Race As a Scientific Hot Potato

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Race As a Scientific Hot Potato 101 Race as a Scientific Hot Potato: a Review of The Retreat of Scientific Racism Randoif Arguelles Elazar Barkan. The Retreat ofScientific Racism: Changing Concepts ofRace in Britain and the United States between the World Wars. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1992. Pp. xiv, 381. professor of rhetoric once told me jokingly that the easiest way to win an argument is to compare your opponent to Hitler. Ironically, some historians of Ascience have contended that this is precisely the reason for the decline of once- prevalent theories of racial hierarchies in the biological and social sciences. According to this argument, the atrocities committed by the Nazi party during and immediately preceding the Second World War—atrocities motivated by the belief in the inherent superiority of the Aryan race—so repulsed the rest of the world that biological and social scientists in the United States and Great Britain abandoned their own theories of innate racial traits and hierarchies. Under this explanation, argued by such scholars as Leon Poliakov, Thomas F. Gossett, Nancy Stepan, Michael Banton, and Hamilton Cravens (1, note 1), controversial scientific arguments for the superiority of certain races and the corresponding inferiority of others finally lost their currency as the result of political pressures and shifting public sentiment against Nazism. Such views credit the fortuitous rise of right-minded political influences—namely, opposition to Nazism—with disabusing scientists of wrong-headed scientific theories—namely, scientific racism. Elazar Barkan finds this view too simplistic. Global politics, he claims, did have an influence on the judgments of the scientific community, but previous historians have overplayed its significance. More accurately, says Barkan, changes in the nature of the scientific disciplines, changes in the composition of the scientific community, and the personal histories of the scientists active during the interwar years were in fact responsible for scientific racism’s fall from grace (2). Thus, unlike previous historians, in addition to politics, Barkan brings sociological and psychological factors to bear in his analysis. More importantly, Barkan notes, this convergence of sociological, political, and psychological causal dynamics on the scientific thought of the interwar years preceded the rise of Nazism. Barkan’s fuller account is cogent, insightful, and thought-provoking. Barkan argues that a general pattern can be discerned in the American and British scientific communities’ shift away from scientific racism. First, discord occurred among the scientists themselves with respect to the interwar era’s commonly accepted racial typologies and race-based theories of human behavior. According to Barkan, the reification of race had been in vogue since the nineteenth century, and was first articulated in the writings of Count Arthur de Gobineau (15-16). Barkan contends that by the 1920s and 1930s, the lack of solid empirical evidence and the absence of epistemological foundations for scientific racism led inevitably to competing theories of race, which in turn led to scientists questioning the ontological status of race itself. Second, in the midst of this disagreement over the nature and function of racial hierarchies, a new breed of scientists joined the professional ranks. These scientists 102 enjoyed a peculiar dual status: that of simultaneous insider and outsider in the scientific community (9). They were insiders in terms of their professional expertise and position, but outsiders with respect to some characteristic that placed them in an ethnic, gender, geographical, or political minority within their professional peer group. Thus, Jews, women, immigrants, and leftists figure largely in Barkan’s account. As insiders, they had sufficient professional credibility to challenge the scientific status quo. As outsiders, they had a vested interest in promoting egalitarianism within the scientific community and society in general—or at least tended towards egalitarianism more readily than their old- stock, “mainline” colleagues (177). Barkan does not go so far as to say that these insider- outsider scientists were the only ones in their profession arguing against racial hierarchies. He does claim, however, that they were the first to offer a unified public front for anti-racist views (280). This touches upon the third component of Barkan’s thesis: that from 1933 to 193$ the retreat of scientific racism moved from an intra-disciplinary discussion to a full-fledged public discourse when these insider-outsider scientists took it upon themselves to disseminate their anti-racist analyses in a public forum (10-11, 279). Borrowing a term from Michel Foucauk, Barkan marks this transformation of the scientist into a politically active “universal intellectual” as the beginning of the end of scientific racism. The book is organized into three parts, each corresponding to the various stages by which the reification of racial hierarchies in science became undone. Within each section, Barkan covers the material in a similar fashion, examining relevant secondary sources and surveying in detail the published works and private correspondence of the American and British scientists who involved themselves in the ongoing discussions surrounding race. Part One examines the various conceptions of race entertained by British and American anthropologists. Barkan’s discussion of racial theories in British anthropology traces the professionalization of the discipline—from annchair ethnologists to physical and cultural anthropologists working in the field—as much as it discusses concepts of race. According to Barkan, the field of British anthropology was too diffuse for practitioners within the discipline to arrive at a consensus on the function or importance of race. By contrast, the American anthropological community was more clearly defined into two camps: the racists, best exemplified by the theories of Charles Benedict Davenport and his eugenicist Galton Society; and the egalitarians, led most prominently by the German-born Franz Boas and his students, including Alfred Kroeber and Margaret Mead. Barkan notes, however, that even an egalitarian such as Boas did not think to question the reality of racial categories. Boas argued for a basic equality among various racial types, not against racial types as valid scientific categories. Nevertheless, Barkan contends that even in this climate of institutionalized scientific racism, the discrediting of race as a valid causal dynamic in human behavior and differentiation had begun. He argues that the “theoretical chaos” of British anthropology “left the door open to the explicit rejection of racism” (65). Meanwhile, across the Atlantic, Boas and his followers’ managed to distinguish physical anthropology from cultural anthropology, initiating the novel view that race might be a function of society, not heredity (78). Part Two of The Retreat of $cientfic Racism discusses the debates and controversies surrounding race in the biological sciences. Since anthropologists failed to arrive at a consensus on how to define race, let alone how to utilize racial categories in 103 their work, Barkan contends that the task then fell to biologists to expound the nature and meaning of racial categories and hierarchies (137). In this chapter, he focuses on geneticists such as the liberal egalitarian Herbert Spencer Jennings and the conservative egalitarian Raymond Pearl, biometricians such as Karl Pearson (the inventor of the correlation coefficient R in quantitative analysis), the racist Charles Davenport, and Julian Huxley, a convert to the egalitarian camp. Barkan’s main point in this section is that both racist and egalitarian biologists in Britain and America “presented hypotheses divorced from scientific data” (142). for instance, in a re-evaluation of data collected on immigrants by racist biologist Harry H. Laughlin, Herbert Spencer Jennings criticized Laughlin’s statistical interpretations, offering his own politically motivated egalitarian take on the evidence (199-201).’ The hope that biology could settle the disputes over the function and relevance of race was dashed, for, as Barkan notes, “Science could lend itself as easily to either a racist or an anti-racist interpretation, whether by biologists or social scientists. ... [TJhe evolution of anti-racism in science was not inevitable” (228). Part Three of this monograph deals with the repercussions that resulted from a lack of a unified scientific front: from the ashes of this scientific agnosticism arose the phenomenon in the late 1930s of scientists as political activists. The insider-outsider scientists (discussed above) took it upon themselves to oppose racism in a public forum as well as within their respective academic disciplines, even though this practice was generally discouraged by the British and American scientific communities (11). Here, Barkan treads on more familiar ground, since the political activities of scientists in the late 1930s—most notably, Franz Boas in the United States—are well documented. Barkan does not dispute that politics played a large role in the discrediting of scientific racism. In fact, he maintains that “political beliefs had a greater impact in attitudes toward race than did scientific commitments” (343). But he also maintains that the political activities of scientists, even the opposition to Nazi racism, would not have been possible if the social and biological scientific disciplines had not
Recommended publications
  • Using Facial Angle to Prove Evolution and the Human Race Hierarchy Jerry Bergman
    Papers Using facial angle to prove evolution and the human race hierarchy Jerry Bergman A measurement technique called facial angle has a history of being used to rank the position of animals and humans on the evolutionary hierarchy. The technique was exploited for several decades in order to prove evolution and justify racism. Extensive research on the correlation of brain shapes with mental traits and also the falsification of the whole field of phrenology, an area to which the facial angle theory was strongly linked, caused the theory’s demise. he use of the facial angle, a method of measuring but also the difference between the human “races”.8 Science Tthe forehead-to-jaw relationship, has a long history historian John Haller concluded that the “facial angle was and was often used to make judgments of inferiority and the most extensively elaborated and artlessly abused criteria superiority of certain human races. University of Chicago for racial somatology.”2 zoology professor Ransom Dexter wrote that the “subject of Supporters of this theory cited as proof convincing, the facial angle has occupied the attention of philosophers but very distorted, drawings of an obvious black African or from earliest antiquity.”1 Aristotle used it to help determine Australian Aborigine as being the lowest type of human and a person’s intelligence and to rank humans from inferior a Caucasian as the highest racial type. The slanting African to superior.2 It was first used in modern times to compare forehead shown in the pictures indicates a smaller frontal human races by Petrus Camper (1722–1789), and it became cortex, such as is typical of an ape, demonstrating to naïve widely popular until disproved in the early 20th century.2 observers their inferiority.
    [Show full text]
  • Anthropology, History Of
    Encyclopedia of Race and Racism, Vol1 – finals/ 10/4/2007 11:59 Page 93 Anthropology, History of Jefferson, Thomas. 1944. ‘‘Notes on the State of Virginia.’’ In defend that institution from religious abolitionists, who The Life and Selected Writings of Thomas Jefferson, edited by called for the unity of God’s children, and from Enlight- Adrienne Koch and William Peden. New York: Modern enment critics, who called for liberty, fraternity, and American Library. equality of man. During the early colonial experience in Lewis, R. B. 1844. Light and Truth: Collected from the Bible and Ancient and Modern History Containing the Universal History North America, ‘‘race’’ was not a term that was widely of the Colored and Indian Race; from the Creation of the World employed. Notions of difference were often couched in to the Present Time. Boston: Committee of Colored religious terms, and comparisons between ‘‘heathen’’ and Gentlemen. ‘‘Christian,’’ ‘‘saved’’ and ‘‘unsaved,’’ and ‘‘savage’’ and Morton, Samuel. 1844. Crania Aegyptiaca: Or, Observations on ‘‘civilized’’ were used to distinguish African and indige- Egyptian Ethnography Derived from Anatomy, History, and the nous peoples from Europeans. Beginning in 1661 and Monuments. Philadelphia: J. Penington. continuing through the early eighteenth century, ideas Nash, Gary. 1990. Race and Revolution. Madison, WI: Madison about race began to circulate after Virginia and other House. colonies started passing legislation that made it legal to Pennington, James, W. C. 1969 (1841). A Text Book of the enslave African servants and their children. Origins and History of the Colored People. Detroit, MI: Negro History Press. In 1735 the Swedish naturalist Carl Linnaeus com- pleted his first edition of Systema Naturae, in which he attempted to differentiate various types of people scientifi- Mia Bay cally.
    [Show full text]
  • Race As a Legal Concept
    University of Colorado Law School Colorado Law Scholarly Commons Articles Colorado Law Faculty Scholarship 2012 Race as a Legal Concept Justin Desautels-Stein University of Colorado Law School Follow this and additional works at: https://scholar.law.colorado.edu/articles Part of the Conflict of Laws Commons, Jurisprudence Commons, Law and Race Commons, and the Legal History Commons Citation Information Justin Desautels-Stein, Race as a Legal Concept, 2 COLUM. J. RACE & L. 1 (2012), available at https://scholar.law.colorado.edu/articles/137. Copyright Statement Copyright protected. Use of materials from this collection beyond the exceptions provided for in the Fair Use and Educational Use clauses of the U.S. Copyright Law may violate federal law. Permission to publish or reproduce is required. This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Colorado Law Faculty Scholarship at Colorado Law Scholarly Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Articles by an authorized administrator of Colorado Law Scholarly Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. +(,121/,1( Citation: 2 Colum. J. Race & L. 1 2012 Provided by: William A. Wise Law Library Content downloaded/printed from HeinOnline Tue Feb 28 10:02:56 2017 -- Your use of this HeinOnline PDF indicates your acceptance of HeinOnline's Terms and Conditions of the license agreement available at http://heinonline.org/HOL/License -- The search text of this PDF is generated from uncorrected OCR text. -- To obtain permission to use this article beyond the scope of your HeinOnline license, please use: Copyright Information 2012 COLUMBIA JOURNAL OF RACE AND LAW RACE AS A LEGAL CONCEPT JUSTIN DESAUTELS-STEIN* Race is a /el cocpangie a/Il corncepts, it is a matrix of rules.
    [Show full text]
  • Foreign Bodies
    Chapter One Climate to Crania: science and the racialization of human difference Bronwen Douglas In letters written to a friend in 1790 and 1791, the young, German-trained French comparative anatomist Georges Cuvier (1769-1832) took vigorous humanist exception to recent ©stupid© German claims about the supposedly innate deficiencies of ©the negro©.1 It was ©ridiculous©, he expostulated, to explain the ©intellectual faculties© in terms of differences in the anatomy of the brain and the nerves; and it was immoral to justify slavery on the grounds that Negroes were ©less intelligent© when their ©imbecility© was likely to be due to ©lack of civilization and we have given them our vices©. Cuvier©s judgment drew heavily on personal experience: his own African servant was ©intelligent©, freedom-loving, disciplined, literate, ©never drunk©, and always good-humoured. Skin colour, he argued, was a product of relative exposure to sunlight.2 A decade later, however, Cuvier (1978:173-4) was ©no longer in doubt© that the ©races of the human species© were characterized by systematic anatomical differences which probably determined their ©moral and intellectual faculties©; moreover, ©experience© seemed to confirm the racial nexus between mental ©perfection© and physical ©beauty©. The intellectual somersault of this renowned savant epitomizes the theme of this chapter which sets a broad scene for the volume as a whole. From a brief semantic history of ©race© in several western European languages, I trace the genesis of the modernist biological conception of the term and its normalization by comparative anatomists, geographers, naturalists, and anthropologists between 1750 and 1880. The chapter title Ð ©climate to crania© Ð and the introductory anecdote condense a major discursive shift associated with the altered meaning of race: the metamorphosis of prevailing Enlightenment ideas about externally induced variation within an essentially similar humanity into a science of race that reified human difference as permanent, hereditary, and innately somatic.
    [Show full text]
  • Contesting Inequality. Joseph Anténor Firmin's De L'égalité Des Races Humaines, 133 Years On
    FORUM FOR INTER-AMERICAN RESEARCH (FIAR) VOL. 12.1 (JUN. 2019) 21-28 ISSN: 1867-1519 © forum for inter-american research Contesting Inequality. Joseph Anténor Firmin’s De l’égalité des races humaines, 133 years on GUDRUN RATH (UNIVERSITY OF ART AND DESIGN, LINZ) Abstract Methods of comparison have been a central element in the construction of different races and the modeling of scientific racism, such as Arthur de Gobineau’s Essai sur l’inégalité des races humaines (1853). Nevertheless, these racist ideologies didn’t remain uncontested, and it was especially the intellectual legacy of the Haitian Revolution that played a key role in shaping what has recently been referred to as “Haitian Atlantic humanism” (M. Daut). However, 19th century Haitian diasporic intellectuals have frequently been omitted from international research tracing an intellectual history of the Atlantic sphere in the aftermath of the Haitian Revolution. Publications by intellectuals like Louis Joseph Janvier and Joseph Anténor Firmin, both Haitians residing in Paris in the second half of the 19th century, have too easily been discarded for their embracement of nationalism or their ‘imitation’ of French forms. Only recently has research highlighted their importance in thinking a “hemispheric crossculturality” (M. Dash) as well as for pan-African and pan-American thought. In publications such as De l’égalité des races humaines (1885), 19th century Haitian diasporic intellectual Joseph Anténor Firmin contested anthropological methods of comparison which provided a basis for racist ideologies. Similarly, Haitian intellectual Louis Joseph Janvier, who was trained as a medical doctor and anthropologist in France and author of Un people noir devant les blancs (1883), contributed to the modeling of an Atlantic humanism.
    [Show full text]
  • Ernest Renan and the Question of Race. Jane Victoria Dagon Louisiana State University and Agricultural & Mechanical College
    Louisiana State University LSU Digital Commons LSU Historical Dissertations and Theses Graduate School 1999 Ernest Renan and the Question of Race. Jane Victoria Dagon Louisiana State University and Agricultural & Mechanical College Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_disstheses Recommended Citation Dagon, Jane Victoria, "Ernest Renan and the Question of Race." (1999). LSU Historical Dissertations and Theses. 6937. https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_disstheses/6937 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at LSU Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in LSU Historical Dissertations and Theses by an authorized administrator of LSU Digital Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. INFORMATION TO USERS This manuscript has been reproduced from the microfilm master. UMI films the text directly from the original or copy submitted. Thus, some thesis and dissertation copies are in typewriter face, while others may be from any type of computer printer. The quality of this reproduction is dependent upon the quality of the copy submitted. Broken or indistinct print, colored or poor quality illustrations and photographs, print bleedthrough, substandard margins, and improper alignment can adversely affect reproduction. In the unlikely event that the author did not send UMI a complete manuscript and there are missing pages, these will be noted. Also, if unauthorized copyright material had to be removed, a note will indicate the deletion. Oversize materials (e.g., maps, drawings, charts) are reproduced by sectioning the original, beginning at the upper left-hand comer and continuing from left to right in equal sections with small overlaps.
    [Show full text]
  • Arthur De Gobineau, the Inequality of Human Races,[ 18S3-SS]
    44 The Classificationof Races SCIENCE AND EUGENICS Creoles who have made themselves independent of Spain; the native Indians were incapable of doing so. In Paraguay, they were just like small 7 children and were even treated as such by the Jesuits. The natives of America are, therefore, clearly not in a position to maintain themselves in face of the Europeans. The latter will begin a new culture over there on the Arthur de Gobineau, soil they have conquered from the natives. The Inequality of Human Races Arthur de Gobineau (1816-1882) is rememberedboth for his literary works f and his racistphilosophy of history. The latter is most clearly expoundedin his Essay on the Inequality of Human Races. Although Gobineauplaced race at the very center of history, he never offered a clear definition of what he meant by race. Indeed, his division of the races into White (Caucasians, i:: Semitic, or Juphetic), Black, and Yellow (Altaic, Mongol, Finnish, and Tartar) was somewhat crudefor its time. The first two books of GObineau•s Essay werepublished in 18S3. By 18S6, Josiah Nott of Mobile, Alabama, J,~; prepared an English version with the help.of Henry Hotz. The result was a seriouslydoctored text. Nott added an Appendix of his own, and Hotz sup­ 7, plied numerousnotes. From the chapterprinted here, Nott and Hotz omitted the laws of repulsionand attraction, which were at the heart ofGobineau's rJi ~,\ account of the role of race-mixing in the rise and fall of civilizations. The word degenerate,when applied to a people, means (as it ought to I~; mean) that the people has no longer the same intrinsic value as it had ~/-', before, because it has no longer the same blood in its veins, continual adulterations having gradually affected the quality of that blood.
    [Show full text]
  • Aryan Ancestors, Pariahs and the Lunatic Fringe
    Comparative Civilizations Review Volume 25 Number 25 Fall 1991 Article 2 10-1-1991 Aryan Ancestors, Pariahs and the Lunatic Fringe M. Dorothy Figueria State University of New York at Stony Brook Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarsarchive.byu.edu/ccr Recommended Citation Figueria, M. Dorothy (1991) "Aryan Ancestors, Pariahs and the Lunatic Fringe," Comparative Civilizations Review: Vol. 25 : No. 25 , Article 2. Available at: https://scholarsarchive.byu.edu/ccr/vol25/iss25/2 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at BYU ScholarsArchive. It has been accepted for inclusion in Comparative Civilizations Review by an authorized editor of BYU ScholarsArchive. For more information, please contact [email protected], [email protected]. Figueria: Aryan Ancestors, Pariahs and the Lunatic Fringe ARYAN ANCESTORS, PARIAHS AND THE LUNATIC FRINGE DOROTHY M. FIGUEIRA In going East . everyone . ought to feel that he is going to his "old home," full of memories, if only he can read them.1 If we follow them [the Indian poets] cautiously, we shall find that with some effort we are still able to walk in their footsteps.2 De l'lnde . descend un torrent de lumiere, un fleuve de Droit et de Raison.3 I Historians of the occult have made irresponsible claims to the influences of Eastern cosmic theories and practical methods for spiritual development upon National Socialism.4 Mythologizers of Nazism as well as sober scholars have drawn a causal relation- ship between early Sanskrit philology, Indian philosophy
    [Show full text]
  • Twenty-First Century Antisemitism and Its Origins
    TWENTY-FIRST CENTURY ANTISEMITISM AND ITS ORIGINS SLLL - Senior Scholars February 4 – March 3, 2019 T WENT Y -FIRST ANTISEMITISM AND ITS ORIGINS Feb 4 – Greco-Roman Roots Feb 11 – The Theological Angle Feb 18 – Folk Superstition and Economics Feb 25 – From Religion to Race Mar 3 – White Nationalism and White Supremacy Quick Review Arthur de Gobineau (1816-1882) • Arthur de Gobineau, in full Joseph-Arthur, comte de Gobineau • Published The Inequality of Human Races in 1854. • Served as secretary to the writer and statesman Alexis de Tocqueville during the latter’s brief term as foreign minister in 1849. Later he had his own diplomatic career, which took him to posts in Bern, Hanover, Frankfurt, Tehrān, Rio de Janeiro, and Stockholm. Arthur de Gobineau quotes I We come now to the white peoples. These are gifted with reflective energy, or rather with an energetic intelligence. They have a feeling for utility, but in a sense far wider and higher, more courageous and ideal, than the yellow races; a perseverance that takes account of obstacles and ultimately finds a means of overcoming them; a greater physical power, an extraordinary instinct for order, not merely as a guarantee of peace and tranquility, but as an indispensable means of self-preservation. At the same time, they have a remarkable, and even extreme, love of liberty, and are openly hostile to the formalism under which the Chinese are glad to vegetate, as well as to the strict despotism which is the only way of governing the negro. Arthur de Gobineau quotes II The white race are, further, distinguished by an extraordinary attachment to life.
    [Show full text]
  • French and Francophone Narratives of Race and Racism
    University of Pennsylvania ScholarlyCommons Publicly Accessible Penn Dissertations 2019 Writing Verdicts: French And Francophone Narratives Of Race And Racism Andrea Lloyd University of Pennsylvania, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations Recommended Citation Lloyd, Andrea, "Writing Verdicts: French And Francophone Narratives Of Race And Racism" (2019). Publicly Accessible Penn Dissertations. 3538. https://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations/3538 This paper is posted at ScholarlyCommons. https://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations/3538 For more information, please contact [email protected]. Writing Verdicts: French And Francophone Narratives Of Race And Racism Abstract Inspired by Didier Eribon's La société comme verdict, this dissertation examines how the novelistic representation of racism and racialization in French-language texts can push back against a collective social verdict in France that stigmatizes non-white peoples as lesser and as other. Though discussing the existence of race is still taboo in France, I show that this stigmatization is in fact a racial verdict, or one that operates through racialization, as opposed to a verdict predicated on sexuality, gender, or class. To do so, I analyze the representation of racial hierarchies and the experience of racism in six novels written in French: Daniel Biyaoula's L'Impasse, Gisèle Pineau's L'Exil selon Julia, Leïla Sebbar's Le Chinois vert d'Afrique, Zahia Rahmani's "Musulman" roman, Cyril Bedel's Sale nègre, and Bessora's 53 cm. As I argue, these authors resist racial verdicts by writing about and examining the place of the ethnic minority individual in French society. In so doing they also issue counter verdicts that condemn society, individuals, and the state for their complicity in maintaining an unjust status quo.
    [Show full text]
  • Cheryl Sterling, Phd Pennsylvania State University Assoc
    Sterling/1 Cheryl Sterling, PhD Pennsylvania State University Assoc. Professor of African Studies Director of the African Studies Program Email: [email protected] To be Black in Brazil When the Proud Boys descended on Washington D.C. to protest the election in the United States, on December 12, 2020, they were not constituted by people with power, who benefit from the Trump administration and his economic policies. They were members of the working class, who laud Trump and, despite everything to the contrary, believe he is their champion. They believe in a white genocide conspiracy, in that interracial mixing, nonwhite immigrants, racial integration, low fertility rates, a woman’s right to choose, and even land confiscation policies are all parts of a greater plot to overthrow white dominion. In D.C., they burnt down an African- American church, they vandalized other structures, they stabbed people on the streets, all while representing elements of white rage in the United States in the most extreme fashion. For many, they consider groups like the Proud Boys the most dangerous elements of the society and the true racists. Until we had the insurrection of January 6, 2021, in which ordinary, everyday citizens tried to overthrow the government. These citizens were also white, but members of the Republican Party, even if considered its fringe elements, who believed it was their right and duty to recreate the Republic in the way they saw fit. They were clearly racists, but it was one of their many biases on display. However, in these two outlier scenarios, these acts are exemplar of some of the worst aspects of compounded white rage and racism in the U.S.
    [Show full text]
  • The American Eugenics Movement: a Study of the Dispersal and Application of Racial Ideologies by Katherine Stolerman
    The American Eugenics Movement: A Study of the Dispersal and Application of Racial Ideologies by Katherine Stolerman I. Introduction national problems (Schoenl & Peck, 2010). Under the As unthinkable as it may seem today, people Third Reich in Germany, race was meant to supplant from all walks of life supported the eugenics class as the primary organizing principle in society. movement in the United States in the late 19th and To this end, social policies were designed to remodel 20th centuries. It represented a public policy that society in accordance with racial criteria (Burleigh & promised to address the social mores of the time, Wippermann, 1991). and as such, it was taught in schools, exhibited at I aim to demonstrate that eugenics in the United the World’s Fair, propagated by scientific journals States was more than a harmless science blown out of and conferences, and condoned by prominent social proportion. The American eugenics movement was figures, including Theodore Roosevelt, Alexander political from its inception and necessarily a product Graham Bell, and John D. Rockefeller Jr. Yet many of racialist thinking, particularly white supremacy American schoolchildren today either have not (Quigley, 1995). Both in the United States and heard the term or else grow up believing that in Germany, eugenics became an agent of social eugenics was exclusively a piece of National Socialist control. It was an instrument designed to be used by ideology in Germany in the 1930s-1940s. This paper an economic, social, and racial elite. But in Germany, seeks to examine the largely unrecognized personal the emphasis on race became a platform for extreme and ideological connections between American anti-Semitism and subsequent systematic killing—a eugenics, particularly mass sterilization movements, feature that was to some degree present in American and extremist policies such as racial and ethnic discourse, but absent from policy.
    [Show full text]