosopher Terence Parsons. Shalit wonders how one could write a whole book on things that do not exist!1 This whole book, too, is about things that do not exist. But if one stops to think, one may find that, in a sense, there is nothing special about this. There are, in fact, thousands of books speaking about unreal things. You have probably read quite a few of them: Sir Arthur Conan Doyle’s stories portrait the adventures of the detective Sherlock Holmes; The Lord of the Rings speaks at length of Gandalf the wizard. Doyle represents Sherlock Holmes as a detective living in London, Baker Street (precisely, at number 221b), describes his remarkable observational and deductive abilities, makes of him the arch-enemy of the criminal mastermind Moriarty. J.R.R. Tolkien characterizes Gandalf as a wizard with a pointy hat and a grey robe (a white one, from a certain point of the story onwards), a heavy pipe-herb 1 The anecdote is reported by Roy Sorensen [2003], p.
    [Show full text]
  • Ernst Mally's Theory of Properties!
    ERNST MALLY'S THEORY OF PROPERTIES! Roberto POLl University of Trento 1. Of Meinong's pupils, Ernst Mally is the one who probably made the most significant contribution to furthering the ideas of his teacher.2 It is sufficient, in this regard, to cite Meinong's explicit acknowledgement of Mally's work in his "The Theory ofObjects".3 Of greatest importance in this respect are Mally's unravelling of the distinction between Sein and Sosein4 and between nuclear and extra-nuclear properties,S and his introduction of important termi­ nological refinements which for the most part Meinong accepted.6 Nevertheless, the recent revival of interest in Meinong's theories has not been matched by equal consideration of Mally's work and insights. If we inspect the literature of the last fifteen years, it is immediately apparent that the overwhelming majority of references to Mally concern just two passages in his works, the two that Findlay quotes and comments on in his classic book on Meinong.7 One 1. I thank Liliana A1bertazzi, Johannes Brandl, Rudolf Haller, Dale Jacquette, Karl Schuhmann, Barry Smith and Jan Wo1enski for their comments on a previous version of this paper. 2. Ernst Mally was born in Krainburg (now Kranj, Yugoslavia) in 1879 and died in Graz in 1944. He studied philosophy, mathematics and physics at the University of Graz and in 1913 wrote his dissertation in philosophy under Meinong's supervision. On Meinong's death he was appointed director of the psychology laboratory that has been established by Meinong. In 1925 he became full professor and retained his chair in the university until 1942.
    [Show full text]
  • The Intentionality Thesis and Its Developments: from Brentano to Meinong, Husserl, Ehrenfels and Mally
    o THE INTENTIONALITY THESIS AND ITS DEVELOPMENTSphilosophy,... N 2(26), june - 2013 THE INTENTIONALITY THESIS AND ITS DEVELOPMENTS: FROM BRENTANO TO MEINONG, HUSSERL, EHRENFELS AND MALLY Winfried Löffler (*) ccording to Otto Neurath and via his prominent pupils – was one of Rudolf Haller, philosophy in the most influential philosophers in Austria in the 19th and early European philosophy of all times. It is 20th had a very special character, and true that one important root of it is one of the main roots of modern analytic philosophy is the Austro - analytic philosophy: It was open to Polish one which essentially goes the sciences, it was anti-idealistic and back to Brentano, his pupils (like realistic in its ontological tendencies, Meinong and Twardowski) and it had an empiricist tendency and it second-generation-pupils (like Mally, went back to the longer influence of Łukasiewicz, and Tarski).(*)Furthermore, Catholic scholastic philosophy and the Brentano’s influence contributed to Leibniz - Wolff rationalism. This in the appointment of Ernst Mach as turn has to do with the Catholicism of professor in Vienna, and this endorsed the Habsburg emperors, and it a science-friendly climate among prevented a stronger reception of the philosophers and a broader audience. philosophies of Kant and the German Interestingly, also the phenomenological Idealists. Barry Smith proposed an movement – today often seen in harsh addition to this thesis: The central opposition to analytic philosophy – figure for this so - called “Austrian originates in Brentano and his school. philosophy” was Franz Brentano Edmund Husserl writes that without (1838 - 1917); he served as a professor his teacher Brentano, he would not in Vienna from 1874 to 1880 and then have turned into a philosopher, and as a private docent till 1895.
    [Show full text]
  • A Chapter Three
    SSStttooonnnyyy BBBrrrooooookkk UUUnnniiivvveeerrrsssiiitttyyy The official electronic file of this thesis or dissertation is maintained by the University Libraries on behalf of The Graduate School at Stony Brook University. ©©© AAAllllll RRRiiiggghhhtttsss RRReeessseeerrrvvveeeddd bbbyyy AAAuuuttthhhooorrr... The Science of Right in Leibniz’s Practical Philosophy A Dissertation Presented by Christopher Lowell Johns to The Graduate School in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy Stony Brook University August 2007 Copyright by Christopher Lowell Johns August 2007 Stony Brook University The Graduate School Christopher Lowell Johns We, the dissertation committee for the above candidate for the Doctor of Philosophy degree, hereby recommend acceptance of this dissertation. Jeffrey B. Edwards (Dissertation Advisor) Associate Professor Department of Philosophy Allegra de Laurentiis (Chairperson of the Defense) Associate Professor Department of Philosophy Clyde Lee Miller (Department Reader) Professor Department of Philosophy Manfred Baum (Outside Reader) Professor of Philosophy Bergische Universität Wuppertal This dissertation is accepted by the Graduate School Lawrence Martin Dean of the Graduate School ii Abstract of the Dissertation The Science of Right in Leibniz’s Practical Philosophy by Christopher Lowell Johns Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy Stony Brook University 2007 This dissertation examines a neglected area of Leibniz’s philosophy, namely, natural right ( jus ). Contrary to
    [Show full text]
  • On Sober Platonism
    UNIVERSITÀ DEGLI STUDI DI MILANO Dipartimento di Filosofia UNIVERSITÉ PARIS 1 PANTHEON-SORBONNE IHPST - Insistut d’Histoire et de Philosophie des Sciences et des Techniques Costanza Brevini On Sober Platonism New Perspectives in Mathematical Platonism Beyond Strong Ontological Assumptions March, 4th 2016 SUPERVISORS: Marco Panza, Miriam Franchella MEMBERS OF THE JURY: Andrea Bottani Brice Halimi Sebastien Gandon Agustìn Rayo Andrea Sereni To you, the daring venturers and adventurers, and whoever hath embarked with cunning sails upon frightful seas; To you the enigma-intoxicated, the twilight-enjoyers, whose souls are allured by flutes to every treacherous gulf. NIETZSCHE, FRIEDRICH, Thus Spoke Zarathustra !2 TABLE OF CONTENTS: SINTESI 5 RÉSUMÉ 8 ABSTRACT 11 PRELIMINARY REMARKS 15 CHAPTER 1: PLATONISM 25 1.1 FROM PLATO TO CONTEMPORARY PLATONISM 25 1.2 INDEPENDENCE 30 1.3 EXISTENCE 35 1.4 EPISTEMOLOGY 40 1.4.1 THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE 41 1.4.2 TRUTH 45 1.4.3 REFERENCE 50 1.5 SOBER PLATONISM 54 CHAPTER 2: FULL-BLOODED PLATONISM 62 2.1 INTRODUCTION 62 2.1.1 THE PROBLEM OF FORMALIZATION 64 2.2 EPISTEMOLOGY 66 2.2.1 THE EPISTEMOLOGICAL ARGUMENT 66 2.2.2 THE FULL-BLOODED SOLUTION 70 2.3 CONSISTENCY 75 2.4 MATHEMATICAL CORRECTNESS AND MATHEMATICAL TRUTH 82 2.4.1 HOW TO DEAL WITH UNDECIDABLE SENTENCES IN MATHEMATICS 83 2.5 NON-UNIQUENESS 87 2.6 A DEFENSE OF FULL-BLOODED PLATONISM 93 CHAPTER 3: STRUCTURALISM 99 3.1 STRUCTURALISM 99 3.2 EXISTENCE 105 3.4 AXIOMS 114 3.5 EPISTEMOLOGY 118 3.6 REFERENCE 126 !3 3.7 STRUCTURALISM AND CAESAR’S PROBLEM 129 3.8
    [Show full text]
  • Edward N. Zalta
    Edward N. Zalta Curriculum Vitæ Address: CSLI/Cordura Hall, Stanford University, Stanford, CA 94305 Phone: 650-723-0488 (work) Marital Status: married, no children E-Mail: [email protected] Home Page: http://mally.stanford.edu/zalta.html Education Ph.D., Philosophy, University of Massachusetts/Amherst, February 1981 (Thesis Director: Terence Parsons) B.A., Cum Laude, Ideas and Methods, Rice University, May 1975 (approved by the departments of Philosophy, Biology, Behavioral Science, and Music) Areas of Specialization Metaphysics (Ontology) and Epistemology Philosophy of Mathematics Philosophical Logic/Philosophy of Logic Computational Metaphysics Areas of Competence Philosophy of Language/Intensional Logic Philosophy of Mind/Intentionality Contemporary Analytic Philosophy Contemporary History of Philosophy: Bolzano, Brentano, Husserl, Meinong, Frege, Russell, early Wittgenstein, Carnap, Quine Modern Philosophy: Rationalists, Empiricists, Kant Professional Experience Senior Research Scholar Center for the Study of Language and Information, Stanford University September 1997 { present Senior Researcher Center for the Study of Language and Information, Stanford University September 1989 { August 1997 1 Acting Assistant Professor Department of Philosophy, Stanford University September 1988 { August 1989 September 1987 { August 1988 September 1986 { August 1987 Postdoctoral Fellow Center for the Study of Language and Information, Stanford University September 1984 { August 1986 Assistant Professor Department of Philosophy, Rice University
    [Show full text]
  • Downloadable
    2016, 2 (1) ARGUMENTA The Journal of the Italian Society for Analytic Philosophy First published 2016 by University of Sassari © 2016 University of Sassari Produced and designed for digital publication by the Argumenta Staff All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored or transmitted in any form or by any means without the prior permission in writing from Argumenta. Editor Masssimo Dell'Utri (University of Sassari) Editorial Board Carla Bagnoli (University of Modena and Reggio Emilia), Francesca Boccuni (University San Raffaele, Milano), Clotilde Calabi (University of Milano), Stefano Caputo (University of Sassari), Massimiliano Carrara (University of Padova), Richard Davies (University of Bergamo), Ciro De Florio (Università Cattolica, Milano), Elisabetta Galeotti (University of Piemonte Orientale), Pier Luigi Lecis (University of Cagliari), Olimpia Giuliana Loddo (University of Cagliari), Giuseppe Lorini (University of Cagliari), Marcello Montibeller (University of Sassari), Giulia Piredda (IUSS-Pavia), Pietro Salis (University of Cagliari) Argumenta is the official journal of the Italian Society for Analytic Philosophy (SIFA). It was founded in 2014 in response to a common demand for the creation of an Italian journal explicitly devoted to the publication of high quality research in analytic philosophy. From the beginning Argumenta was conceived as an international journal, and has benefitted from the cooperation of some of the most distinguished Italian and non-Italian scholars in all areas of analytic
    [Show full text]
  • Mechanizing Principia Logico-Metaphysica in Functional Type Theory
    D. Kirchner, C. Benzmüller, and E. Zalta 2 system Isabelle/HOL. Initial experiments within this framework reveal a crucial but overlooked fact: a deeply-rooted and known paradox is reintroduced in AOT when the logic of complex terms is simply adjoined to AOT’s specially formulated comprehension Mechanizing Principia Logico-Metaphysica principle for relations. This result constitutes a new and impor- ∗ tant paradox, given how much expressive and analytic power is in Functional Type Theory contributed by having the two kinds of complex terms in the sys- tem. Its discovery is the highlight of our joint project and provides Daniel Kirchner strong evidence for a new kind of scientific practice in philosophy, Fachbereich Mathematik und Informatik namely, computational metaphysics. Our results were made technically possible by a suitable adap- Freie Universität Berlin tation of Benzmüller’s metalogical approach to universal reason- [email protected] ing by semantically embedding theories in classical higher-order logic. This approach enables one to reuse state-of-the-art higher- Christoph Benzmüller order proof assistants, such as Isabelle/HOL, for mechanizing and Fachbereich Mathematik und Informatik experimentally exploring challenging logics and theories such as Freie Universität Berlin AOT. Our results also provide a fresh perspective on the question [email protected] of whether relational type theory or functional type theory better serves as a foundation for logic and metaphysics. & Computer Science and Communications University of Luxembourg [email protected] 1 Abstract Summary Edward N. Zalta Principia Logico-Metaphysica (PLM) [16] is an online research monograph Center for the Study of Language and Information that contains a canonical presentation of Abstract Object Theory (AOT) arXiv:1711.06542v4 [cs.LO] 24 Jul 2019 Stanford University [17], [18], along with motivation for, and commentary on, the theory.
    [Show full text]
  • Download Download
    c:\users\kenneth\documents\type3401\rj 3401 196 red.docx 2014-05-17 9:24 AM NOTES AND CORRESPONDENCE FOR RUSSELL’S 1905 REVIEW OF MEINONG Bernard Linsky Philosophy / U. of Alberta Edmonton, ab, Canada t6g 2e5 [email protected] Bertrand Russell took fourteen pages of notes on Meinong’s Unter- suchungen zur Gegenstandstheorie und Psychologie [Studies in object theory and psychology] in preparation for his review of the book in Mind. Translations of Russell’s letters from Alexius Meinong, Rudolf Ameseder and Ernst Mally discuss their contributions to the volume (with transcriptions of the German originals appended in this journal’s online edition). Together the notes and correspondence record the or- igin of Russell’s famous criticisms of Meinong’s theory of non-existent objects, which appeared in both “On Denoting” and the review in Mind in October 1905. ertrand Russell published a review in Mind 1905 of a collection of papers by Alexius Meinong and his students, Untersuchun- =gen zur Gegenstandstheorie und Psychologie (1904).1 The review _appeared later in the same issue of Mind as Russell’s most famous paper from 1905, “On Denoting”, in which Meinong’s views are dis- cussed in passing. To prepare for writing the review Russell read through the book’s contents, making several comments in the mar- gins, and then wrote fourteen leaves of notes on the articles that figure in the review. Russell also corresponded with Meinong and two of his authors, Ernst Mally and Rudolf Ameseder, in early 1905.2 The read- ing notes are described in the prefatory notes to the edition of the 1 “Review of Meinong and Others, Untersuchungen zur Gegenstandstheorie und Psychol- ogie”, Mind 14 (Oct.
    [Show full text]
  • Content and Competence
    Rechtstheorie · Legal Theory herausgegeben von Thomas Gutmann, Tatjana Hörnle und Matthias Jestaedt 1 Jakob Weissinger Content and Competence A Descriptive Approach to the Concept of Rights Mohr Siebeck Jakob Weissinger, born 1986; study of law at the University of Münster; 2013 first legal state examination; academic assistant at the Institute for Criminal Law and Criminal Procedural Law at the University of Münster; 2018 dissertation; legal clerkship in Cologne and academic assistant at the Institute for Foreign and International Criminal Law at the University of Cologne. ISBN 978-3-16-157030-8 / eISBN 978-3-16-157031-5 DOI 10.1628/978-3-16-157031-5 ISSN 2629-723X / eISSN 2629-7248 (Rechtstheorie · Legal Theory) The Deutsche Nationalbibliothek lists this publication in the Deutsche Nationalbibliographie; detailed bibliographic data are available at http://dnb.dnb.de. © 2019 Mohr Siebeck Tübingen, Germany. www.mohrsiebeck.com This work is licensed under the license “Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 Inter-national” (CC BY-NC-ND 4.0). A complete Version of the license text can be found at: https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0/. An electronic version of this book is freely available, thanks to the support of libraries working with Knowledge Unlatched. KU is a collaborative initiative designed to make high quality books Open Access for the public good. More information about the initiative can be found at www.knowledgeunlatched.org. Any use not covered by the above license is prohibited and illegal without the permission of the publisher. The book was typeset by epline in Böblingen using Times typeface, printed on non-aging paper and bound by Gulde Druck in Tübingen.
    [Show full text]
  • Ii Studies and Articles Studije I Članci
    II STUDIES AND ARTICLES STUDIJE I ČLANCI UDK: 165.62 Meinong A. https://doi.org/10.2298/FID2001073C Original Scientific Article PHILOSOPHY AND SOCIETY Received: 03.05.2019. Accepted: 11.08.2019. VOL. 31, NO. 1, 001–138 Ekaterina Cherepanova JUSTIFICATION OF ATEMPORAL VALUES IN ALEXIUS MEINONG’S THEORY OF OBJECTS ABSTRACT KEYWORDS In the history of philosophy, Alexius Meinong’s interest in axiology has Meinong’s value traditionally been seen as confined to his earlier works. However, if we theory, subject of analyze his writing after 1917, in which Meinong discusses timeless desire, subject of values, it becomes clear that he became increasingly disinterested in axiological feelings, existence of absolute psychology. Moreover, since the theory of the object, in Meinong’s view, values, psychologism could not be a part of metaphysics, he had to deal with the additional methodological difficulty of proving that the good exists independently of human subjectivity. The article discusses A. Meinong’s understanding of the object of desire, the object of a value-feeling and the connection between ethical values as objects of consciousness and time. It is shown that, according to Meinong, language is where values actually reside and only through language can their reality be explained. Alexius Meinong’s theory of objects was brought to the forefront of public discussion owing to a debate initiated by Bertrand Russell and, to a certain extent, owing to the logical interpretation proposed by the former’s disciple and successor Ernst Mally (Mally 1912). Though Russell thought highly of Mei- nong’s works, his theory of objects came under criticism for being inconsistent and unpromising on the grounds that analytical philosophy cannot deal with non-existent objects (Russell 1923, Russell 1973).
    [Show full text]